06 September 2018
Supreme Court
Download

NAVTEJ SINGH JOHAR Vs UNION OF INDIA MINISTRY OF LAW AND JUSTICE SECRETARY.

Bench: HON'BLE THE CHIEF JUSTICE, HON'BLE MR. JUSTICE ROHINTON FALI NARIMAN, HON'BLE MR. JUSTICE A.M. KHANWILKAR, HON'BLE DR. JUSTICE D.Y. CHANDRACHUD, HON'BLE MS. JUSTICE INDU MALHOTRA
Judgment by: HON'BLE THE CHIEF JUSTICE
Case number: W.P.(Crl.) No.-000076-000076 / 2016
Diary number: 14961 / 2016
Advocates: E. C. AGRAWALA Vs


Page 1
Page 2
Page 3
Page 4
Page 5
Page 6
Page 7
Page 8
Page 9
Page 10
Page 11
Page 12
Page 13
Page 14
Page 15
Page 16
Page 17
Page 18
Page 19
Page 20
Page 21
Page 22
Page 23
Page 24
Page 25
Page 26
Page 27
Page 28
Page 29
Page 30
Page 31
Page 32
Page 33
Page 34
Page 35
Page 36
Page 37
Page 38
Page 39
Page 40
Page 41
Page 42
Page 43
Page 44
Page 45
Page 46
Page 47
Page 48
Page 49
Page 50
Page 51
Page 52
Page 53
Page 54
Page 55
Page 56
Page 57
Page 58
Page 59
Page 60
Page 61
Page 62
Page 63
Page 64
Page 65
Page 66
Page 67
Page 68
Page 69
Page 70
Page 71
Page 72
Page 73
Page 74
Page 75
Page 76
Page 77
Page 78
Page 79
Page 80
Page 81
Page 82
Page 83
Page 84
Page 85
Page 86
Page 87
Page 88
Page 89
Page 90
Page 91
Page 92
Page 93
Page 94
Page 95
Page 96
Page 97
Page 98
Page 99
Page 100
Page 101
Page 102
Page 103
Page 104
Page 105
Page 106
Page 107
Page 108
Page 109
Page 110
Page 111
Page 112
Page 113
Page 114
Page 115
Page 116
Page 117
Page 118
Page 119
Page 120
Page 121
Page 122
Page 123
Page 124
Page 125
Page 126
Page 127
Page 128
Page 129
Page 130
Page 131
Page 132
Page 133
Page 134
Page 135
Page 136
Page 137
Page 138
Page 139
Page 140
Page 141
Page 142
Page 143
Page 144
Page 145
Page 146
Page 147
Page 148
Page 149
Page 150
Page 151
Page 152
Page 153
Page 154
Page 155
Page 156
Page 157
Page 158
Page 159
Page 160
Page 161
Page 162
Page 163
Page 164
Page 165
Page 166
Page 167
Page 168
Page 169
Page 170
Page 171
Page 172
Page 173
Page 174
Page 175
Page 176
Page 177
Page 178
Page 179
Page 180
Page 181
Page 182
Page 183
Page 184
Page 185
Page 186
Page 187
Page 188
Page 189
Page 190
Page 191
Page 192
Page 193
Page 194
Page 195
Page 196
Page 197
Page 198
Page 199
Page 200
Page 201
Page 202
Page 203
Page 204
Page 205
Page 206
Page 207
Page 208
Page 209
Page 210
Page 211
Page 212
Page 213
Page 214
Page 215
Page 216
Page 217
Page 218
Page 219
Page 220
Page 221
Page 222
Page 223
Page 224
Page 225
Page 226
Page 227
Page 228
Page 229
Page 230
Page 231
Page 232
Page 233
Page 234
Page 235
Page 236
Page 237
Page 238
Page 239
Page 240
Page 241
Page 242
Page 243
Page 244
Page 245
Page 246
Page 247
Page 248
Page 249
Page 250
Page 251
Page 252
Page 253
Page 254
Page 255
Page 256
Page 257
Page 258
Page 259
Page 260
Page 261
Page 262
Page 263
Page 264
Page 265
Page 266
Page 267
Page 268
Page 269
Page 270
Page 271
Page 272
Page 273
Page 274
Page 275
Page 276
Page 277
Page 278
Page 279
Page 280
Page 281
Page 282
Page 283
Page 284
Page 285
Page 286
Page 287
Page 288
Page 289
Page 290
Page 291
Page 292
Page 293
Page 294
Page 295
Page 296
Page 297
Page 298
Page 299
Page 300
Page 301
Page 302
Page 303
Page 304
Page 305
Page 306
Page 307
Page 308
Page 309
Page 310
Page 311
Page 312
Page 313
Page 314
Page 315
Page 316
Page 317
Page 318
Page 319
Page 320
Page 321
Page 322
Page 323
Page 324
Page 325
Page 326
Page 327
Page 328
Page 329
Page 330
Page 331
Page 332
Page 333
Page 334
Page 335
Page 336
Page 337
Page 338
Page 339
Page 340
Page 341
Page 342
Page 343
Page 344
Page 345
Page 346
Page 347
Page 348
Page 349
Page 350
Page 351
Page 352
Page 353
Page 354
Page 355
Page 356
Page 357
Page 358
Page 359
Page 360
Page 361
Page 362
Page 363
Page 364
Page 365
Page 366
Page 367
Page 368
Page 369
Page 370
Page 371
Page 372
Page 373
Page 374
Page 375
Page 376
Page 377
Page 378
Page 379
Page 380
Page 381
Page 382
Page 383
Page 384
Page 385
Page 386
Page 387
Page 388
Page 389
Page 390
Page 391
Page 392
Page 393
Page 394
Page 395
Page 396
Page 397
Page 398
Page 399
Page 400
Page 401
Page 402
Page 403
Page 404
Page 405
Page 406
Page 407
Page 408
Page 409
Page 410
Page 411
Page 412
Page 413
Page 414
Page 415
Page 416
Page 417
Page 418
Page 419
Page 420
Page 421
Page 422
Page 423
Page 424
Page 425
Page 426
Page 427
Page 428
Page 429
Page 430
Page 431
Page 432
Page 433
Page 434
Page 435
Page 436
Page 437
Page 438
Page 439
Page 440
Page 441
Page 442
Page 443
Page 444
Page 445
Page 446
Page 447
Page 448
Page 449
Page 450
Page 451
Page 452
Page 453
Page 454
Page 455
Page 456
Page 457
Page 458
Page 459
Page 460
Page 461
Page 462
Page 463
Page 464
Page 465
Page 466
Page 467
Page 468
Page 469
Page 470
Page 471
Page 472
Page 473
Page 474
Page 475
Page 476
Page 477
Page 478
Page 479
Page 480
Page 481
Page 482
Page 483
Page 484
Page 485
Page 486
Page 487
Page 488
Page 489
Page 490
Page 491
Page 492
Page 493
Page 494
Page 495
1

1  

REPORTABLE  

 

IN THE SUPREME COURT OF INDIA    

CRIMINAL ORIGINAL JURISDICTION    

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO. 76 OF 2016     

NAVTEJ SINGH JOHAR & ORS.              …Petitioner(s)   

 

VERSUS  

UNION OF INDIA   

THR. SECRETARY   

MINISTRY OF LAW AND JUSTICE        …Respondent(s)   

 

WITH  

 

WRIT PETITION (CIVIL) NO. 572 OF 2016  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO. 88 OF 2018  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO. 100 OF 2018  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO. 101 OF 2018  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO. 121 OF 2018  

 

J U D G M E N T    Dipak Misra, CJI (for himself and A.M. Khanwilkar, J.)  

 

 

C O N T E N T S  

S. No(s). Heading Page No(s)    

A. Introduction………………………………………… 3-11  

B. The Reference……………………………………… 11-15

2

2  

C. Submissions on behalf of the petitioners…… 15-30  

D. Submissions on behalf of the respondents  and other intervenors.………………………….…  

 31-44  

 E. Decisions in Naz Foundation and Suresh  

Koushal………………..……………………………..    

45-48    

F. Other judicial pronouncements on Section 377  IPC ……………………….…………………………..  

 48-57  

 G. The Constitution – an organic charter of  

progressive rights…………………………………    

57-64    

H. Transformative constitutionalism and the  rights of LGBT community……………………….  

 65-74  

 I. Constitutional morality and Section 377 IPC…. 74-81  

J. Perspective of human dignity…………………… 81-89  

K. Sexual orientation…………………………………. 89-96  

L. Privacy and its concomitant aspects…………... 96-111  

M. Doctrine of progressive realization of  rights………………………………………………….    

 111-118  

N. International perspective…………………………. 118  

(i) United States……………………………… 118-122  

(ii) Canada…………………………………….. 123-125  

(iii) South Africa………………………………. 125  

(iv) United Kingdom…………………………. 126-127  

(v) Other Courts/Jurisdictions…………….. 127-129

3

3  

O. Comparative analysis of Section 375 and  Section 377 IPC………………………………….…  

 129-140  

P.  

 Q.  

The litmus test for survival of Section 377  IPC…….………………………………………………    Conclusions…………………………………………  

 140-156  

156-166  

 

A. Introduction  

Not for nothing, the great German thinker, Johann Wolfgang  

von Goethe, had said, ―I am what I am, so take me as I am‖ and  

similarly, Arthur Schopenhauer had pronounced, ―No one can escape  

from their individuality‖.  In this regard, it is profitable to quote a few  

lines from John Stuart Mill:-  

―But society has now fairly got the better of individuality;  and the danger which threatens human nature is not  the excess, but the deficiency of personal impulses  and preferences.‖  

  The emphasis on the unique being of an individual is the salt of  

his/her life.  Denial of self-expression is inviting death.  Irreplaceability  

of individuality and identity is grant of respect to self.  This realization  

is one‘s signature and self-determined design.  One defines oneself.   

That is the glorious form of individuality.  In the present case, our

4

4  

deliberation and focus on the said concept shall be from various  

spectrums.   

2. Shakespeare through one of his characters in a play says  

―What‘s in a name? That which we call a rose by any other name  

would smell as sweet‖. The said phrase, in its basic sense, conveys  

that what really matters is the essential qualities of the substance and  

the fundamental characteristics of an entity but not the name by  

which it or a person is called. Getting further deeper into the meaning,  

it is understood that the name may be a convenient concept for  

identification but the essence behind the same is the core of identity.  

Sans identity, the name only remains a denotative term. Therefore,  

the identity is pivotal to one‘s being. Life bestows honour on it and  

freedom of living, as a facet of life, expresses genuine desire to have  

it. The said desire, one is inclined to think, is satisfied by the  

conception of constitutional recognition, and hence, emphasis is laid  

on the identity of an individual which is conceived under the  

Constitution. And the sustenance of identity is the filament of life. It is  

equivalent to authoring one‘s own life script where freedom broadens  

everyday.  Identity is equivalent to divinity.  

5

5  

3. The overarching ideals of individual autonomy and liberty,  

equality for all sans discrimination of any kind, recognition of identity  

with dignity and privacy of human beings constitute the cardinal four  

corners of our monumental Constitution forming the concrete  

substratum of our fundamental rights that has eluded certain sections  

of our society who are still living in the bondage of dogmatic social  

norms, prejudiced notions, rigid stereotypes, parochial mindset and  

bigoted perceptions.  Social exclusion, identity seclusion and isolation  

from the social mainstream are still the stark realities faced by  

individuals today and it is only when each and every individual is  

liberated from the shackles of such bondage and is able to work  

towards full development of his/her personality that we can call  

ourselves a truly free society.  The first step on the long path to  

acceptance of the diversity and variegated hues that nature has  

created has to be taken now by vanquishing the enemies of prejudice  

and injustice and undoing the wrongs done so as to make way for a  

progressive and inclusive realisation of social and economic rights  

embracing all and to begin a dialogue for ensuring equal rights and  

opportunities for the ―less than equal‖ sections of the society.  We  

have to bid adieu to the perceptions, stereotypes and prejudices

6

6  

deeply ingrained in the societal mindset so as to usher in inclusivity in  

all spheres and empower all citizens alike without any kind of  

alienation and discrimination.  

4. The natural identity of an individual should be treated to be  

absolutely essential to his being.  What nature gives is natural.  That  

is called nature within. Thus, that part of the personality of a person  

has to be respected and not despised or looked down upon. The said  

inherent nature and the associated natural impulses in that regard are  

to be accepted.  Non-acceptance of it by any societal norm or notion  

and punishment by law on some obsolete idea and idealism affects  

the kernel of the identity of an individual.  Destruction of individual  

identity would tantamount to crushing of intrinsic dignity that  

cumulatively encapsulates the values of privacy, choice, freedom of  

speech and other expressions.  It can be viewed from another angle.   

An individual in exercise of his choice may feel that he/she should be  

left alone but no one, and we mean, no one, should impose solitude  

on him/her.    

5. The eminence of identity has been luculently stated in National  

Legal Services Authority v. Union of India and others1, popularly  

                                                           1 (2014) 5 SCC 438

7

7  

known as NALSA case, wherein the Court was dwelling upon the  

status of identity of the transgenders. Radhakrishnan, J., after  

referring to catena of judgments and certain International Covenants,  

opined that gender identity is one of the most fundamental aspects of  

life which refers to a person‘s intrinsic sense of being male, female or  

transgender or transsexual person. A person‘s sex is usually  

assigned at birth, but a relatively small group of persons may be born  

with bodies which incorporate both or certain aspects of both male  

and female physiology. The learned Judge further observed that at  

times, genital anatomy problems may arise in certain persons in the  

sense that their innate perception of themselves is not in conformity  

with the sex assigned to them at birth and may include pre-and post-

operative transsexual persons and also persons who do not choose  

to undergo or do not have access to operation and also include  

persons who cannot undergo successful operation. Elaborating  

further, he said:-  

―Gender identity refers to each person‘s deeply felt  internal and individual experience of gender, which  may or may not correspond with the sex assigned at  birth, including the personal sense of the body which  may involve a freely chosen, modification of bodily  appearance or functions by medical, surgical or other  means and other expressions of gender, including  dress, speech and mannerisms. Gender identity,

8

8  

therefore, refers to an individual‘s self-identification as  a man, woman, transgender or other identified  category.‖  

 6. Adverting to the concept of discrimination, he stated:-  

―The discrimination on the ground of ―sex‖ under  Articles 15 and 16, therefore, includes discrimination  on the ground of gender identity. The expression ―sex‖  used in Articles 15 and 16 is not just limited to  biological sex of male or female, but intended to  include people who consider themselves to be neither  male nor female.‖  

 7. Dealing with the legality of transgender identity, Radhakrishnan,  

J. ruled:-  

―The self-identified gender can be either male or  female or a third gender. Hijras are identified as  persons of third gender and are not identified either as  male or female. Gender identity, as already indicated,  refers to a person‘s internal sense of being male,  female or a transgender, for example hijras do not  identify as female because of their lack of female  genitalia or lack of reproductive capability. This  distinction makes them separate from both male and  female genders and they consider themselves neither  man nor woman, but a ―third gender‖.‖  

 

8. Sikri, J., in his concurring opinion, dwelling upon the rights of  

transgenders, laid down that gender identification is an essential  

component which is required for enjoying civil rights by the  

community. It is only with this recognition that many rights attached to  

the sexual recognition as ―third gender‖ would be available to the said

9

9  

community more meaningfully viz. the right to vote, the right to own  

property, the right to marry, the right to claim a formal identity through  

a passport and a ration card, a driver‘s licence, the right to education,  

employment, health and so on. Emphasising on the aspect of human  

rights, he observed:-  

―…there seems to be no reason why a transgender  must be denied of basic human rights which includes  right to life and liberty with dignity, right to privacy and  freedom of expression, right to education and  empowerment, right against violence, right against  exploitation and right against discrimination. The  Constitution has fulfilled its duty of providing rights to  transgenders. Now it is time for us to recognise this  and to extend and interpret the Constitution in such a  manner to ensure a dignified life for transgender  people. All this can be achieved if the beginning is  made with the recognition of TG as third gender.‖    The aforesaid judgment, as is manifest, lays focus on  

inalienable ―gender identity‖ and correctly connects with human rights  

and the constitutionally guaranteed right to life and liberty with dignity.  

It lays stress on the judicial recognition of such rights as an  

inextricable component of Article 21 of the Constitution and decries  

any discrimination as that would offend Article 14, the ―fon juris‖ of  

our Constitution.  

9. It has to be borne in mind that search for identity as a basic  

human ideal has reigned the mind of every individual in many a

10

10  

sphere like success, fame, economic prowess, political assertion,  

celebrity status and social superiority, etc. But search for identity, in  

order to have apposite space in law, sans stigmas and sans fear has  

to have the freedom of expression about his/her being which is  

keenly associated with the constitutional concept of ―identity with  

dignity‖. When we talk about identity from the constitutional spectrum,  

it cannot be pigeon-holed singularly to one‘s orientation that may be  

associated with his/her birth and the feelings he/she develops when  

he/she grows up. Such a narrow perception may initially sound to  

subserve the purpose of justice but on a studied scrutiny, it is soon  

realized that the limited recognition keeps the individual choice at  

bay. The question that is required to be posed here is whether sexual  

orientation alone is to be protected or both orientation and choice are  

to be accepted as long as the exercise of these rights by an individual  

do not affect another‘s choice or, to put it succinctly, has the consent  

of the other where dignity of both is maintained and privacy, as a  

seminal facet of Article 21, is not dented. At the core of the concept of  

identity lies self-determination, realization of one‘s own abilities  

visualizing the opportunities and rejection of external views with a  

clear conscience that is in accord with constitutional norms and

11

11  

values or principles that are, to put in a capsule, ―constitutionally  

permissible‖. As long as it is lawful, one is entitled to determine and  

follow his/her pattern of life. And that is where the distinction between  

constitutional morality and social morality or ethicality assumes a  

distinguished podium, a different objective. Non-recognition in the  

fullest sense and denial of expression of choice by a statutory penal  

provision and giving of stamp of approval by a two-Judge Bench of  

this Court to the said penal provision, that is, Section 377 of the  

Indian Penal Code, in Suresh Kumar Koushal and another v. Naz  

Foundation and others2  overturning the judgment of the Delhi High  

Court in Naz Foundation v. Government of NCT of Delhi and  

others3, is the central issue involved in the present controversy.   

B.  The Reference  

10.  Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 76 of 2016 was filed for declaring  

―right to sexuality‖, ―right to sexual autonomy‖ and ―right to choice of a  

sexual partner‖ to be part of the right to life guaranteed under Article  

21 of the Constitution of India and further to declare Section 377 of  

the Indian Penal Code (for short, ―IPC‖) to be unconstitutional.  When  

the said Writ Petition was listed before a three-Judge Bench on  

                                                           2 (2014) 1 SCC 1  3 (2009) 111 DRJ 1

12

12  

08.01.2018, the Court referred to a two-Judge Bench decision  

rendered in Suresh Koushal (supra) wherein this Court had  

overturned the decision rendered by the Division Bench of the Delhi  

High Court in Naz Foundation (supra).  It was submitted by Mr.  

Arvind Datar, learned senior counsel appearing for the writ  

petitioners, on the said occasion that the two-Judge Bench in Suresh  

Koushal (supra) had been guided by social morality leaning on  

majoritarian perception whereas the issue, in actuality, needed to be  

debated upon in the backdrop of constitutional morality. A contention  

was also advanced that the interpretation placed in Suresh Kumar  

(supra) upon Article 21 of the Constitution is extremely narrow and, in  

fact, the Court has been basically guided by Article 14 of the  

Constitution.  Reliance was placed on the pronouncement in NALSA  

case wherein this Court had emphasized on ―gender identity and  

sexual orientation‖. Attention of this Court was also invited to a nine-

Judge Bench decision in K.S. Puttaswamy and another v. Union of  

India and others 4  wherein the majority, speaking through  

Chandrachud, J., has opined that sexual orientation is an essential  

component of rights guaranteed under the Constitution which are not  

                                                           4 (2017) 10 SCC 1  

13

13  

formulated on majoritarian favour or acceptance. Kaul, J, in his  

concurring opinion, referred to the decision in Mosley v. News  

Group Newspapers Ltd. 5  to highlight that the emphasis for  

individual‘s freedom to conduct his sex life and personal relationships  

as he wishes, subject to the permitted exceptions, countervails public  

interest.  

11. The further submission that was advanced by Mr. Datar was  

that privacy of the individual having been put on such a high pedestal  

and sexual orientation having been emphasized in the NALSA case,  

Section 377 IPC cannot be construed as a reasonable restriction as  

that would have the potentiality to destroy the individual autonomy  

and sexual orientation. It is an accepted principle of interpretation of  

statutes that a provision does not become unconstitutional merely  

because there can be abuse of the same. Similarly, though a  

provision on the statute book is not invoked on many occasions, yet it  

does not fall into the sphere of the doctrine of desuetude. However,  

Suresh Koushal's case has been guided by the aforesaid doctrine of  

desuetude.  

                                                           5 [2008] EWHC 1777 (QB)

14

14  

12. Appreciating the said submissions, the three-Judge Bench  

stated that:-   

―Certain other aspects need to be noted. Section 377  IPC uses the phraseology ―carnal intercourse against  the order of nature‖. The determination of order of  nature is not a constant phenomenon. Social morality  also changes from age to age. The law copes with life  and accordingly change takes place. The morality that  public perceives, the Constitution may not conceive of.  The individual autonomy and also individual orientation  cannot be atrophied unless the restriction is regarded  as reasonable to yield to the morality of the  Constitution. What is natural to one may not be natural  to the other but the said natural orientation and choice  cannot be allowed to cross the boundaries of law and  as the confines of law cannot tamper or curtail the  inherent right embedded in an individual under Article  21 of the Constitution. A section of people or  individuals who exercise their choice should never  remain in a state of fear. When we say so, we may not  be understood to have stated that there should not be  fear of law because fear of law builds civilised society.  But that law must have the acceptability of the  Constitutional parameters. That is the litmus test.       It is necessary to note, in the course of hearing  on a query being made and Mr. Datar very fairly stated  that he does not intend to challenge that part of  Section 377 which relates to carnal intercourse with  animals and that apart, he confines to consenting acts  between two adults. As far as the first aspect is  concerned, that is absolutely beyond debate. As far as  the second aspect is concerned, that needs to be  debated. The consent between two adults has to be  the primary pre-condition. Otherwise the children  would become prey, and protection of the children in  all spheres has to be guarded and protected. Taking all  the apsects in a cumulative manner, we are of the

15

15  

view, the decision in Suresh Kumar Koushal's case  (supra) requires re-consideration.‖  

 

The three-Judge Bench expressed the opinion that the issues  

raised should be answered by a larger Bench and, accordingly,  

referred the matter to the larger Bench. That is how the matter has  

been placed before us.  

C.  Submissions on behalf of the petitioners  

13. We have heard Mr. Mukul Rohatgi, learned senior counsel  

assisted by Mr. Saurabh Kirpal, learned counsel appearing for the  

petitioners in Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 76 of 2016, Ms. Jayna  

Kothari, learned counsel for the petitioner in Writ Petition (Civil) No.  

572 of 2016, Mr. Arvind P. Datar, learned senior counsel for the  

petitioner in Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 88 of 2018, Mr. Anand  

Grover, learned senior counsel for the petitioners in Writ Petition  

(Criminal) Nos. 100 of 2018 and 101 of 2018 and Dr. Menaka  

Guruswamy, learned counsel for the petitioner in Writ Petition  

(Criminal) No. 121 of 2018. We have also heard Mr. Ashok Desai, Mr.  

Chander Uday Singh, Mr. Shyam Divan and Mr. Krishnan Venugopal,  

learned senior counsel appearing for various intervenors in the  

matter. A compilation of written submissions has been filed by the  

petitioners as well as the intervenors.  

16

16  

14. We have heard Mr. Tushar Mehta, learned Additional Solicitor  

General for the Union of India, Mr. K. Radhakrishnan, learned senior  

counsel appearing in Interlocutory Application No. 94284 of 2018 in  

Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 76 of 2016, Mr. Mahesh Jethmalani,  

learned senior counsel appearing in Interlocutory Application No.  

91147 in Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 76 of 2016, Mr. Soumya  

Chakraborty, learned senior counsel appearing in Interlocutory  

Application No. 94348 of 2018 in Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 76 of  

2016, Mr. Manoj V. George, learned counsel appearing for Apostolic  

Alliance of Churches & Utkal Christian Council and Dr. Harshvir  

Pratap Sharma, learned counsel appearing in Interlocutory  

Application No. 93411 of 2018 in Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 76 of  

2016.  

15. It is submitted on behalf of the petitioners and the intervenors  

that homosexuality, bisexuality and other sexual orientations are  

equally natural and reflective of expression of choice and inclination  

founded on consent of two persons who are eligible in law to express  

such consent and it is neither a physical nor a mental illness, rather  

they are natural variations of expression and free thinking process  

and to make it a criminal offence is offensive of the well established

17

17  

principles pertaining to individual dignity and decisional autonomy  

inherent in the personality of a person, a great discomfort to gender  

identity, destruction of the right to privacy which is a pivotal facet of  

Article 21 of the Constitution, unpalatable to the highly cherished idea  

of freedom and a trauma to the conception of expression of biological  

desire which revolves around the pattern of mosaic of true  

manifestation of identity. That apart, the phrase ―order of nature‖ is  

limited to the procreative concept that may have been conceived as  

natural by a systemic conservative approach and such limitations do  

not really take note of inborn traits or developed orientations or, for  

that matter, consensual acts which relate to responses to series of  

free exercise of assertions of one‘s bodily autonomy. It is further  

argued that their growth of personality, relation building endeavour to  

enter into a live-in relationship or to form an association with a sense  

of commonality have become a mirage and the essential desires are  

crippled which violates Article 19(1)(a) of the Constitution. It is urged  

that the American Psychological Association has opined that sexual  

orientation is a natural condition and attraction towards the same sex  

or opposite sex are both naturally equal, the only difference being  

that the same sex attraction arises in far lesser numbers.  

18

18  

16. The petitioners have highlighted that the rights of the lesbian,  

gay, bisexual and transgender (LGBT) community, who comprise 7-

8% of the total Indian population, need to be recognized and  

protected, for sexual orientation is an integral and innate facet of  

every individual‘s identity. A person belonging to the said community  

does not become an alien to the concept of individual and his  

individualism cannot be viewed with a stigma. The impact of sexual  

orientation on an individual‘s life is not limited to their intimate lives  

but also impacts their family, professional, social and educational life.  

As per the petitioners, such individuals (sexual minorities in societies)  

need protection more than the heterosexuals so as to enable them to  

achieve their full potential and to live freely without fear,  

apprehension or trepidation in such a manner that they are not  

discriminated against by the society openly or insidiously or by the  

State in multifarious ways in matters such as employment, choice of  

partner, testamentary rights, insurability, medical treatment in  

hospitals and other similar rights arising from live-in relationships  

which, after the decision in Indra Sarma v. V.K.V. Sarma 6 , is  

recognized even by the ―Protection of Women from Domestic  

                                                           6 (2013) 15 SCC 755

19

19  

Violence Act, 2005‖ for various kinds of live-in relationships. The  

same protection, as per the petitioners, must be accorded to same  

sex relationships.   

17. It is urged by the learned counsel for the petitioners that  

individuals belonging to the LGBT group suffer discrimination and  

abuse throughout their lives due to the existence of Section 377 IPC  

which is nothing but a manifestation of a mindset of societal values  

prevalent during the Victorian era where sexual activities were  

considered mainly for procreation. The said community remains in a  

constant state of fear which is not conducive for their growth.  It is  

contended that they suffer at the hands of law and are also deprived  

of the citizenry rights which are protected under the Constitution. The  

law should have treated them as natural victims and sensitized the  

society towards their plight and laid stress on such victimisation,  

however, the reverse is being done due to which a sense of  

estrangement and alienation has developed and continues to prevail  

amongst the members belonging to the LGBT group. Compulsory  

alienation due to stigma and threat is contrary to the fundamental  

principle of liberty.

20

20  

18. The petitioners have referred to the decision of this Court in  

NALSA case wherein transgenders have been recognized as a third  

gender apart from male and female and have been given certain  

rights. Yet, in view of the existence of Section 377 in the IPC,  

consensual activities amongst transgenders would continue to  

constitute an offence. Drawing inspiration from the NALSA case, the  

petitioners submit that the rights of the LGBT group are not fully  

realized and they remain incomplete citizens because their  

expression as regards sexuality is not allowed to be pronounced  

owing to the criminality attached to the sexual acts between these  

persons which deserves to be given a burial and, therefore, the rights  

of the LGBT community also need equal, if not more, constitutional  

protection. Accordingly, the petitioners are of the view that Section  

377 of the IPC be read down qua the LGBT community so as to  

confine it only to the offence of bestiality and non-consensual acts in  

view of the fact that with the coming into force of the Criminal Law  

(Amendment) Act, 2013 and the Protection of Children from Sexual  

Offences Act, 2012 (POCSO Act), the scope of sexual assault has  

been widened to include non peno-vaginal sexual assault and also

21

21  

criminalize non-consensual sexual acts between children thereby  

plugging important gaps in the law governing sexual violence in India.   

19. The petitioners have also submitted that Section 377, despite  

being a pre-constitutional law, was retained post the Constitution  

coming into effect by virtue of Article 372 of the Constitution, but it  

must be noted that the presumption of constitutionality is merely an  

evidentiary burden initially on the person seeking to challenge the  

vires of a statute and once any violation of fundamental rights or  

suspect classification is prima facie shown, then such presumption  

has no role. In the case at hand, the petitioners face a violation of  

their fundamental rights to an extent which is manifestly clear and it is  

a violation which strikes at the very root or substratum of their  

existence. The discrimination suffered at the hands of the majority,  

the onslaught to their dignity and invasion on the right to privacy is  

demonstrably visible and permeates every nook and corner of the  

society.  

20. It is the argument of the petitioners that Section 377, if retained in  

its present form, would involve the violation of, not one but, several  

fundamental rights of the LGBTs, namely, right to privacy, right to  

dignity, equality, liberty and right to freedom of expression. The

22

22  

petitioners contend that sexual orientation which is a natural corollary  

of gender identity is protected under Article 21 of the Constitution and  

any discrimination meted out to the LGBT community on the basis of  

sexual orientation would run counter to the mandate provided under  

the Constitution and the said view has also gained approval of this  

Court in the NALSA case.  

21. The petitioners have also relied upon the view in K.S.  

Puttaswamy (supra) to advance their argument that sexual  

orientation is also an essential attribute of privacy. Therefore,  

protection of both sexual orientation and right to privacy of an  

individual is extremely important, for without the enjoyment of these  

basic and fundamental rights, individual identity may lose  

significance, a sense of trepidation may take over and their existence  

would be reduced to mere survival. It is further urged that sexual  

orientation and privacy lie at the core of the fundamental rights which  

are guaranteed under Articles 14, 19 and 21 of the Constitution and  

in the light of the decision in Puttaswamy (supra), it has become  

imperative that Section 377 be struck down. It is contended that the  

right to privacy has to take within its ambit and sweep the right of  

every individual, including LGBTs, to make decisions as per their

23

23  

choice without the fear that they may be subjected to humiliation or  

shunned by the society merely because of a certain choice or manner  

of living.  

22. Having canvassed with vehemence that sexual orientation is an  

important facet of the right to privacy which has been raised to the  

pedestal of a cherished right, the learned counsel for the petitioners  

have vigorously propounded that sexual autonomy and the right to  

choose a partner of one‘s choice is an inherent aspect of the right to  

life and right to autonomy.  In furtherance of the said view, they have  

relied upon the authorities in Shakti Vahini v. Union of India and  

others7 and Shafin Jahan v. Asokan K.M.8 wherein it has been  

clearly recognized that an individual‘s exercise of choice in choosing  

a partner is a feature of dignity and, therefore, it is protected under  

Articles 19 and 21 of the Constitution.    

23. According to the petitioners, there is no difference between  

persons who defy social conventions to enter into inter-religious and  

inter-caste marriages and those who choose a same sex partner in  

the sense that the society may disapprove of inter-caste or inter-

religious marriages but this Court is for enforcing constitutional rights.  

                                                           7(2018) 7 SCC 192  8AIR 2018 SC 1933 : 2018 (5) SCALE 422

24

24  

Similarly, as per the petitioners, even if there is disapproval by the  

majority of the sexual orientation or exercise of choice by the LGBT  

persons, the Court as the final arbiter of the constitutional rights,  

should disregard social morality and uphold and protect constitutional  

morality which has been adverted to by this Court in several cases,  

including Manoj Narula v. Union of India9, for that is the governing  

rule. It is argued that the Delhi High Court in Naz Foundation (supra)  

has referred to and analysed the concept of constitutional morality  

and ultimately struck down Section 377 IPC clearly stating that carnal  

intercourse between homosexuals and heterosexuals with consent  

cannot be an offence.   

24. The LGBT persons cannot, according to the petitioners, be  

penalized simply for choosing a same sex partner, for the  

constitutional guarantee of choice of partner extends to the LGBT  

persons as well. Learned counsel for the petitioners and the  

supporting intervenors have submitted that sexual orientation, being  

an innate facet of individual identity, is protected under the right to  

dignity. To bolster the said argument, reliance has been placed upon  

Francis Coralie Mullin v. Administrator, Union Territory of Delhi  

                                                           9 (2014) 9 SCC 1

25

25  

and others10 and Common Cause (A Registered Society) v. Union  

of India and another11 wherein it was held that the right to life and  

liberty, as envisaged under Article 21, is meaningless unless it  

encompasses within its sphere individual dignity and right to dignity  

includes the right to carry such functions and activities as would  

constitute the meaningful expression of the human self.  

25.  It is submitted that Section 377 is an anathema to the concept  

of fraternity as enshrined in the Preamble to our Constitution and the  

Indian Constitution mandates that we must promote fraternity  

amongst the citizens sans which unity shall remain a distant dream.  

26. The petitioners have further contended that Section 377 is  

violative of Article 14 of the Constitution as the said Section is vague  

in the sense that carnal intercourse against the order of nature is  

neither defined in the Section nor in the IPC or, for that matter, any  

other law. There is, as per the petitioners, no intelligible differentia or  

reasonable classification between natural and unnatural sex as long  

as it is consensual in view of the decision of this Court in Anuj Garg  

and others v. Hotel Association of India and others12 which lays  

down the principle that classification which may have been treated as                                                              10(1981) 1 SCC 608  11(2018) 5 SCC 1  12(2008) 3 SCC 1

26

26  

valid at the time of its adoption may cease to be so on account of  

changing social norms.  

27. Section 377, as argued by the petitioners, is manifestly arbitrary  

and over-broad and for the said purpose, immense inspiration has  

been drawn from the principles stated in Shayara Bano v. Union of  

India and others13 , for making consensual relationship a crime on  

the ground that it is against the order of nature suffers from manifest  

arbitrariness at the fulcrum.  

28.  It is the case of the petitioners that Section 377 violates Article  

15 of the Constitution since there is discrimination inherent in it based  

on the sex of a person‘s sexual partner as under Section 376(c) to (e),  

a person can be prosecuted for acts done with an opposite sex  

partner without her consent, whereas the same acts if done with a  

same-sex partner are criminalized even if the partner consents. The  

petitioners have drawn the attention of this Court to the Justice J.S  

Verma Committee on Amendments to Criminal Law which had  

observed that ‗sex‘ occurring in Article 15 includes sexual orientation  

and, thus, as per the petitioners, Section 377 is also violative of  

Article 15 of the Constitution on this count.  

                                                           13(2017) 9 SCC 1

27

27  

29.  It is argued with astuteness that Section 377 has a chilling  

effect on Article 19(1)(a) of the Constitution which protects the  

fundamental right of freedom of expression including that of LGBT  

persons to express their sexual identity and orientation, through  

speech, choice of romantic/sexual partner, expression of  

romantic/sexual desire, acknowledgment of relationships or any other  

means and that Section 377 constitutes an unreasonable exception  

and is thereby not covered  under Article 19(2) of the Constitution. To  

buttress the said stance, reliance is placed upon the decision in S.  

Khushboo v. Kanniammal and another14 wherein it has been held  

that law should not be used in such a manner that it has a chilling  

effect on the freedom of speech and expression.  Additionally, the  

view in NALSA case has also been strongly pressed into service to  

emphasize that the said decision clearly spells out that the right under  

Article 19(1)(a) includes one‘s right to expression of his/her self-

identified gender which can be expressed through words, action,  

behaviour or any other form.  

30. The petitioners have also contended that Section 377 violates the  

rights of LGBT persons under Article 19(1)(c) and denies them the  

                                                           14(2010) 5 SCC 600

28

28  

right to form associations. Similarly, such persons are hesitant to  

register companies to provide benefits to sexual minorities due to the  

fear of state action and social stigma. Further, a conviction under  

Section 377 IPC renders such persons ineligible for appointment as a  

director of a company.  

31.  It is averred that Section 377 IPC, by creating a taint of  

criminality, deprives the LGBT persons of their right to reputation  

which is a facet of the right to life and liberty of a citizen under Article  

21 of the Constitution as observed by this Court in Kishore Samrite v.  

State of U.P. and others15 and Umesh Kumar v. State of Andhra  

Pradesh and another16 to the effect that reputation is an element of  

personal security and protected by the Constitution with the right to  

enjoyment of life and liberty. This right, as per the petitioners, is being  

denied to the LGBT persons because of Section 377 IPC as it makes  

them apprehensive to speak openly about their sexual orientation and  

makes them vulnerable to extortion, blackmail and denial of State  

machinery for either protection or for enjoyment of other rights and  

amenities and on certain occasions, the other concomitant rights are  

affected.    

                                                           15(2013) 2 SCC 398  16(2013) 10 SCC 591

29

29  

32.  The petitioners have advanced their argument that Section 377  

IPC impedes the ability of the LGBTs to realize the constitutionally  

guaranteed right to shelter. To illustrate the same, the petitioners  

have drawn the attention of the Court to the fact that LGBTs seek  

assistance of private resources such as Gay Housing Assistance  

Resources (GHAR) in order to access safe and suitable shelter and  

this is an indication that the members of this community are in need  

of immediate care and protection of the State.    

33. The decision in Suresh Koushal (supra), as per the petitioners,  

is per incuriam as the view observed therein has failed to take into  

account the amendment to Section 375 IPC which has rendered  

sexual ‗carnal intercourse against the order of nature‘ between man  

and woman as permissible. Section 377, on the other hand, has  

continued to render same sex carnal intercourse as an offence, even  

if it is consensual. Further, the petitioners have assailed the decision  

of this Court in Suresh Koushal’s case on the ground that the view  

in the said decision on classification is contrary to the ‗impact or effect  

test‘, for the result, in ultimate eventuality, leads to discrimination.   

Thus, the petitioners have contended that after Puttaswamy (supra),  

the view in Suresh Koushal (supra) needs to be overruled and the

30

30  

proper test would be whether Section 377 IPC can be enacted by the  

Parliament today after the decisions of this Court in NALSA (supra)  

and Puttaswamy (supra) and other authorities laying immense  

emphasis on individual choice.  

34.  It is further contended that LGBT persons are deprived of their  

rights due to the presence of Section 377 as they fear prosecution  

and persecution upon revealing their sexual identities and, therefore,  

this class of persons never approached this Court as petitioners,  

rather they have always relied upon their teachers, parents, mental  

health professionals and other organizations such as NGOs to speak  

on their behalf. It is urged that the appellants in Suresh Koushal  

(supra) led this Court to assume that LGBT persons constitute only a  

minuscule fraction whereas most of the studies indicate that they  

constitute at least 7-8% of the population and that apart, rights are  

not determined on the basis of percentage of populace but on a real  

scrutiny of the existence of right and denial of the same.  It is the  

stand of the petitioners that majority perception or view cannot be the  

guiding factor for sustaining the constitutionality of a provision or to  

declare a provision as unconstitutional.  

 

31

31  

D. Submissions on behalf of the respondents and other  intervenors  

 35. The respondent, Union of India, has, vide affidavit dated 11th  

July, 2018, submitted that the matter at hand was referred to a  

Constitution Bench to decide as to whether the law laid down in  

Suresh Koushal (supra) is correct or not and the only question  

referred to this Bench is the question of the constitutional validity of  

criminalizing 'consensual acts of adults in private' falling under  

Section 377 IPC.  

36. Further, the Union has submitted that so far as the  

constitutional validity of Section 377 IPC, to the extent it applies to  

'consensual acts of adults in private', is concerned, the respondent  

leaves the same to the wisdom of this Court.  

37. The respondent has also contended that in the event Section  

377 IPC so far as 'consensual acts of adults in private' is declared  

unconstitutional, other ancillary issues or rights which have not been  

referred to this Bench for adjudication may not be dealt with by this  

Bench as in that case, the Union of India expresses the wish to file  

detailed affidavit in reply, for consideration of other issues and rights  

would have far reaching and wide ramifications under various other  

laws and will also have consequences which are neither

32

32  

contemplated in the reference nor required to be answered by this  

Hon‘ble Bench.  

38. The respondent has submitted that allowing any other issue  

(other than the constitutional validity of Section 377 IPC) to be argued  

and adjudicating the same without giving an opportunity to the Union  

of India to file a counter affidavit may not be in the interest of justice  

and would be violative of the principles of natural justice.  

39. Another set of written submissions has been filed by Shri K.  

Radhakrishnan, senior counsel, on behalf of intervenor-NGO, Trust  

God Ministries. The said intervenor has submitted that the  

observations of this Court in Puttaswamy (supra), particularly in Para  

146, virtually pre-empt and forestall the aforesaid NGO from raising  

substantial contentions to the effect that there is no uncanalised and  

unbridled right to privacy and the said right cannot be abused. Further,  

the intervenor has contended that there is no personal liberty to  

abuse one‘s organs and that the offensive acts proscribed by Section  

377 IPC are committed by abusing the organs. Such acts, as per the  

intervenor, are undignified and derogatory to the constitutional  

concept of dignity and if any infraction is caused to the concept of

33

33  

dignity, then it would amount to constitutional wrong and  

constitutional immorality.   

40. It is also the case of the intervenor that issues pertaining to the  

constitutional and other legal rights of the transgender community,  

their gender identity and sexual orientation have been exhaustively  

considered in the light of the various provisions of the Constitution  

and, accordingly, reliefs have been granted by this Court in NALSA  

(supra). It is contended by the intervenor that no further reliefs can be  

granted to them and the prayers made by them is only to abuse  

privacy and personal liberty by transgressing the concepts of dignity  

and public morality.  

41. As per the intervenor, Section 377 rightly makes the acts stated  

therein punishable as Section 377 has been incorporated after taking  

note of the legal systems and principles which prevailed in ancient  

India and now in 2018, the said Section is more relevant legally,  

medically, morally and constitutionally.  

42. To illustrate this, the intervenor has drawn the attention of this  

Court to W. Friedmann from 'Law in a Changing Society' wherein he  

has observed that to prohibit a type of conduct which a particular  

society considers worthy of condemnation by criminal sanctions is

34

34  

deeply influenced by the values governing that society and it,  

therefore, varies from one country to another and one period of  

history to another.  

43. Further, it has been contended by the intervenor that persons  

indulging in unnatural sexual acts which have been made punishable  

under Section 377 IPC are more susceptible and vulnerable to  

contracting HIV/AIDS and the percentage of prevalence of AIDS in  

homosexuals is much greater than heterosexuals and that the right to  

privacy may not be extended in order to enable people to indulge in  

unnatural offences and thereby contact AIDS.  

44. It is also the case of the intervenor that if Section 377 is  

declared unconstitutional, then the family system which is the bulwark  

of social culture will be in shambles, the institution of marriage will be  

detrimentally affected and rampant homosexual activities for money  

would tempt and corrupt young Indians into this trade.  

45. Written submissions have also been filed on behalf of Mr.  

Suresh Kumar Koushal, intervenor, submitting therein that the  

argument of the petitioners that consensual acts of adults in private  

have been decriminalized in many parts of the world and, therefore, it  

deserves to be decriminalized in India as well does not hold good for

35

35  

several reasons inasmuch as the political, economic and cultural  

heritage of those countries are very different from India which is a  

multicultural and multi-linguistic country.  

46. The intervenor has contended that since fundamental rights are  

not absolute, there is no unreasonableness in Section 377 IPC and  

decriminalizing the same would run foul to all religions practised in  

the country, and, while deciding the ambit and scope of constitutional  

morality, Article 25 also deserves to be given due consideration.  

47. Another application for intervention, being I.A No. 91250 of  

2018, was filed and the same was allowed. It has been contended by  

the said intervenor that in the attempt that Section 377 is struck down,  

it would render the victims complaining of forced acts covered under  

the existing Section 377 IPC remediless as the said Section not only  

impinges on carnal intercourse against the order of nature between  

two consenting adults but also applies to forced penile non- vaginal  

sexual intercourse between adults. This, as per the intervenor, would  

be contrary to the decision of this Court in Iqbal Singh Marwah and  

another v. Meenakshi Marwah and another17.  

                                                           17 (2005) 4 SCC 370

36

36  

48. The applicant has also submitted that in the event consenting  

acts between two same sex adults are excluded from the ambit of  

Section 377 IPC, then a married woman would be rendered  

remediless under the IPC against her bi-sexual husband and his  

consenting male partner indulging in any sexual acts.  

49. The intervenor has suggested that the alleged misuse of  

Section 377 IPC as highlighted by the petitioners can be curbed by  

adding an explanation to Section 377 IPC defining 'aggrieved person'  

which shall include only non-consenting partner or aggrieved person  

or wife or husband or any person on their behalf on the lines of  

Section 198(1) of Code of Criminal Procedure, 1973. This, as per  

the applicant, would curb any mala fide complaint lodged by  

authorities and vindictive or mischievous persons when the act  

complained of is 'consenting act' between two persons. Further, the  

applicant has submitted that this Court may be pleased to identify that  

the courts shall take cognizance of an offence under Section 377 IPC  

only on a complaint made by an aggrieved person. Such an approach,  

as per the applicant, inherently respects consent and also protects  

from interference and safeguards the privacy and dignity of an  

individual under Article 21 of the Constitution.

37

37  

50. The applicant has also contended that the constitutionality of  

any legislation is always to be presumed and if there is any  

vagueness in the definition of any section, the courts have to give  

such a definition which advances the purpose of the legislation and  

that the courts must make every effort to uphold the constitutional  

validity of a statute if that requires giving a stretched construction in  

view of the decisions of this Court in K.A. Abbas v. Union of India  

and another18 and Rt. Rev. Msgr. Mark Netto v. State of Kerala  

and others19.  

51. The applicant, through his learned counsel Mr. Harvinder  

Chowdhury, submits that if the right to privacy as recognized in  

Puttaswamy (supra) is allowed its full scope and swing, then that  

itself would rule out prosecution in all cases of consensual  

unnatural sex between all couples, whether heterosexual or  

homosexual, and without having to engage in reading down, much  

less striking down of, the provisions of Section 377 IPC in its  

present form. This is so because the State cannot compel  

individuals engaging in consensual sexual acts from testifying  

                                                           18 (1970) 2 SCC 780  19 (1979) 1 SCC 23

38

38  

against one another as it involves a breach of privacy unless the  

consent itself is under challenge and one cannot be a consenting  

victim of a crime so long as the consent is legally valid.  

52. Submissions have also been advanced on behalf of Raza  

Academy, intervenor, through its learned counsel Mr. R.R Kishore,  

who has contended that homosexuality is against the order of  

nature and Section 377 rightly forbids it. Prohibition against carnal  

intercourse involving penetration into non-sexual parts of the body  

does not constitute discrimination as laws based on biological  

reality can never be unconstitutional, for if a male is treated as a  

male, a female as a female and a transgender as a transgender, it  

does not amount to discrimination.  

53. The applicant has submitted that the purpose of criminal law is  

to protect the citizens from something that is injurious and since  

carnal intercourse between two persons is offensive and injurious, it  

is well within the State's jurisdiction to put reasonable restrictions to  

forbid such aberrant human behaviour by means of legislation, for it  

is the duty of the State that people with abnormal conduct are  

prohibited from imperiling the life, health and security of the

39

39  

community. Unrestrained pleasure, and that too of a lascivious  

nature, is not conducive for the growth of a civilized society, such  

inordinate gratification needs to be curbed and, thus, prohibition  

against carnal intercourse as defined in Section 377 IPC does not  

violate the constitutional rights of a person.  

54. Another application for intervention, being I.A No. 9341 of  

2011, was filed and allowed. The applicant, in his written  

submissions, after delineating the concept of immorality, has  

submitted that the doctrine of manifest arbitrariness is of no  

application to the present case as the law is not manifestly or  

otherwise arbitrary, for Section 377 criminalizes an act irrespective of  

gender or sexual orientation of the persons involved. The universal  

application of the said provision without any gender bias is the  

touchstone of Part III of the Constitution and is not arbitrary as there  

is no intentional or unreasonable discrimination in the provision.  

55. The applicant has drawn the attention of this Court to the case  

of Fazal Rab Choudhary v. State of Bihar20 wherein this Court  

held that the offence under Section 377 IPC implies sexual  

                                                           20(1982) 3 SCC 9

40

40  

perversity. Further, it is the case of the applicant that there should  

not be identical transplantation of Western ideology in our country  

which has also been a matter of concern for this Court in  

Jagmohan Singh v. State of U.P.21  

56. The applicant, after citing the case of State of Gujarat v.  

Mirzapur Moti Kureshi Kassab Jamat and others22, has stressed  

upon the fact that the interest of a citizen or a section of the society,  

howsoever important, is secondary to the interest of the country or  

community as a whole and while judging the reasonability of  

restrictions imposed on fundamental rights, due consideration must  

also be given to the Directive Principles stated in Part IV. In view of  

these aforesaid submissions, the applicant has submitted that  

fundamental rights may not be overstretched and the Directive  

Principles of State Policy which are fundamental in the governance  

of the country cannot be neglected, for they are not less significant  

than what is fundamental in the life of an individual as held in  

Kesavananda Bharati v. Union of India23.  

                                                           21 (1973) 1 SCC 20  22 (2005) 8 SCC 534  23 (1973) 4 SCC 225

41

41  

57. Another application for intervention, being I.A. No. 76790 of  

2018, has been filed by Apostolic Alliance of Churches and the Utkal  

Christian Council. The applicants have submitted that the Court,  

while interpreting Section 377 IPC, has to keep in mind that there can  

be situations where consent is obtained by putting a person in fear of  

death or hurt or consent can also be obtained under some  

misconception or due to unsoundness of mind, intoxication or  

inability to understand the nature and the consequences of the acts  

prohibited by Section 377 IPC.  

58. The applicant has also advanced the argument that Section  

377 IPC in its present form does not violate Article 14 of the  

Constitution as it merely defines a particular offence and its  

punishment and it is well within the power of the State to determine  

who should be regarded as a class for the purpose of a legislation  

and this, as per the applicant, is reasonable classification in the  

context of Section 377 IPC.  

59. Further, the applicant has contended that Section 377 IPC is  

not violative of Article 15 of the Constitution as the said Article  

prohibits discrimination on the grounds of only religion, race, caste,

42

42  

sex, place of birth or any of them but not sexual orientation. The word  

‗sexual orientation‘, as per the applicant, is alien to our Constitution  

and the same cannot be imported within it for testing the  

constitutional validity of a provision or legislation. As per the applicant,  

if the word 'sex' has to be replaced by 'sexual orientation', it would  

require a constitutional amendment.  

60. It is also the case of the applicant that the Yogyakarta  

principles which have been heavily relied upon by the petitioners to  

bolster their stand have limited sanctity inasmuch as they do not  

amount to an international treaty binding on the State parties and  

there are no inter-governmentally negotiated international  

instruments or agreed human rights treaties on the issue of LGBTs.  

61. Further, the applicant has submitted that there is no  

requirement to reconsider the decision of this Court in Suresh  

Koushal (supra) wherein it was held that there is a presumption of  

constitutionality of a legislation and the Court must adopt self-

restraint and thereby refrain from giving birth to judicial legislation. In  

the applicant's view, the legislative wisdom of the Parliament must be

43

43  

respected and it must be left to the Parliament to amend Section 377  

IPC, if so desired.  

62. The applicant has contended that if the prayers of the  

petitioners herein are allowed, it would amount to judicial legislation,  

for the Courts cannot add or delete words into a statute.  It is stated  

that the words 'consent' and/or 'without consent' are not mentioned in  

Section 377 IPC and, therefore, the Courts cannot make such an  

artificial distinction. To buttress this stand, the applicant has relied  

upon the decision of this Court in Sakshi v. Union of India and  

others 24  wherein it was observed that the attention of the Court  

should be on what has been said and also on what has not been said  

while interpreting the statute and that it would be wrong and  

dangerous for the Court to proceed by substituting some other words  

in a statute since it is well settled that a statute enacting an offence  

or imposing a penalty has to be strictly construed.   

63. The applicant has also drawn the attention of this Court to the  

decision in Union of India and another v. Deoki Nandan  

Aggarwal25 wherein it was observed that the Court cannot rewrite,  

                                                           24(2004) 5 SCC 518  251992 Supp. (1) SCC 323

44

44  

recast or re-frame the legislation for the good reason that it has no  

power to legislate since the power to legislate has not been conferred  

upon the Court and, therefore, the Courts cannot add words to a  

statute or read words into it which are not there. The Courts are to  

decide what the law is and not what it should be.  

64.  It is also the case of the applicant that the decriminalization of  

Section 377 IPC will open a floodgate of social issues which the  

legislative domain is not capable of accommodating as same sex  

marriages would become social experiments with unpredictable  

outcome.  

65. Further, it is the contention of the applicant that  

decriminalization of Section 377 IPC will have cascading effect on  

existing laws such as Section 32(d) of the Parsi Marriage and  

Divorce Act, 1936; Section 27(7)(1A) A of the Special Marriage Act,  

1954 which permits a wife to present a petition for divorce to the  

district court on the ground,—(i) that her husband has, since the  

solemnization of the marriage, been guilty of rape, sodomy or  

bestiality; Section 10(2) of the Indian Divorce Act, 1869 and Section  

13(2) of the Hindu Marriage Act, 1955.  

45

45  

E.  Decisions in Naz Foundation and Suresh Koushal    66. We shall now advert to what had been stated by the Delhi High  

Court in Naz Foundation and thereafter advert to the legal base of  

the decision in Suresh Koushal’s case.  The Delhi High Court had  

taken the view that Article 15 of the Constitution prohibits  

discrimination on several enumerated grounds including sex. The  

High Court preferred an expansive interpretation of 'sex' so as to  

include prohibition of discrimination on the ground of 'sexual  

orientation' and that sex-discrimination cannot be read as applying to  

gender simpliciter. Discrimination, as per the High Court's view, on  

the basis of sexual orientation is grounded in stereotypical judgments  

and generalization about the conduct of either sex.  

67. Another facet of the Indian Constitution that the High Court  

delineated was that of inclusiveness as the Indian Constitution  

reflects this value of inclusiveness deeply ingrained in the Indian  

society and nurtured over several generations. The High Court  

categorically said that those who are perceived by the majority as  

deviants or different are not to be, on that score, excluded or  

ostracised. In the High Court's view, where a society displays

46

46  

inclusiveness and understanding, the LGBT persons can be assured  

of a life of dignity and non-discrimination.  

68. It has been further opined by the High Court that the  

Constitution does not permit any statutory criminal law to be held  

captive of the popular misconceptions of who the LGBTs are, as it  

cannot be forgotten that discrimination is the antithesis of equality  

and recognition of equality in its truest sense will foster the dignity of  

every individual. That apart, the High Court had taken the view that  

social morality has to succumb to the concept of constitutional  

morality.  

69. On the basis of the aforesaid reasons, the High Court declared  

Section 377 IPC violative of Articles 14, 15 and 21 of the Constitution  

in so far as it criminalises consensual sexual acts of adults in private,  

whereas for non-consensual penile non-vaginal sex and penile non-

vaginal sex involving minors, the High Court ruled that Section 377  

IPC was valid.  

70. The Delhi High Court judgment was challenged in Suresh  

Koushal (supra) wherein this Court opined that acts which fall within  

the ambit of Section 377 IPC can only be determined with reference  

to the act itself and to the circumstances in which it is executed.

47

47  

While so opining, the Court held that Section 377 IPC would apply  

irrespective of age and consent, for Section 377 IPC does not  

criminalize a particular people or identity or orientation and only  

identifies certain acts which, when committed, would constitute an  

offence. Such a prohibition, in the Court's view in Suresh Koushal  

(supra), regulates sexual conduct regardless of gender identity and  

orientation.  

71. The Court further observed that those who indulge in carnal  

intercourse in the ordinary course and those who indulge in carnal  

intercourse against the order of nature constitute different classes  

and the people falling in the latter category cannot claim that Section  

377 IPC suffers from the vice of arbitrariness and irrational  

classification. The Court further observed that while reading down  

Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code, it cannot be overlooked that  

only a minuscule fraction of the country's population constitutes  

lesbians, gays, bisexuals or transgenders and in last more than 150  

years, less than 200 persons have been prosecuted under Section  

377 of the Indian Penal Code which cannot, therefore, be made a  

sound basis for declaring Section 377 IPC ultra vires the provisions of  

Articles 14, 15 and 21 of the Constitution.

48

48  

72. The submission advanced by the respondents therein to the  

effect that the provision had become a pernicious tool for perpetrating  

harassment, blackmail and torture on those belonging to the LGBT  

community was repelled by stating that such treatment is neither  

mandated by the Section nor condoned by it and the mere fact that  

the Section is misused by police authorities and others is not a  

reflection of the vires of the Section, though it might be a relevant  

factor for the Legislature to consider while judging the desirability of  

amending Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code.  

F.  Other judicial pronouncements on Section 377 IPC  

73. Presently, we may refer to some of the judgments and the  

views taken therein by this Court as well as by the High Courts on  

Section 377 IPC so as to have a holistic perspective.    

74. While interpreting the said provision, the Courts have held that  

the provision stipulates certain acts, which when committed, would  

constitute a criminal offence. In Childline India Foundation and  

another v. Allan John Waters and others26, the Court was dealing  

with carnal intercourse against the order of nature when the material  

on record showed that the accused Nos. 2 and 3 used to have sex  

                                                           26 (2011) 6 SCC 261

49

49  

and fellatio with PWs 1 and 4. The Court opined that the ingredients  

of Section 377 IPC were proved and, accordingly, restored the  

conviction and sentence of 6 years‘ rigorous imprisonment and  

confirmed the imposition of fine. In Fazal Rab Choudhary (supra),  

although the Court convicted the accused under Section 377 IPC, yet  

it took note of the absence of any force in the commission of the act.  

The Court also took into account the prevalent notions of permissive  

society and the fact that homosexuality has been legalized in some  

countries. In view of the same, the Court reduced the sentence of 3  

years imposed on the accused to 6 months opining that the aforesaid  

aspects must also be kept in view as they have a bearing on the  

question of offence and quantum of sentence.  

75. A reference may be made to Khanu v. Emperor27 which was  

also alluded to in Suresh Koushal‘s case. We deem it appropriate to  

reproduce a part of Khanu‘s decision to understand how the courts in  

India had understood the word ―carnal intercourse against the order  

of nature‖. The said passage reads thus:-   

―The principal point in this case is: whether the  accused (who is clearly guilty of having committed the  sin of Gomorrah coitus per os) with a certain little child,  the innocent accomplice of his abomination, has  

                                                           27 AIR 1925 Sind 286

50

50  

thereby committed an offence under Section 377 of the  Penal Code.  

 

Section 377 punishes certain persons who have  carnal intercourse against the order of nature with inter  alia human beings. Is the act here committed one of  carnal intercourse? If so, it is clearly against the order  of nature, because the natural object of carnal  intercourse is that there should be the possibility of  conception of human beings which in the case of  coitus per os is impossible. Intercourse may be defined  as mutual frequent action by members of independent  organisation. Commercial intercourse [is thereafter  referred to; emphasis is made on the reciprocity].  

 

By a metaphor the word intercourse like the word  commerce is applied to the relations of the sexes. Here  also there is the temporary visitation of one organism  by a member of other organisation, for certain clearly  defined and limited objects. The primary object of the  visiting organisation is to obtain euphoria by means of  a detent of the nerves consequent on the sexual crisis.  But there is no intercourse unless the visiting member  is enveloped at least partially by the visited organism,  for intercourse connotes reciprocity. Looking at the  question in this way it would seem that sin of  Gomorrah is no less carnal intercourse than the sin of  sodomy. …  

 

It is to be remembered that the Penal Code does  not, except in Section 377, render abnormal sexual  vice punishable at all. In England indecent assaults are  punishable very severely. It is possible that under the  Penal Code, some cases might be met by prosecuting  the offender for simple assault, but that is a  compoundable offence and in any case the patient  could in no way be punished. It is to be supposed that  the legislature intended that a Tigellinus should carry

51

51  

on his nefarious profession perhaps vitiating and  depraving hundreds of children with perfect immunity?  

 

I doubt not, therefore, that coitus per os is  punishable under Section 377 of the Penal Code.‖  

 

76. In Suresh Koushal‘s case, there has also been a reference to  

the decision of the Gujarat High Court in Lohana Vasantlal  

Devchand v. State28 wherein the issue presented before the High  

Court was whether an offence under Section 377 read with Section  

511 IPC had been committed on account of the convict putting his  

male organ in the mouth of the victim, if the act was done voluntarily  

by him.  A contention was raised that there was no penetration and,  

therefore, there could not have been any carnal intercourse.  The  

High Court referred to a passage from the book ‗Pyschology of Sex‘  

29 authored by Mr. Havelock Ellis which reads thus:-  

"While the kiss may be regarded as the typical and  normal erogenic method of contrectation for the end of  attaining tumescene, there are others only less  important. Any orifical contact 'between persons of  opposite sex' is sometimes almost equally as effective  as the kiss in stimulating tumescene; all such contacts,  indeed, belong to the group of which the kiss is the  type, Cunnilinctus (often incorrectly termed  cunnilingus) and fellatio cannot be regarded as  unnatural for they have their prototypic forms among  animals, and they are found among various savage  

                                                           28 AIR 1968 Guj 252  29 ‘Psychology of Sex’ Twelfth Impression, 1948, London

52

52  

races. As forms of contrecttion and aides to tumescene  they are thus natural and are sometimes regarded by  both sexes as quintessential forms of sexual pleasure,  though they may not be considered aesthetic. They  become deviations, however, and this liable to be  termed "perversions", when they replace the desire of  coitus"‖  

 

77. After referring to the definition of sodomy, the pronouncement  

in Khanu (supra), Stroud‘s Judicial Dictionary, 3rd Edition and  

Webster‘s New 20th Century Dictionary, unabridged, 2nd Edition, the  

Gujarat High Court opined thus:-  

―In the instant case, there was an entry of a male penis  in the orifice of the mouth of the victim. There was the  enveloping of a visiting member by the visited  organism. There was thus reciprocity; intercourse  connotes reciprocity. It could, therefore, be said  without any doubt in my mind that the act in question  will amount to an offence, punishable under Section  337 of the Indian Penal Code.‖  

 

78. The decision in State of Kerala v. Kundumkara Govindan  

and another30 has also been reproduced in Suresh Koushal‘s case.   

The High Court of Kerala held thus:-   

―18. Even if I am to hold that there was no penetration  into the vagina and the sexual acts were committed  only between the thighs, I do not think that the  respondents can escape conviction under Section 377  of the Penal Code. The counsel of the respondents  contends (in this argument the Public Prosecutor also  

                                                           301969 Cri LJ 818 (Ker)

53

53  

supports him) that sexual act between the thighs is not  intercourse. The argument is that for intercourse there  must be encirclement of the male organ by the organ  visited; and that in the case of sexual act between the  thighs, there is no possibility of penetration.  

19. The word ‗intercourse‘ means ‗sexual connection‘  (Concise Oxford Dictionary). In Khanu v. Emperor the  meaning of the word ‗intercourse‘ has been  considered: (AIR p. 286)  

 

‗Intercourse may be defined as mutual frequent action  by members of independent organisation.‘  

Then commercial intercourse, social intercourse, etc.  have been considered; and then appears:  

 

‗By a metaphor the word intercourse, like the word  commerce, is applied to the relations of the sexes.  Here also there is the temporary visitation of one  organism by a member of the other organisation, for  certain clearly defined and limited objects. The primary  object of the visiting organisation is to obtain euphoria  by means of a detent of the nerves consequent on the  sexual crisis. But there is no intercourse unless the  visiting member is enveloped at least partially by the  visited organism, for intercourse connotes reciprocity.‘  

Therefore, to decide whether there is intercourse or  not, what is to be considered is whether the visiting  organ is enveloped at least partially by the visited  organism. In intercourse between the thighs, the  visiting male organ is enveloped at least partially by  the organism visited, the thighs: the thighs are kept  together and tight.  

 

20. Then about penetration. The word ‗penetrate‘  means in the Concise Oxford Dictionary ‗find access  into or through, pass through.‘ When the male organ is  inserted between the thighs kept together and tight, is  there no penetration? The word ‗insert‘ means place,

54

54  

fit, thrust.‘ Therefore, if the male organ is ‗inserted‘ or  ‗thrust‘ between the thighs, there is ‗penetration‘ to  constitute unnatural offence.  

21. Unnatural offence is defined in Section 377 of the  Penal Code; whoever voluntarily has carnal  intercourse against the order of nature with any man,  woman or animal commits unnatural offence. The act  of committing intercourse between the thighs is carnal  intercourse against the order of nature. Therefore  committing intercourse by inserting the male organ  between the thighs of another is an unnatural offence.  In this connection, it may be noted that the act in  Section 376 is ‗sexual intercourse‘ and the act in  Section 377 is ‗carnal intercourse against the order of  nature‘.   

22. The position in English law on this question has  been brought to my notice. The old decision of R. v.  Samuel Jacobs31 lays down that penetration through  the mouth does not amount to the offence of sodomy  under English law. The counsel therefore argues that  sexual intercourse between the thighs cannot also be  an offence under Section 377 of the Penal Code. In  Sirkar v. Gula Mythien Pillai Chaithu Maho Mathu32 a  Full Bench of the Travancore High Court held that  having connection with a person in the mouth was an  offence under Section 377 of the Penal Code. In a  short judgment, the learned Judges held that it was  unnecessary to refer to English Statute Law and  English text books which proceeded upon an  interpretation of the words sodomy, buggery and  bestiality; and that the words used in the Penal Code  were very simple and wide enough to include all acts  against the order of nature. My view on the question is  also that the words of Section 377 are simple and wide  enough to include any carnal intercourse against the  order of nature within its ambit. Committing intercourse  

                                                           31 1817 Russ & Ry 331 : 168 ER 830 (CCR)  32 (1908) 14 TLR Appendix 43 (Ker)

55

55  

between the thighs of another is carnal intercourse  against the order of nature.‖  

 

79.   In Calvin Francis v. State of Orissa33, the Orissa High Court  

had reproduced certain passages from Corpus Juris Secundum, Vol.  

81, pp. 368-70. We may reproduce the same:-   

―A statute providing that any person who shall commit  any act or practice of sexual perversity, either with  mankind or beast, on conviction shall be punished, is  not limited to instances involving carnal copulation, but  is restricted to cases involving the sex organ of at least  one of the parties. The term ‗sexual perversity‘ does  not refer to every physical contact by a male with the  body of the female with intent to cause sexual  satisfaction to the actor, but the condemnation of the  statute is limited to unnatural conduct performed for  the purpose of accomplishing abnormal sexual  satisfaction for the actor. Under a statute providing that  any person participating in the act or copulating the  mouth of one person with the sexual organ of another  is guilty of the offence a person is guilty of violating the  statute when he has placed his mouth on the genital  organ of another, and the offence may be committed  by two persons of opposite sex.‖  

 80. Referring to the said decision, the two-Judge Bench in Suresh  

Koushal‘s case has opined:-   

―60. However, from these cases no uniform test can be  culled out to classify acts as ―carnal intercourse  against the order of nature‖. In our opinion the acts  which fall within the ambit of Section 377 IPC can only  be determined with reference to the act itself and the  circumstances in which it is executed. All the  

                                                           33 1992 (1) OLR 316

56

56  

aforementioned cases refer to non-consensual and  markedly coercive situations and the keenness of the  Court in bringing justice to the victims who were either  women or children cannot be discounted while  analysing the manner in which the section has been  interpreted. We are apprehensive of whether the court  would rule similarly in a case of proved consensual  intercourse between adults.  …‖   

 81. From the aforesaid analysis, it is perceptible that the two-Judge  

Bench has drawn a distinction between the ―class‖ and the ―act‖ that  

has been treated as an offence.  On a plain reading of the provision,  

it is noticeable that the ―act‖ covers all categories of persons if the  

offence is committed. Thus, the seminal issue that emerges for  

consideration, as has been understood by various High Courts and  

this Court, is whether the act can be treated as a criminal offence if it  

violates Articles 19(1)(a) and 21 of the Constitution.  Therefore, the  

provision has to be tested on the anvil of the said constitutional  

provisions. Additionally, it is also to be tested on the touchstone of  

Article 14 especially under the scanner of its second limb, that is,  

manifest arbitrariness.  For adjudging the aforesaid facets, certain  

fundamental concepts which are intrinsically and integrally associated  

with the expression of a person who enjoys certain inalienable natural  

rights which also have been recognized under the Constitution are  

required to be addressed. In this context, the individuality of a person

57

57  

and the acceptance of identity invite advertence to some necessary  

concepts which eventually recognize the constitutional status of an  

individual that resultantly brushes aside the ―act‖ and respects the  

dignity and choice of the individual.  

G.  The Constitution – an organic charter of progressive rights  

82. A democratic Constitution like ours is an organic and breathing  

document with senses which are very much alive to its surroundings,  

for it has been created in such a manner that it can adapt to the  

needs and developments taking place in the society. It was  

highlighted by this Court in the case of Chief Justice of Andhra  

Pradesh and others v. L.V.A. Dixitulu and others 34  that the  

Constitution is a living, integrated organism having a soul and  

consciousness of its own and its pulse beats, emanating from the  

spinal cord of its basic framework, can be felt all over its body, even  

in the extremities of its limbs.  

83. In the case of Saurabh Chaudri and others v. Union of India  

and others35, it was observed:-  

"Our Constitution is organic in nature, being a living  organ, it is ongoing and with the passage of time, law  

                                                           34 (1979) 2 SCC 34  35 (2003) 11 SCC 146

58

58  

must change. Horizons of constitutional law are  expanding."    

84. Thus, we are required to keep in view the dynamic concepts  

inherent in the Constitution that have the potential to enable and urge  

the constitutional courts to beam with expansionism that really grows  

to adapt to the ever-changing circumstances without losing the  

identity of the Constitution.   The idea of identity of the individual  

and the constitutional legitimacy behind the same is of immense  

significance. Therefore, in this context, the duty of the constitutional  

courts gets accentuated. We emphasize on the role of the  

constitutional courts in realizing the evolving nature of this living  

instrument. Through its dynamic and purposive interpretative  

approach, the judiciary must strive to breathe life into the Constitution  

and not render the document a collection of mere dead letters. The  

following observations made in the case of Ashok Kumar Gupta and  

another v. State of U.P. and others36 further throws light on this role  

of the courts:-  

"Therefore, it is but the duty of the Court to supply  vitality, blood and flesh, to balance the competing  rights by interpreting the principles, to the language or  the words contained in the living and organic  Constitution, broadly and liberally."  

                                                           36 (1997) 5 SCC 201

59

59  

 85. The rights that are guaranteed as Fundamental Rights under  

our Constitution are the dynamic and timeless rights of 'liberty' and  

'equality' and it would be against the principles of our Constitution to  

give them a static interpretation without recognizing their  

transformative and evolving nature. The argument does not lie in the  

fact that the concepts underlying these rights change with the  

changing times but the changing times illustrate and illuminate the  

concepts underlying the said rights. In this regard, the observations in  

Video Electronics Pvt. Ltd. and another v. State of Punjab and  

another37 are quite instructive:-  

"Constitution is a living organism and the latent  meaning of the expressions used can be given effect  to only if a particular situation arises. It is not that with  changing times the meaning changes but changing  times illustrate and illuminate the meaning of the  expressions used. The connotation of the expressions  used takes its shape and colour in evolving dynamic  situations."    

86. Our Constitution fosters and strengthens the spirit of equality  

and envisions a society where every person enjoys equal rights which  

enable him/her to grow and realize his/her potential as an individual.  

This guarantee of recognition of individuality runs through the entire  

                                                           37 (1990) 3 SCC 87

60

60  

length and breadth of this dynamic instrument. The Constitution has  

been conceived of and designed in a manner which acknowledges  

the fact that 'change is inevitable'. It is the duty of the courts to realize  

the constitutional vision of equal rights in consonance with the current  

demands and situations and not to read and interpret the same as  

per the standards of equality that existed decades ago. The judiciary  

cannot remain oblivious to the fact that the society is constantly  

evolving and many a variation may emerge with the changing times.   

There is a constant need to transform the constitutional idealism into  

reality by fostering respect for human rights, promoting inclusion of  

pluralism, bringing harmony, that is, unity amongst diversity,  

abandoning the idea of alienation or some unacceptable social  

notions built on medieval egos and establishing the cult of egalitarian  

liberalism founded on reasonable principles that can withstand  

scrutiny.  

87. In Ashok Kumar Gupta (supra), the Court had observed that  

common sense has always served in the court's ceaseless striving as  

a voice of reason to maintain the blend of change and continuity of  

order which are sine qua non for stability in the process of change in  

a parliamentary democracy. The Court ruled that it is not bound to

61

61  

accept an interpretation which retards the progress or impedes social  

integration. The Court further observed that it is required to adopt  

such interpretation which would give the ideals set out in the  

Preamble to the Constitution aided by Part III and Part IV a  

meaningful and living reality for all sections of the society.  

88. It is through this armoury of expansive dynamism that the  

courts have been able to give an all-inclusive interpretation to the  

fundamental rights enshrined in Part III of our Constitution. This is  

borne testimony by the decisions of the constitutional courts which  

have evolved views for extending the protection of fundamental rights  

to those who have been deprived of the enjoyment of the same. If not  

for such an approach adopted by the courts, our Constitution and its  

progressive principles would have been rendered ineffective and the  

dynamic charter would be reduced to a mere ornate document  

without any purpose or object.   

89. The Court, as the final arbiter of the Constitution, has to keep in  

view the necessities of the needy and the weaker sections. The role  

of the Court assumes further importance when the class or  

community whose rights are in question are those who have been the  

object of humiliation, discrimination, separation and violence by not

62

62  

only the State and the society at large but also at the hands of their  

very own family members. The development of law cannot be a mute  

spectator to the struggle for the realisation and attainment of the  

rights of such members of the society.   

90. The authority in NALSA is one such recent illustration where  

the rights of transgenders as a third sex was recognized which had  

been long due in a democracy like ours. This Court ruled: -  

"It is now very well recognized that the Constitution is a  living character; its interpretation must be dynamic. It  must be understood in a way that intricate and  advances modern realty. The judiciary is the guardian  of the Constitution and by ensuring to grant legitimate  right that is due to TGs, we are simply protecting the  Constitution and the democracy inasmuch as judicial  protection and democracy in general and of human  rights in particular is a characteristic of our vibrant  democracy.    As we have pointed out above, our Constitution  inheres liberal and substantive democracy with rule of  law as an important and fundamental pillar. It has its  own internal morality based on dignity and equality of  all human beings. Rule of law demands protection of  individual human rights. Such rights are to be  guaranteed to each and every human being. These  TGs, even though insignificant in numbers, are still  human beings and therefore they have every right to  enjoy their human rights."    The ‗living document‘ concept finds place in several  

international authorities as well. The courts in other jurisdictions have

63

63  

endorsed the view that the Constitution is forever evolving in nature  

and that a progressive approach is mandated by the principles  

inherent in the Constitution itself.   

91. The Supreme Court of Canada, while giving an expansive  

interpretation to marriage by including same-sex unions within its  

encompass, in Re: Same Sex Marriage38, has observed:-  

"The "frozen concepts" reasoning runs contrary to one  of the most fundamental principles of Canadian  constitutional interpretation: that our Constitution is a  living tree which, by way of progressive interpretation,  accommodates and addresses the realities of modern  life."    

92. As early as the 1920s, the Supreme Court of the United States  

in the case of State of Missouri v. Holland 39 , while making a  

comparison between the ‗instrument in dispute' and the 'Constitution',  

had made the following observations with regard to the nature of the  

Constitution:-  

"When we are dealing with words that also are a  constituent act, like the Constitution of the United  States, we must realize that they have called into life a  being the development of which could not have been  foreseen completely by the most gifted of its begetters.  It was enough for them to realize or to hope that they  had created an organism; it has taken a century and  

                                                           38[2004] 3 S.C.R. 698  39 252 U.S. 416 (1920)

64

64  

has cost their successors much sweat and blood to  prove that they created a nation."    

93. In one of his celebrated works, Judge Richard Posner made  

certain observations which would be relevant to be reproduced here:-  

"A constitution that did not invalidate so offensive,  oppressive, probably undemocratic, and sectarian law  [as the Connecticut law banning contraceptives] would  stand revealed as containing major gaps. Maybe that  is the nature of our, or perhaps any, written  Constitution; but yet, perhaps the courts are authorized  to plug at least the most glaring gaps. Does anyone  really believe, in his heart of hearts, that the  Constitution should be interpreted so literally as to  authorize every conceivable law that would not violate  a specific constitutional clause? This would mean that  a state could require everyone to marry, or to have  intercourse at least once a month, or it could take  away every couple's second child and place it in a  foster home.... We find it reassuring to think that the  courts stand between us and legislative tyranny even if  a particular form of tyranny was not foreseen and  expressly forbidden by framers of the Constitution."40    

94. Thus, it is demonstrable that expansive growth of constitutional  

idealism is embedded in the theory of progress, abandonment of  

status quoist attitude, expansion of the concept of inclusiveness and  

constant remembrance of the principle of fitting into the norm of  

change with a constitutional philosophy.  

                                                           40

Posner, Richard: (1992) Sex and Reason,  Harvard University Press, pg. 328. ISBN 0-674-        80280-2

65

65  

H.  Transformative constitutionalism and the rights of LGBT  community  

 95. For understanding the need of having a constitutional  

democracy and for solving the million dollar question as to why we  

adopted the Constitution, we perhaps need to understand the  

concept of transformative constitutionalism with some degree of  

definiteness. In this quest of ours, the ideals enshrined in the  

Preamble to our Constitution would be a guiding laser beam. The  

ultimate goal of our magnificent Constitution is to make right the  

upheaval which existed in the Indian society before the adopting of  

the Constitution.  The Court in State of Kerala and another v. N.M.  

Thomas and others41  observed that the Indian Constitution is a  

great social document, almost revolutionary in its aim of transforming  

a medieval, hierarchical society into a modern, egalitarian democracy  

and its provisions can be comprehended only by a spacious, social-

science approach, not by pedantic, traditional legalism.  The whole  

idea of having a Constitution is to guide the nation towards a  

resplendent future. Therefore, the purpose of having a Constitution is  

to transform the society for the better and this objective is the  

fundamental pillar of transformative constitutionalism.    

                                                           41 AIR 1976 SC 490

66

66  

96. The concept of transformative constitutionalism has at its kernel  

a pledge, promise and thirst to transform the Indian society so as to  

embrace therein, in letter and spirit, the ideals of justice, liberty,  

equality and fraternity as set out in the Preamble to our Constitution.   

The expression ‗transformative constitutionalism‘ can be best  

understood by embracing a pragmatic lens which will help in  

recognizing the realities of the current day. Transformation as a  

singular term is diametrically opposed to something which is static  

and stagnant, rather it signifies change, alteration and the ability to  

metamorphose. Thus, the concept of transformative constitutionalism,  

which is an actuality with regard to all Constitutions and particularly  

so with regard to the Indian Constitution, is, as a matter of fact, the  

ability of the Constitution to adapt and transform with the changing  

needs of the times.  

97. It is this ability of a Constitution to transform which gives it the  

character of a living and organic document. A Constitution  

continuously shapes the lives of citizens in particular and societies in  

general. Its exposition and energetic appreciation by constitutional  

courts constitute the lifeblood of progressive societies. The  

Constitution would become a stale and dead testament without

67

67  

dynamic, vibrant and pragmatic interpretation. Constitutional  

provisions have to be construed and developed in such a manner that  

their real intent and existence percolates to all segments of the  

society. That is the raison d'etre for the Constitution.  

98. The Supreme Court as well as other constitutional courts have  

time and again realized that in a society undergoing fast social and  

economic change, static judicial interpretation of the Constitution  

would stultify the spirit of the Constitution. Accordingly, the  

constitutional courts, while viewing the Constitution as a  

transformative document, have ardently fulfilled their obligation to act  

as the sentinel on qui vive for guarding the rights of all individuals  

irrespective of their sex, choice and sexual orientation.  

99. The purpose of transformative constitutionalism has been aptly  

described in the case of Road Accident Fund and another v.  

Mdeyide42 wherein the Constitutional Court of South Africa, speaking  

in the context of the transformative role of the Constitution of South  

Africa, had observed:-  

―Our Constitution has often been described as  ―transformative‖. One of the most important purposes  of this transformation is to ensure that, by the  realisation of fundamental socio-economic rights,  

                                                           422008 (1) SA 535 (CC)

68

68  

people disadvantaged by their deprived social and  economic circumstances become more capable of  enjoying a life of dignity, freedom and equality that lies  at the heart of our constitutional democracy.‖    

100. In Bato Star Fishing (Pty) Ltd v. Minister of Environmental  

Affairs and Tourism and others43, the Constitutional Court of South  

Africa opined:-  

―The achievement of equality is one of the fundamental  goals that we have fashioned for ourselves in the  Constitution. Our constitutional order is committed to  the transformation of our society from a grossly  unequal society to one "in which there is equality  between men and women and people of all races". In  this fundamental way, our Constitution differs from  other constitutions which assume that all are equal and  in so doing simply entrench existing inequalities. Our  Constitution recognises that decades of systematic  racial discrimination entrenched by the apartheid legal  order cannot be eliminated without positive action  being taken to achieve that result. We are required to  do more than that. The effects of discrimination may  continue indefinitely unless there is a commitment to  end it."    

101.     Davies44 understands transformation as follows:-  

"Transformation which is based on the continuing  evaluation and modification of a complex material and  ideological environment cannot be reduced to a  scientific theory of change, like those of evolution or  the halflife of radioactive substances ... practical  change occurs within a climate of serious reflection,  

                                                           43 [2004] ZACC 15  44 Asking the Law Question: The Dissolution of Legal Theory 205 (2002), Margaret Davies.

69

69  

and diversity of opinion is in my view absolutely  essential as a stimulus to theory."  

 102. A J Van der Walt 45  has metaphorically, by comparing  

'constitutional transformation' to 'dancing', described the art of  

constitutional transformation to be continually progressive where one  

does not stop from daring to imagine alternatives and that the society  

could be different and a better place where the rights of every  

individual are given due recognition:-  

"However, even when we trade the static imagery of  position, standing, for the more complex imagery of  dancing, we still have to resist the temptation to see  transformation as linear movement or progress - from  authoritarianism to justification, from one dancing code  to another, or from volkspele jurisprudence to toyitoyi  jurisprudence... I suggest that we should not only  switch to a more complex metaphorical code such as  dancing when discussing transformation, but that we  should also deconstruct the codes we dance to; pause  to reflect upon the language in terms of which we think  and talk and reason about constitutionalism, about  rights, and about transformation, and recognize the  liberating and the captivating potential of the codes  shaping and shaped by that language.     

103. Again, the Supreme Court of South Africa in President of the  

Republic of South Africa v. Hugo46 observed that the prohibition on  

unfair discrimination in the interim Constitution seeks not only to  

                                                           45 Van der Walt, Dancing with codes - Protecting, developing and deconstructing property rights in      a constitutional state, 118 (2)  J. S. APR. L. 258 (2001)  46

(1997) 6 B.C.L.R. 708 (CC)

70

70  

avoid discrimination against people who are members of  

disadvantaged groups but also that at the heart of the prohibition of  

unfair discrimination lies a recognition that the purpose of our new  

constitutional and democratic order is the establishment of a society  

in which all human beings will be accorded equal dignity and respect,  

regardless of their membership of particular groups.  

104. Equality does not only imply recognition of individual dignity but  

also includes within its sphere ensuring of equal opportunity to  

advance and develop their human potential and social, economic and  

legal interests of every individual and the process of transformative  

constitutionalism is dedicated to this purpose. It has been observed  

by Albertyn & Goldblatt47:-  

"The challenge of achieving equality within this  transformation project involves the eradication of  systemic forms of discrimination and material  disadvantage based on race, gender, class and other  forms of inequality. It also entails the development of  opportunities which allow people to realise their full  human potential within positive social relationships."  

 105. In Investigating Directorate: Serious Economic Offences  

and others v. Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and others: In  

                                                           47

Albertyn & Goldblatt, Facing the challenge of transformation: Difficulties in the development of     an indigenous jurisprudence of equality, 14 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 248 (1998)

71

71  

Re Hyundai Motor Distributors (Pty) Ltd and others v. Smit NO  

and others48, the Constitutional Court of South Africa observed:-  

"The Constitution is located in a history which involves  a transition from a society based on division, injustice  and exclusion from the democratic process to one  which respects the dignity of all citizens and includes  all in the process of governance. As such, the process  of interpreting the Constitution must recognise the  context in which we find ourselves and the  Constitution's goal of a society based on democratic  values, social justice and fundamental human rights.  This spirit of transition and transformation  characterises the constitutional enterprise as a whole.  

 ... The Constitution requires that judicial officers  read legislation, where possible, in ways which give  effect to its fundamental values. Consistently with  this, when the constitutionality of legislation is in  issue, they are under a duty to examine the objects  and purport of an Act and to read the provisions of  the legislation, so far as is possible, in conformity  with the Constitution."    

106. The society has changed much now, not just from the year  

1860 when the Indian Penal Code was brought into force but there  

has also been continuous progressive change.  In many spheres, the  

sexual minorities have been accepted.  They have been given space  

after the NALSA judgment but the offence punishable under Section  

377 IPC, as submitted, creates a chilling effect. The freedom that is  

required to be attached to sexuality still remains in the pavilion with  

                                                           482001 (1) SA 545 (CC)

72

72  

no nerves to move.  The immobility due to fear corrodes the desire to  

express one‘s own sexual orientation as a consequence of which the  

body with flesh and bones feels itself caged and a sense of fear  

gradually converts itself into a skeleton sans spirit.   

107. The question of freedom of choosing a partner is reflective from  

a catena of recent judgments of this Court such as Shafin Jahan  

(supra) wherein the Court held that a person who has come of age  

and has the capability to think on his/her own has a right to choose  

his/her life partner. It is apposite to reproduce some of the  

observations made by the Court which are to the following effect:-  

―It is obligatory to state here that expression of choice  in accord with law is acceptance of individual identity.  Curtailment of that expression and the ultimate action  emanating therefrom on the conceptual structuralism  of obeisance to the societal will destroy the  individualistic entity of a person. The social values and  morals have their space but they are not above the  constitutionally guaranteed freedom. The said freedom  is both a constitutional and a human right. Deprivation  of that freedom which is ingrained in choice on the plea  of faith is impermissible.‖  

108. Recently, in Shakti Vahini (supra), the Court has ruled that the  

right to choose a life partner is a facet of individual liberty and the  

Court, for the protection of this right, issued preventive, remedial and

73

73  

punitive measures to curb the menace of honour killings. The Court  

observed:-  

―When the ability to choose is crushed in the name of  class honour and the person‘s physical frame is  treated with absolute indignity, a chilling effect  dominates over the brains and bones of the society at  large.‖  

 

109. An argument is sometimes advanced that what is permissible  

between two adults engaged in acceptable sexual activity is different  

in the case of two individuals of the same sex, be it homosexuals or  

lesbians, and the ground of difference is  supported by social  

standardization. Such an argument ignores the individual orientation,  

which is naturally natural, and disrobes the individual of his/her  

identity and the inherent dignity and choice attached to his/her being.   

110. The principle of transformative constitutionalism also places  

upon the judicial arm of the State a duty to ensure and  uphold the  

supremacy of the Constitution, while at the same time ensuring that a  

sense of transformation is ushered constantly and endlessly in the  

society by interpreting and enforcing the Constitution as well as other  

provisions of law in consonance with the avowed object. The idea is  

to steer the country and its institutions in a democratic egalitarian  

direction where there is increased protection of fundamental rights

74

74  

and other freedoms. It is in this way that transformative  

constitutionalism attains the status of an ideal model imbibing the  

philosophy and morals of constitutionalism and fostering greater  

respect for human rights.  It ought to be remembered that the  

Constitution is not a mere parchment; it derives its strength from the  

ideals and values enshrined in it.  However, it is only when we adhere  

to constitutionalism as the supreme creed and faith and develop a  

constitutional culture to protect the fundamental rights of an individual  

that we can preserve and strengthen the values of our  

compassionate Constitution.   

I. Constitutional morality and Section 377 IPC  

111. The concept of constitutional morality is not limited to the mere  

observance of the core principles of constitutionalism as the  

magnitude and sweep of constitutional morality is not confined to the  

provisions and literal text which a Constitution contains, rather it  

embraces within itself virtues of a wide magnitude such as that of  

ushering a pluralistic and inclusive society, while at the same time  

adhering to the other principles of constitutionalism. It is further the  

result of embodying constitutional morality that the values of  

constitutionalism trickle down and percolate through the apparatus of

75

75  

the State for the betterment of each and every individual citizen of the  

State.  

112. In one of the Constituent Assembly Debates, Dr. Ambedkar,  

explaining the concept of constitutional morality by quoting the Greek  

historian, George Grote, said:-  

"By constitutional morality, Grote meant... a paramount  reverence for the forms of the constitution, enforcing  obedience to authority and acting under and within  these forms, yet combined with the habit of open  speech, of action subject only to definite legal control,  and unrestrained censure of those very authorities as  to all their public acts combined, too with a perfect  confidence in the bosom of every citizen amidst the  bitterness of party contest that the forms of constitution  wall not be less sacred in the eyes of his opponents  than his own."49    

113. Our Constitution was visualized with the aim of securing to the  

citizens of our country inalienable rights which were essential for  

fostering a spirit of growth and development and at the same time  

ensuring that the three organs of the State working under the aegis of  

the Constitution and deriving their authority from the supreme  

document, that is, the Constitution, practise constitutional morality.  

The Executive, the Legislature and the Judiciary all have to stay alive  

to the concept of constitutional morality.  

                                                           49 Constituent Assembly Debates, Vol. 7 (4th November 1948)

76

76  

114. In the same speech50, Dr. Ambedkar had quoted George Grote  

who had observed:-  

"The diffusion of 'constitutional morality', not merely  among the majority of any community, but throughout  the whole is the indispensable condition of a  government at once free and peaceable; since even  any powerful and obstinate minority may render the  working of a free institution impracticable, without  being strong enough to conquer ascendance for  themselves."51    This statement of Dr. Ambedkar underscores that constitutional  

morality is not a natural forte for our country for the simple reason  

that our country had attained freedom after a long period of colonial  

rule and, therefore, constitutional morality at the time when the  

Constituent Assembly was set up was an alien notion. However, the  

strengthening of constitutional morality in contemporary India remains  

a duty of the organs of the State including the Judiciary.  

115. The society as a whole or even a minuscule part of the society  

may aspire and prefer different things for themselves. They are  

perfectly competent to have such a freedom to be different, like  

different things, so on and so forth, provided that their different tastes  

and liking remain within their legal framework and neither violates any  

statute nor results in the abridgement of fundamental rights of any  

                                                           50 Ibid  51 Grote, A History of Greece. Routledge, London, 2000, p. 93.

77

77  

other citizen. The Preambular goals of our Constitution which contain  

the noble objectives of Justice, Liberty, Equality and Fraternity can  

only be achieved through the commitment and loyalty of the organs of  

the State to the principle of constitutional morality.  

116. It is the concept of constitutional morality which strives and  

urges the organs of the State to maintain such a heterogeneous fibre  

in the society, not just in the limited sense, but also in multifarious  

ways. It is the responsibility of all the three organs of the State to curb  

any propensity or proclivity of popular sentiment or majoritarianism.  

Any attempt to push and shove a homogeneous, uniform, consistent  

and a standardised philosophy throughout the society would violate  

the principle of constitutional morality. Devotion and fidelity to  

constitutional morality must not be equated with the popular  

sentiment prevalent at a particular point of time.  

117. Any asymmetrical attitude in the society, so long as it is within  

the legal and constitutional framework, must at least be provided an  

environment in which it could be sustained, if not fostered. It is only  

when such an approach is adopted that the freedom of expression  

including that of choice would be allowed to prosper and flourish and

78

78  

if that is achieved, freedom and liberty, which is the quintessence of  

constitutional morality, will be allowed to survive.  

118. In Government of NCT of Delhi v. Union of India and  

others52, one of us (Dipak Misra, CJI) observed:-  

"Constitutional morality, appositely understood, means  the morality that has inherent elements in the  constitutional norms and the conscience of the  Constitution. Any act to garner justification must  possess the potentiality to be in harmony with the  constitutional impulse. We may give an example.  When one is expressing an idea of generosity, he may  not be meeting the standard of justness. There may be  an element of condescension. But when one shows  justness in action, there is no feeling of any grant or  generosity. That will come within the normative value.  That is the test of constitutional justness which falls  within the sweep of constitutional morality. It advocates  the principle of constitutional justness without  subjective exposition of generosity."    

119. The duty of the constitutional courts is to adjudge the validity of  

law on well-established principles, namely, legislative competence or  

violations of fundamental rights or of any other constitutional  

provisions. At the same time, it is expected from the courts as the  

final arbiter of the Constitution to uphold the cherished principles of  

the Constitution and not to be remotely guided by majoritarian view or  

                                                           522018 (8) SCALE 72

79

79  

popular perception. The Court has to be guided by the conception of  

constitutional morality and not by the societal morality.  

120. We may hasten to add here that in the context of the issue at  

hand, when a penal provision is challenged as being violative of the  

fundamental rights of a section of the society, notwithstanding the fact  

whether the said section of the society is a minority or a majority, the  

magna cum laude and creditable principle of constitutional morality, in  

a constitutional democracy like ours where the rule of law prevails,  

must not be allowed to be trampled by obscure notions of social  

morality which have no legal tenability.  The concept of constitutional  

morality would serve as an aid for the Court to arrive at a just  

decision which would be in consonance with the constitutional rights  

of the citizens, howsoever small that fragment of the populace may  

be. The idea of number, in this context, is meaningless; like zero on  

the left side of any number.   

121. In this regard, we have to telescopically analyse social morality  

vis-à-vis constitutional morality. It needs no special emphasis to state  

that whenever the constitutional courts come across a situation of  

transgression or dereliction in the sphere of fundamental rights, which  

are also the basic human rights of a section, howsoever small part of

80

80  

the society, then it is for the constitutional courts to ensure, with the  

aid of judicial engagement and creativity, that constitutional morality  

prevails over social morality.  

122. In the garb of social morality, the members of the LGBT  

community must not be outlawed or given a step-motherly treatment  

of malefactor by the society. If this happens or if such a treatment to  

the LGBT community is allowed to persist, then the constitutional  

courts, which are under the obligation to protect the fundamental  

rights, would be failing in the discharge of their duty. A failure to do so  

would reduce the citizenry rights to a cipher.  

123. We must not forget that the founding fathers adopted an  

inclusive Constitution with provisions that not only allowed the State,  

but also, at times, directed the State, to undertake affirmative action  

to eradicate the systematic discrimination against the backward  

sections of the society and the expulsion and censure of the  

vulnerable communities by the so-called upper caste/sections of the  

society that existed on a massive scale prior to coming into existence  

of the Constituent Assembly. These were nothing but facets of the  

majoritarian social morality which were sought to be rectified by  

bringing into force the Constitution of India. Thus, the adoption of the

81

81  

Constitution, was, in a way, an instrument or agency for achieving  

constitutional morality and means to discourage the prevalent social  

morality at that time. A country or a society which embraces  

constitutional morality has at its core the well-founded idea of  

inclusiveness.  

124.  While testing the constitutional validity of impugned provision  

of law, if a constitutional court is of the view that the impugned  

provision falls foul to the precept of constitutional morality, then the  

said provision has to be declared as unconstitutional for the pure and  

simple reason that the constitutional courts exist to uphold the  

Constitution.  

J.  Perspective of human dignity  

125. While discussing about the role of human dignity in gay rights  

adjudication and legislation, Michele Finck53 observes:-  

―As a concept devoid of a precise legal meaning, yet  widely appealing at an intuitive level, dignity- can be  easily manipulated and transposed into a number of  legal contexts. With regard to the rights of lesbian and  gay individuals, dignity captures what Nussbaum  described as the transition from "disgust" to  "humanity." Once looked at with disgust and  considered unworthy of some rights, there is  

                                                           53The role of human dignity in gay rights adjudication and legislation: A comparative perspective,       Michele Finck, International Journal of Constitutional Law, Volume 14, Jan 2016, page no.26 to 53

82

82  

increasing consensus that homosexuals should no  longer be deprived of the benefits of citizenship that  are available to heterosexuals, such as the ability to  contract marriage, on the sole ground of their sexual  orientation. Homosexuals are increasingly considered  as "full humans" disposing of equal rights, and dignity  functions as the vocabulary that translates such socio- cultural change into legal change‖  

 126. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 1948 became the  

Magna Carta of people all over the world. The first Article of the  

UDHR was uncompromising in its generality of application: All  

human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. Justice  

Kirby succinctly observed:-  

―This language embraced every individual in our world.  It did not apply only to citizens. It did not apply only to  'white' people. It did not apply only to good people.  Prisoners, murderers and even traitors were to be  entitled to the freedoms that were declared. There  were no exceptions to the principles of equality.‖54  

 127. The fundamental idea of dignity is regarded as an inseparable  

facet of human personality. Dignity has been duly recognized as an  

important aspect of the right to life under Article 21 of the Constitution.  

In the international sphere, the right to live with dignity had been  

identified as a human right way back in 1948 with the introduction of  

the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. The constitutional courts  

                                                           54Human Rights Gay Rights by Michael Kirby, Published in ‘Humane Rights’ in 2016 by Future Leaders    

83

83  

of our country have solemnly dealt with the task of assuring and  

preserving the right to dignity of each and every individual whenever  

the occasion arises, for without the right to live with dignity, all other  

fundamental rights may not realise their complete meaning.   

128. To understand a person‘s dignity, one has to appreciate how  

the dignity of another is to be perceived. Alexis de Tocqueville tells  

us55:-  

―Whenever I find myself in the presence of another  human being, of whatever station, my dominant feeling  is not so much to serve him or please him as not to  offend his dignity.‖  

 129. Every individual has many possessions which assume the  

position of his/her definitive characteristics. There may not be any  

obsession with them but he/she may abhor to be   denuded of them,  

for they are sacred to him/her and so inseparably associated that  

he/she may not conceive of any dissolution.  He/she would like others  

to respect the said attributes with a singular acceptable condition that  

there is mutual respect. Mutual respect abandons outside  

interference and is averse to any kind of interdiction. It is based on  

the precept that the individuality of an individual is recognized,  

accepted and respected. Such respect for the conception of dignity  

                                                           5556, New York State Bar Journal (No 3. April, 1984), p.50

84

84  

has become a fundamental right under Article 21 of the Constitution  

and that ushers in the right of liberty of expression. Dignity and liberty  

as a twin concept in a society that cares for both, apart from painting  

a grand picture of humanity, also smoothens the atmosphere by  

promoting peaceful co-existence and thereby makes the  

administration of justice easy. In such a society, everyone becomes a  

part of the social engineering process where rights as inviolable and  

sacrosanct principles are adhered to; individual choice is not an  

exception and each one gets his/her space. Though no tower is built,  

yet the tower of individual rights with peaceful co-existence is visible.   

130. In Common Cause (A Regd. Society) (supra), one of us has  

observed that human dignity is beyond definition and it may, at times,  

defy description. To some, it may seem to be in the world of  

abstraction and some may even perversely treat it as an attribute of  

egotism or accentuated eccentricity. This feeling may come from the  

roots of absolute cynicism, but what really matters is that life without  

dignity is like a sound that is not heard. Dignity speaks, it has its  

sound, it is natural and human. It is a combination of thought and  

feeling.  

85

85  

131. In Maneka Gandhi v. Union of India and another56,  Krishna  

Iyer, J. observed that life is a terrestrial opportunity for unfolding  

personality and when any aspect of Article 21 is viewed in a truncated  

manner, several other freedoms fade out automatically. It has to be  

borne in mind that dignity of all is a sacrosanct human right and sans  

dignity, human life loses its substantial meaning.  

132. Dignity is that component of one‘s being without which  

sustenance of his/her being to the fullest or completest is  

inconceivable. In the theatre of life, without possession of the attribute  

of identity with dignity, the entity may be allowed entry to the centre  

stage but would be characterized as a spineless entity or, for that  

matter, projected as a ruling king without the sceptre. The purpose of  

saying so is that the identity of every individual attains the quality of  

an ―individual being‖ only if he/she has the dignity.  Dignity while  

expressive of choice is averse to creation of any dent. When  

biological expression, be it an orientation or optional expression of  

choice, is faced with impediment, albeit through any imposition of law,  

the individual‘s natural and constitutional right is dented. Such a  

situation urges the conscience of the final constitutional arbiter to  

                                                           56 (1978) 1 SCC 248

86

86  

demolish the obstruction and remove the impediment so as to allow  

the full blossoming of the natural and constitutional rights of  

individuals. This is the essence of dignity and we say, without any  

inhibition, that it is our constitutional duty to allow the individual to  

behave and conduct himself/herself as he/she desires and allow  

him/her to express himself/herself, of course, with the consent of the  

other. That is the right to choose without fear. It has to be ingrained  

as a necessary pre-requisite that consent is the real fulcrum of any  

sexual relationship.   

133.  In this context, we may travel a little abroad. In Law v. Canada  

(Minister of Employment and Immigration)57 capturing the essence  

of dignity, the Supreme Court of Canada has made the following  

observations:-  

"Human dignity means that an individual or group feels  self-respect and self-worth. It is concerned with  physical and psychological integrity and empowerment.  Human dignity is harmed by unfair treatment premised  upon personal traits or circumstances which do not  relate to individual needs, capacities, or merits. It is  enhanced by laws which are sensitive to the needs,  capacities, and merits of different individuals, taking  into account the context underlying their differences.  Human dignity is harmed when individuals and groups  are marginalized, ignored, or devalued, and is  

                                                           57

1999 1 S.C.R. 497

87

87  

enhanced when laws recognise the full place of all  individuals and groups within Canadian society."    

134. It is not only the duty of the State and the Judiciary to protect  

this basic right to dignity, but the collective at large also owes a  

responsibility to respect one another's dignity, for showing respect for  

the dignity of another is a constitutional duty. It is an expression of the  

component of constitutional fraternity.   

135. The concept of dignity gains importance in the present scenario,  

for a challenge has been raised to a provision of law which  

encroaches upon this essential right of a severely deprived section of  

our society. An individual's choice to engage in certain acts within  

their private sphere has been restricted by criminalising the same on  

account of the age old social perception. To harness such an  

essential decision, which defines the individualism of a person, by  

tainting it with criminality would violate the individual's right to dignity  

by reducing it to mere letters without any spirit.  

136. The European Court of Justice in P v. S58 in the context of  

rights of individuals who intend to or have undergone sex  

reassignment has observed that where a person is dismissed on the  

ground that he or she intends to undergo or has undergone gender  

                                                           58 Judgment of 30 April 1996. P v S and Cornwall County Council Case C-13/94. paras.  21-22.

88

88  

reassignment, he or she is treated unfavorably by comparison with  

persons of the sex to which he or she was deemed to belong before  

undergoing gender reassignment. To tolerate such discrimination  

would tantamount, as regards such a person, to a failure to respect  

the dignity and freedom to which he or she is entitled and which the  

Court has a duty to safeguard.  

137.  In Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey59, the  

United States Supreme Court had opined that such matters which  

involve the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in  

a lifetime, choices central to personal dignity and autonomy, are  

central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment.    

138. From the aforesaid pronouncements, some in different spheres  

but some also in the sphere of sexual orientation, the constitutional  

courts have laid emphasis on individual inclination, expression of both  

emotional and physical behaviour and freedom of choice, of course,  

subject to the consent of the other. A biological engagement, in  

contradistinction to going to a restaurant or going to a theatre to see a  

film or a play, is founded on company wherein both the parties have  

consented for the act. The inclination is an expression of choice that  

                                                           59505 U.S. 833 (1992)

89

89  

defines the personality to cumulatively build up the elevated paradigm  

of dignity. Be it clarified that expression of choice, apart from being a  

facet of  dignity, is also an essential component of liberty. Liberty as a  

concept has to be given its due place in the realm of dignity, for both  

are connected with the life and living of a persona.   

K.  Sexual orientation  

139. After stating about the value of dignity, we would have  

proceeded to deal with the cherished idea of privacy which has  

recently received concrete clarity in Puttaswamy‘s case. Prior to that,  

we are advised to devote some space to sexual orientation and the  

instructive definition of LGBT by Michael Kirby, former Judge of the  

High Court of Australia:-  

―Homosexual: People of either gender who are attracted, sexually,  

emotionally and in relationships, to persons of the same sex.  

Bisexual: Women who are attracted to both sexes; men who are  

attracted to both sexes.   

Lesbian: Women who are attracted to women.   

Gay: Men who are attracted to men, although this term is sometimes  

also used generically for all same-sex attracted persons.

90

90  

Gender identity: A phenomenon distinct from sexual orientation  

which refers to whether a person identifies as male or female. This  

identity' may exist whether there is "conformity or non-conformity"  

between their physical or biological or birth sex and their  

psychological sex and the way they express it through physical  

characteristics, appearance and conduct. It applies whether, in the  

Indian sub-continent, they identify as hijra or kothi or by another  

name.  

Intersex: Persons who are born with a chromosomal pattern or  

physical characteristics that do not clearly fall on one side or the  

other of a binary malefemale line.  

LGBT or LGBTIQ: Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, Transsexual, Intersex and  

Queer minorities. The word 'Queer' is sometimes used generically,  

usually by younger people, to include the members of all of the  

sexual minorities. I usually avoid this expression because of its  

pejorative overtones within an audience unfamiliar with the  

expression. However, it is spreading and, amongst the young, is  

often seen as an instance of taking possession of a pejorative word  

in order to remove its sting.

91

91  

MSM: Men who have sex with men. This expression is common in  

United Nations circles. It refers solely to physical, sexual activity by  

men with men. The expression is used on the basis that in some  

countries - including India - some men may engage in sexual acts  

with their own sex although not identifying as homosexual or even  

accepting a romantic or relationship emotion.‖60   

140. Presently, we shall focus on the aspect of sexual orientation.  

Every human being has certain basic biological characteristics and  

acquires or develops some facets under certain circumstances.   

The first can generally be termed as inherent orientation that is  

natural to his/her being. The second can be described as a  

demonstration of his/her choice which gradually becomes an  

inseparable quality of his/her being, for the individual also leans on  

a different expression because of the inclination to derive  

satisfaction. The third one has the proclivity which he/she  

maintains and does not express any other inclination. The first one  

is homosexuality, the second, bisexuality and third, heterosexuality.  

The third one is regarded as natural and the first one, by the same  

standard, is treated to be unnatural. When the second category                                                              60Sexual Orientation & Gender Identity – A New Province of Law for India, J. Michael D. Kirby, Tagore      Lectures, 2013    

92

92  

exercises his/her choice of homosexuality and involves in such an  

act, the same is also not accepted. In sum, the ‗act‘ is treated  

either in accord with nature or against the order of nature in terms  

of societal perception.  

141. The Yogyakarta Principles define the expression "sexual  

orientation‖ thus:-  

"Sexual Orientation" is understood to refer to each  person's capacity for profound emotional, affectional  and sexual attraction to and intimate and sexual  relations with, individuals of a different gender or the  same gender or more than one gender."    

142. In its study, the American Psychological Association has  

attempted to define ―sexual orientation‖ in the following manner:-  

"Sexual orientation refers to an enduring pattern of  emotional, romantic and/or sexual attractions to men.  women or both sexes. Sexual orientation also refers to  a person's sense of identity based on those attractions,  related behaviors, and membership in a community of  others who share those attractions. Research over  several decades has demonstrated that sexual  orientation ranges along a continuum, from exclusive  attraction to the other sex to exclusive attraction to the  same sex.‖61    

143. From the aforesaid, it has to be appreciated that homosexuality  

is something that is based on sense of identity. It is the reflection of a  

                                                           61American Psychological Association, "Answers to Your Questions for a Better Understanding of         Sexual Orientation & Homosexuality," 2008                  

93

93  

sense of emotion and expression of eagerness to establish intimacy.  

It is just as much ingrained, inherent and innate as heterosexuality.  

Sexual orientation, as a concept, fundamentally implies a pattern of  

sexual attraction. It is as natural a phenomenon as other natural  

biological phenomena. What the science of sexuality has led to is that  

an individual has the tendency to feel sexually attracted towards the  

same sex, for the decision is one that is controlled by neurological  

and biological factors. That is why it is his/her natural orientation  

which is innate and constitutes the core of his/her being and identity.   

That apart, on occasions, due to a sense of mutuality of release of  

passion, two adults may agree to express themselves in a different  

sexual behaviour which may include both the genders. To this, one  

can attribute a bisexual orientation which does not follow the rigidity  

but allows room for flexibility.   

144. The society cannot remain unmindful to the theory which  

several researches, conducted both in the field of biological and  

psychological science, have proven and reaffirmed time and again.  

To compel a person having a certain sexual orientation to proselytize  

to another is like asking a body part to perform a function it was never  

designed to perform in the first place. It is pure science, a certain

94

94  

manner in which the brain and genitals of an individual function and  

react. Whether one's sexual orientation is determined by genetic,  

hormonal, developmental, social and/or cultural influences (or a  

combination thereof), most people experience little or no sense of  

choice about their sexual orientation.62  

145. The statement of the American Psychological Association  on  

homosexuality which was released in July 1994 reiterates this  

position in the following observations:-  

"The research on homosexuality is very7 clear.  Homosexuality is neither mental illness nor moral  depravity. It is simply the way a minority of our  population expresses human love and sexuality. Study  after study documents the mental health of gay men  and lesbians. Studies of judgment, stability, reliability,  and social and vocational adaptiveness all show that  gay men and lesbians function every bit as well as  heterosexuals. Nor is homosexuality a matter of  individual choice. Research suggests that the  homosexual orientation is in place very early in the life  cycle, possibly even before birth. It is found in about  ten percent of the population, a figure which is  surprisingly constant across cultures, irrespective of  the different moral values and standards of a particular  culture. Contrary to what some imply, the incidence of  homosexuality in a population does not appear to  change with new moral codes or social mores.  Research findings suggest that efforts to repair  homosexuals are nothing more than social prejudice  garbed in psychological accouterments."  

(Emphasis is ours)

                                                           62 UNHCR GUIDELINES ON INTERNATIONAL PROTECTION NO. 9: Claims to Refugee Status based on        Sexual Orientation and/or Gender Identity within the context of Article 1A(2) of the 1951       Convention and/or its 1967 Protocol relating to the Status of Refugees

95

95  

146. In the said context, the observations made by Leonard Sax to  

the following effect are relevant and are reproduced below:-  

―Biologically, the difference between a gay man and a  straight man is something like the difference between a  left-handed person and a right-handed person. Being  left- handed isn't just a phase. A left-handed person  won't someday magically turn into a right-handed  person.... Some children are destined at birth to be left- handed, and some boys are destined at birth to grow  up to be gay.‖    

147. The Supreme Court of Canada in the case of James Egan and  

John Norris Nesbit v. Her Majesty The Queen in Right of Canada  

and another63, while holding that sexual orientation is one of the  

grounds for claiming the benefit under Section 15(1) as it is  

analogous to the grounds already set out in the list in Section 15(1)  

and the said list not being finite and exhaustive can be extended to  

LGBTs on account of the historical, social, political and economic  

disadvantage suffered by LGBTs, has observed:-  

"Sexual orientation is a deeply personal characteristic  that is either unchangeable or changeable only at  unacceptable personal costs, and so falls within the  ambit of s. 15 protection as being analogous to the  enumerated grounds."  

148. It is worth noting that scientific study has, by way of keen  

analysis, arrived at the conclusion as regards the individual‘s  

                                                           63[1995] 2 SCR 513  

96

96  

inherent orientation. Apart from orientation, as stated earlier, there  

can be situations which influence the emotional behaviour of an  

individual to seek intimacy in the same gender that may bring two  

persons together in a biological pattern.  It has to be treated as  

consensual activity and reflective of consensual choice.   

L. Privacy and its concomitant aspects     149. While testing the constitutional validity of Section 377 IPC, due  

regard must be given to the elevated right to privacy as has been  

recently proclaimed in Puttaswamy (supra). We shall not delve in  

detail upon the concept of the right to privacy as the same has been  

delineated at length in Puttaswamy (supra). In the case at hand, our  

focus is limited to dealing with the right to privacy vis-à-vis Section  

377 IPC and other facets such as right to choice as part of the  

freedom of expression and sexual orientation. That apart, within the  

compartment of privacy, individual autonomy has a significant space.  

Autonomy is individualistic. It is expressive of self-determination and  

such self-determination includes sexual orientation and declaration of  

sexual identity. Such an orientation or choice that reflects an  

individual‘s autonomy is innate to him/her. It is an inalienable part of

97

97  

his/her identity. The said identity under the constitutional scheme  

does not accept any interference as long as its expression is not  

against decency or morality. And the morality that is conceived of  

under the Constitution is constitutional morality. Under the autonomy  

principle, the individual has sovereignty over his/her body. He/she  

can surrender his/her autonomy wilfully to another individual and their  

intimacy in privacy is a matter of their choice.  Such concept of  

identity is not only sacred but is also in recognition of the  

quintessential facet of humanity in a person‘s nature. The autonomy  

establishes identity and the said identity, in the ultimate eventuate,  

becomes a part of dignity in an individual. This dignity is special to the  

man/woman who has a right to enjoy his/her life as per the  

constitutional norms and should not be allowed to wither and perish  

like a mushroom. It is a directional shift from conceptual macrocosm  

to cognizable microcosm. When such culture grows, there is an  

affirmative move towards a more inclusive and egalitarian society.  

Non-acceptance of the same would tantamount to denial of human  

rights to people and one cannot be oblivious of the saying of Nelson  

Mandela ― ―to deny  people their human rights is to challenge their  

very humanity.‖

98

98  

150. Article 12 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, (1948)  

makes a reference to privacy by stating:-  

"No one shall be subjected to arbitrary interference  with his privacy, family, home or correspondence nor  to attacks upon his honour and reputation. Everyone  has the right to the protection of the law against such  interference or attacks."    

151. Similarly, Article 17 of the International Covenant of Civil and  

Political Rights, to which India is a party, talks about privacy thus:-  

"No one shall be subjected to arbitrary or unlawful  interference with his privacy, family, home and  correspondence, nor to unlawful attacks on his honour  and reputation."     

152.  The European Convention on Human Rights also seeks to  

protect the right to privacy by stating:-  

"1. Everyone has the right to respect for his private and  family life, his home and his correspondence.  2. There shall be no interference by a public authority  except such as is in accordance with law and is  necessary in a democratic society in the interests of  national security, public safety or the economic well  being of the country, for the protection of health or  morals or for the protection of the rights and freedoms  of others."    

153. In the case of Dudgeon v. United Kingdom64, privacy has  

been defined as under:-  

                                                           64

[1981] 4 EHRR 149

99

99  

"Perhaps the best and most succinct legal definition of  privacy is that given by Warren and Brandeis - it is "the  right to be let alone"."    

154. In R. Rajagopal v. State of Tamil Nadu and others65, while  

discussing the concept of right to privacy, it has been observed that  

the right to privacy is implicit in the right to life and liberty guaranteed  

to the citizens of this country by Article 21 and it is a "right to be let  

alone", for a citizen has a right to safeguard the privacy of his/her  

own, his/her family, marriage, procreation, motherhood, child-bearing  

and education, among other matters.  

155. The above authorities capture the essence of the right to  

privacy. There can be no doubt that an individual also has a right to a  

union under Article 21 of the Constitution. When we say union, we do  

not mean the union of marriage, though marriage is a union. As a  

concept, union also means companionship in every sense of the word,  

be it physical, mental, sexual or emotional. The LGBT community is  

seeking realisation of its basic right to companionship, so long as  

such a companionship is consensual, free from the vice of deceit,  

force, coercion and does not result in violation of the fundamental  

rights of others.  

                                                           65

(1994) 6 SCC 632

100

100  

156. Justice Blackmun, in his vigorous dissent, in the case of  

Bowers, Attorney General of Georgia v. Hardwick et al. 66 ,  

regarding the ―right to be let alone‖, referred to Paris Adult Theatre I  

v. Slaton67 wherein he observed that only the most willful blindness  

could obscure the fact that sexual intimacy is a sensitive, key  

relationship of human existence, central to family life, community  

welfare and the development of human personality.  Justice  

Blackmun went on to observe:-  

―The fact that individuals define themselves in a  significant way through their intimate sexual  relationships with others suggests, in a Nation as  diverse as ours, that there may be many "right" ways  of conducting those relationships, and that much of the  richness of a relationship will come from the freedom  an individual has to choose the form and nature of  these intensely personal bonds. … In a variety of  circumstances, we have recognized that a necessary  corollary of giving individuals freedom to choose how  to conduct their lives is acceptance of the fact that  different individuals will make different choices.‖  

 

157.  In A.R. Coeriel and M.A.R. Aurik v. The Netherlands68, the  

Human Rights Committee observed that the notion of privacy refers  

to the sphere of a person's life in which he or she can freely express  

his or her identity, be it by entering into relationships with others or                                                              66

Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986)  67

413 U.S. 49 (1973)  68

Communication No. 453/1991, para. 10.2

101

101  

alone. The Committee was of the view that a person's surname  

constitutes an important component of one's identity and that the  

protection against arbitrary or unlawful interference with one's privacy  

includes the protection against arbitrary or unlawful interference with  

the right to choose and change one's own name.  

158. We may also usefully refer to the views of the Human Rights  

Committee in Toonen v. Australia69 to the effect that the introduction  

of the concept of arbitrariness is intended to guarantee that every  

interference provided for by the law should be in accordance with the  

provisions, aims and objectives of the Covenant and should be, in  

any event, reasonable in the circumstances. The requirement of  

reasonableness implies that any interference with privacy must be  

proportional to the end sought and be necessary in the circumstances  

of any given case.  

159. The South African Constitutional Court in National Coalition  

for Gay and Lesbian Equality and another v. Minister of Justice  

and others 70  has arrived at a theory of privacy in sexuality that  

includes both decisional and relational elements. It lays down that  

privacy recognises that we all have a right to a sphere of private  

                                                           69

Communication No. 488/1992, U.C. Doc CCPR/C/ 50/D 488/ 1992, March 31, 1994, para. 8.3  70

1998 (12) BCLR 1517 (CC)

102

102  

intimacy and autonomy which allows us to establish and nurture  

human relationships without interference from the outside community.  

The way in which we give expression to our sexuality is at the core of  

this area of private intimacy. If, in expressing our sexuality, we act  

consensually and without harming one another, invasion of that  

precinct will be a breach of our privacy. The Court admitted that the  

society had a poor record of seeking to regulate the sexual  

expression of South Africans. It observed that in some cases, as in  

this one, the reason for the regulation was discriminatory; the law, for  

example, outlawed sexual relationships among people of different  

races. The fact that a law prohibiting forms of sexual conduct is  

discriminatory does not, however, prevent it at the same time from  

being an improper invasion of the intimate sphere of human life to  

which protection is given by the Constitution in Section 14. The Court  

emphasized that the importance of a right to privacy in the new  

constitutional order should not be denied even while acknowledging  

the importance of equality. In fact, emphasising the breach of both  

these rights in the present case highlights just how egregious the  

invasion of the constitutional rights of gay persons has been. The  

offence which lies at the heart of the discrimination in this case

103

103  

constitutes, at the same time and independently, a breach of the  

rights of privacy and dignity which, without doubt, strengthens the  

conclusion that the discrimination is unfair.  

160. At home, the view as to the right to privacy underwent a sea-

change when a nine-Judge Bench of this Court in Puttaswamy  

(supra) elevated the right to privacy to the stature of fundamental  

right under Article 21 of the Constitution. One of us, Chandrachud, J.,  

speaking for the majority, regarded the judgment in Suresh Koushal  

as a discordant note and opined that the reasons stated therein  

cannot be regarded as a valid constitutional basis for disregarding a  

claim based on privacy under Article 21 of the Constitution. Further,  

he observed that the reasoning in Suresh Koushal‘s decision to the  

effect that ―a minuscule fraction of the country's population  

constitutes lesbians, gays, bisexuals or transgenders"  is not a  

sustainable basis to deny the right to privacy.   

161. It was further observed that the purpose of elevating certain  

rights to the stature of guaranteed fundamental rights is to insulate  

their exercise from the disdain of majorities, whether legislative or  

popular, and the guarantee of constitutional rights does not depend  

upon their exercise being favourably regarded by majoritarian opinion.  

104

104  

162. The test of popular acceptance, in view of the majority opinion,  

was not at all a valid basis to disregard rights which have been  

conferred with the sanctity of constitutional protection. The Court  

noted that the discrete and insular minorities face grave dangers of  

discrimination for the simple reason that their views, beliefs or way of  

life does not accord with the 'mainstream', but in a democratic  

Constitution founded on the Rule of Law, it does not mean that their  

rights are any less sacred than those conferred on other citizens.  

163. As far as the aspect of sexual orientation is concerned, the  

Court opined that it is an essential attribute of privacy and  

discrimination against an individual on the basis of sexual orientation  

is deeply offensive to the dignity and self-worth of the individual. The  

Court was of the view that equality demands that the sexual  

orientation of each individual in the society must be protected on an  

even platform, for the right to privacy and the protection of sexual  

orientation lie at the core of the fundamental rights guaranteed by  

Articles 14, 15 and 21 of the Constitution.  

164. Regarding the view in Suresh Koushal‘s case to the effect that  

the Delhi High Court in Naz Foundation case had erroneously relied  

upon international precedents in its anxiety to protect the so-called

105

105  

rights of LGBT persons, the nine-Judge Bench was of the opinion that  

the aforesaid view in Suresh Koushal (supra) was unsustainable.  

The rights of the lesbian, gay, bisexual and transgender population,  

as per the decision in Puttaswamy (supra), cannot be construed to  

be "so-called rights" as the expression "so-called" seems to suggest  

the exercise of liberty in the garb of a right which is illusory.  

165. The Court regarded such a construction in Suresh Koushal‘s  

case as inappropriate of the privacy based claims of the LGBT  

population, for their rights are not at all "so-called" but are real rights  

founded on sound constitutional doctrine. The Court went on to  

observe that the rights of the LGBT community inhere in the right to  

life, dwell in privacy and dignity and they constitute the essence of  

liberty and freedom. Further, the Court observed that sexual  

orientation being an essential component of identity, equal protection  

demands equal protection of the identity of every individual without  

discrimination.  

166. Speaking in the same tone and tenor, Kaul, J., while concurring  

with the view of Chandrachud, J., observed that the right to privacy  

cannot be denied even if there is a minuscule fraction of the  

population which is affected. He was of the view that the majoritarian

106

106  

concept does not apply to constitutional rights and the Courts are  

often called upon to take what may be categorized as a non-

majoritarian view.  

167. Kaul, J. went on to opine that one‘s sexual orientation is  

undoubtedly an attribute of privacy and in support of this view, he  

referred to the observations made in Mosley (supra) which read  

thus:-  

"130... It is not simply a matter of personal privacy v.  the public interest. The modern perception is that there  is a public interest in respecting personal privacy. It is  thus a question of taking account of conflicting public  interest considerations and evaluating them according  to increasingly well recognized criteria.    131. When the courts identify an infringement of a  person‘s Article 8 rights, and in particular in the context  of his freedom to conduct his sex life and personal  relationships as he wishes, it is right to afford a remedy  and to vindicate that right. The only permitted  exception is where there is a countervailing public  interest which in the particular circumstances is strong  enough to outweigh it; that is to say. because one at  least of the established "limiting principles" comes into  play. Was it necessary and proportionate for the  intrusion to take place, for example, in order to expose  illegal activity or to prevent the public from being  significantly misled by public claims hitherto made by  the individual concerned (as with Naomi Campbell's  public denials of drug- taking)? Or was it necessary  because the information, in the words of the  Strasbourg court in Von Hannover at (60) and (76).  would make a contribution to "a debate of general  interest"? That is, of course, a very high test, it is yet to

107

107  

be determined how far that doctrine will be taken in the  courts of this jurisdiction in relation to photography in  public places. If taken literally, it would mean a very  significant change in what is permitted. It would have a  profound effect on the tabloid and celebrity culture to  which we have become accustomed in recent years.""  

 168. After the nine-Judge bench decision in Puttaswamy (supra),  

the challenge to the vires of Section 377 IPC has been stronger than  

ever. It needs to be underscored that in the said decision, the nine-

Judge Bench has held that sexual orientation is also a facet of a  

person's privacy and that the right to privacy is a fundamental right  

under the Constitution of India.   

169. The observation made in Suresh Koushal (supra) that gays,  

lesbians, bisexuals and transgenders constitute a very minuscule part  

of the population is perverse due to the very reason that such an  

approach would be violative of the equality principle enshrined under  

Article 14 of the Constitution. The mere fact that the percentage of  

population whose fundamental right to privacy is being abridged by  

the existence of Section 377 in its present form is low does not  

impose a limitation upon this Court from protecting the fundamental  

rights of those who are so affected by the present Section 377 IPC.  

170. The constitutional framers could have never intended that the  

protection of fundamental rights was only for the majority population.

108

108  

If such had been the intention, then all provisions in Part III of the  

Constitution would have contained qualifying words such as 'majority  

persons' or 'majority citizens'. Instead, the provisions have employed  

the words 'any person‘ and ‗any citizen' making it manifest that the  

constitutional courts are under an obligation to protect the  

fundamental rights of every single citizen without waiting for the  

catastrophic situation when the fundamental rights of the majority of   

citizens get violated.  

171. Such a view is well supported on two counts, namely, one that  

the constitutional courts have to embody in their approach a  

telescopic vision wherein they inculcate the ability to be futuristic and  

do not procrastinate till the day when the number of citizens whose  

fundamental rights are affected and violated grow in figures. In the  

case at hand, whatever be the percentage of gays, lesbians,  

bisexuals and transgenders, this Court is not concerned with the  

number of persons belonging to the LGBT community. What matters  

is whether this community is entitled to certain fundamental rights  

which they claim and whether such fundamental rights are being  

violated due to the presence of a law in the statute book. If the  

answer to both these questions is in the affirmative, then the

109

109  

constitutional courts must not display an iota of doubt and must not  

hesitate in striking down such provision of law on the account of it  

being violative of the fundamental rights of certain citizens, however  

minuscule their percentage may be.  

172. A second count on which the view in Suresh Koushal (supra)  

becomes highly unsustainable is that the language of both Articles 32  

and 226 of the Constitution is not reflective of such an intention. A  

cursory reading of both the Articles divulges that the right to move the  

Supreme Court and the High Courts under Articles 32 and 226  

respectively is not limited to a situation when there is violation of the  

fundamental rights of a large chunk of populace.  

173. Such a view is also fortified by several landmark judgments of  

the Supreme Court such as D.K. Basu v. State of W.B.71 wherein the  

Court was concerned with the fundamental rights of only those  

persons who were put under arrest and which again formed a  

minuscule fraction of the total populace. Another recent case wherein  

the Supreme Court while discharging its constitutional duty did not  

hesitate to protect the fundamental right to die with dignity is  

Common Cause (A Regd. Society) (supra) wherein the Supreme  

                                                           71

(1997) 1 SCC 416

110

110  

Court stepped in to protect the said fundamental right of those who  

may have slipped into permanent vegetative state, who again form a  

very minuscule part of the society.   

174. Such an approach reflects the idea as also mooted by Martin  

Luther King Jr. who said, ―Injustice anywhere is a threat to justice  

everywhere‖. While propounding this view, we are absolutely  

conscious of the concept of reasonable classification and the fact that  

even single person legislation could be valid as held in Chiranjit Lal  

Chowdhury v. Union of India72, which regarded the classification to  

be reasonable from both procedural and substantive points of view.  

175. We are aware that the legislature is fully competent to enact  

laws which are applicable only to a particular class or group. But, for  

the classification to be valid, it must be founded on an intelligible  

differentia and the differentia must have a rational nexus with the  

object sought to be achieved by a particular provision of law.  

176. That apart, since it is alleged that Section 377 IPC in its present  

form violates a fundamental right protected by Article 21 of the  

Constitution, that is, the right to personal liberty, it has to not only  

stand the test of Article 21 but it must also stand the test of Article 19  

                                                           72

[1950] 1 SCR 869

111

111  

which is to say that the restriction imposed by it has to be reasonable  

and also that of Article 14 which is to say that Section 377 must not  

be arbitrary.  

177. Whether Section 377 stands the trinity test of Articles 14, 19  

and 21 as propounded in the case of Maneka Gandhi (supra) will be  

ascertained and determined at a later stage of this judgment when we  

get into the interpretative dissection of Section 377 IPC.  

M.  Doctrine of progressive realization of rights     

178. When we talk about the rights guaranteed under the  

Constitution and the protection of these rights, we observe and  

comprehend a manifest ascendance and triumphant march of such  

rights which, in turn, paves the way for the doctrine of progressive  

realization of the rights under the Constitution. This doctrine  

invariably reminds us about the living and dynamic nature of a  

Constitution. Edmund Burke, delineating upon the progressive and  

the perpetual growing nature of a Constitution, had said that a  

Constitution is ever-growing and it is perpetually continuous as it  

embodies the spirit of a nation. It is enriched at the present by the  

past experiences and influences and makes the future richer than the  

present.

112

112  

179. In N.M. Thomas (supra), Krishna Iyer, J., in his concurring  

opinion, observed thus:-  

"Law, including constitutional law, can no longer go it  alone' but must be illumined in the interpretative  process by sociology and allied fields of knowledge.  Indeed, the term 'constitutional law' symbolizes an  intersection of law and politics, wherein issues of  political power are acted on by persons trained in the  legal tradition, working in judicial institutions, following  the procedures of law, thinking as lawyers think. So  much so, a wider perspective is needed to resolve  issues of constitutional law."     And again:-     ―An overview of the decided cases suggests the need  to re-interpret the dynamic import of the 'equality  clauses' and, to stress again, beyond reasonable  doubt, that the paramount law. which is organic and  regulates our nation's growing life, must take in its  sweep ethics, economics, politics and sociology'.‖     

The learned Judge, expanding the horizon of his concern,  

reproduced the lament of Friedman:-  

"It would be tragic if the law were so petrified  as to be unable to respond to the unending  challenge of evolutionary or revolutionary  changes in society.''    

The main assumptions which Friedman makes are:    

"first, the law is, in Holmes' phrase, not a  brooding omnipotence in the sky', but a  flexible instrument of social order, dependent  on the political values of the society which it  purports to regulate...."  

113

113  

 Naturally surges the interrogation, what are the  challenges of changing values to which the guarantee  of equality must respond and how?‖     

180.  Further, Krishna Iyer, J. referred to the classic statement made  

by Chief Justice Marshall in McCulloch v. Maryland73 which was  

also followed by Justice Brennan in Kazenbach v. Morgan74. The  

said observation reads thus:-  

"Let the end be legitimate, let it be within the scope of  the constitution, and all means which are appropriate,  which are plainly adapted to that end, which are not  prohibited, but consist with the letter and spirit of the  constitution, are constitutional."    

181. In Manoj Narula (supra), the Court recognized the dynamic  

nature of the Indian Constitution and observed that it is a living  

document with capabilities of enormous dynamism. It is a Constitution  

made for a progressive society and the working of such a Constitution  

depends upon the prevalent atmosphere and conditions.  

182. In Government of NCT of Delhi (supra), the Court, while  

contemplating on what is it that makes a Constitution a dynamic and  

a living document, observed that it is the philosophy of 'constitutional  

culture' which, as a set of norms and practices, breathes life into the  

                                                           73

(1816) 17 US 316  74

(1966) 384 US 641

114

114  

words of the great document and it constantly enables the words to  

keep stride with the rapid and swift changes occurring in the society  

and the responsibility of fostering a constitutional culture rests upon  

the shoulders of the State. Thereafter, the Court went on to observe:-  

―The Constitutional Courts, while interpreting the  constitutional provisions, have to take into account the  constitutional culture, bearing in mind its flexible and  evolving nature, so that the provisions are given a  meaning which reflect the object and purpose of the  Constitution.‖    

And again, it proceeded to reproduce the wise words of Justice  

Brennan:-   

"We current Justices read the Constitution in the only  way that we can: as Twentieth Century Americans. We  look to the history of the time of framing and to the  intervening history of interpretation. But the ultimate  question must be, what do the words of the text mean  in our time? For the genius of the Constitution rests not  in any static meaning it might have had in a world that  is dead and gone, but in the adaptability of its great  principles to cope with current problems and current  needs. What the constitutional fundamentals meant to  the wisdom of other times cannot be their measure to  the vision of our time. Similarly, what those  fundamentals mean for us, our descendants will learn,  cannot be the measure to the vision of their time."  

 183. We have discussed, in brief, the dynamic and progressive  

nature of the Constitution to accentuate that rights under the  

Constitution are also dynamic and progressive, for they evolve with

115

115  

the evolution of a society and with the passage of time. The rationale  

behind the doctrine of progressive realization of rights is the dynamic  

and ever growing nature of the Constitution under which the rights  

have been conferred to the citizenry.  

184.  The constitutional courts have to recognize that the  

constitutional rights would become a dead letter without their dynamic,  

vibrant and pragmatic interpretation. Therefore, it is necessary for the  

constitutional courts to inculcate in their judicial interpretation and  

decision making a sense of engagement and a sense of constitutional  

morality so that they, with the aid of judicial creativity, are able to fulfill  

their foremost constitutional obligation, that is, to protect the rights  

bestowed upon the citizens of our country by the Constitution.  

185. Here, it is also apposite to refer to the words of Lord Roskill in  

his presidential address to the Bentham Club at University College of  

London on February 29, 1984 on the subject 'Law Lords,  

Reactionaries or Reformers'75 which read as follows:-  

"Legal policy now stands enthroned and will I hope  remain one of the foremost considerations governing  the development by the House of Lords of the common  law. What direction should this development now take?  I can think of several occasions upon which we have  all said to ourselves:-  

                                                           75

Lord Roskill, “Law Lords, Reactionaries or Reformers”, Current Legal Problems (1984)

116

116  

 "this case requires a policy decision what is  the right policy decision?" The answer is, and  I hope will hereafter be, to follow that route  which is most consonant with the current  needs of the society, and which will be seen to  be sensible and will pragmatically thereafter  be easy to apply. No doubt the Law Lords will  continue to be the targets for those academic  lawyers who will seek intellectual perfection  rather than imperfect pragmatism. But much  of the common law and virtually all criminal  law, distasteful as it may be to some to have  to acknowledge it. is a blunt instrument by  means of which human beings, whether they  like it or not, are governed and subject to  which they are required to live, and blunt  instruments are rarely perfect intellectually or  otherwise. By definition they operate bluntly  and not sharply."  

[Emphasis supplied]    

186. What the words of Lord Roskill suggest is that it is not only the  

interpretation of the Constitution which needs to be pragmatic, due to  

the dynamic nature of a Constitution, but also the legal policy of a  

particular epoch must be in consonance with the current and the  

present needs of the society, which are sensible in the prevalent  

times and at the same time easy to apply.  

187. This also gives birth to an equally important role of the State to  

implement the constitutional rights effectively. And of course, when  

we say State, it includes all the three organs, that is, the legislature,

117

117  

the executive as well as the judiciary. The State has to show  

concerned commitment which would result in concrete action. The  

State has an obligation to take appropriate measures for the  

progressive realization of economic, social and cultural rights.  

188. The doctrine of progressive realization of rights, as a natural  

corollary, gives birth to the doctrine of non-retrogression. As per this  

doctrine, there must not be any regression of rights. In a progressive  

and an ever-improving society, there is no place for retreat. The  

society has to march ahead.  

189. The doctrine of non-retrogression sets forth that the State  

should not take measures or steps that deliberately lead to  

retrogression on the enjoyment of rights either under the Constitution  

or otherwise.  

190. The aforesaid two doctrines lead us to the irresistible  

conclusion that if we were to accept the law enunciated in Suresh  

Koushal's case, it would definitely tantamount to a retrograde step in  

the direction of the progressive interpretation of the Constitution and  

denial of progressive realization of rights.  It is because Suresh  

Koushal’s view gets wrongly embedded with the minuscule facet and  

assumes criminality on the bedrock being guided by a sense of social

118

118  

morality. It discusses about health which is no more a phobia and is  

further moved by the popular morality while totally ignoring the  

concepts of privacy, individual choice and the orientation. Orientation,  

in certain senses, does get the neuro-impulse to express while seeing  

the other gender.  That apart, swayed by data, Suresh Koushal fails  

to appreciate that the sustenance of fundamental rights does not  

require majoritarian sanction. Thus, the ruling becomes sensitively  

susceptible.   

N.  International perspective  

(i)  United States  

191. The Supreme Court of the United States in Obergefell, et al. v.  

Hodges, Director, Ohio Department of Health, et al.76,  highlighting  

the plight of homosexuals, observed that until the mid-20th century,  

same-sex intimacy had long been condemned as  immoral by the  

State itself in most Western nations and a belief was often embodied  

in the criminal law and for this reason, homosexuals, among others,  

were not deemed to  have dignity in their own distinct identity. The  

Court further noted that truthful declaration by same-sex couples of  

what was in their  hearts had to remain unspoken and even when a  

                                                           76576 US (2015)

119

119  

greater awareness of the humanity and integrity of homosexual   

persons came in the period after World War II, the argument that  

gays and lesbians had a just claim to dignity  was in conflict with both  

law and widespread social conventions. The Court also observed that  

same-sex intimacy remained a crime in many States and that gays  

and lesbians were prohibited from most government employment,  

barred from military service, excluded under immigration laws,  

targeted by the police and burdened in their rights to associate.   

192. The Court further observed that what the statutes in question  

seek to control is a personal relationship, whether or not entitled to  

formal recognition in the law, that is within the liberty of persons to  

choose without being punished as criminals. Further, the Court  

acknowledged that adults may choose to enter upon a relationship in  

the confines of their homes and their own private lives and still retain  

their dignity as free persons and that when sexuality finds overt  

expression in intimate conduct with another person, the conduct can  

be but one element in a personal bond that is more enduring. The  

Court held that such liberty protected by the Constitution allows  

homosexual persons the right to make this choice.

120

120  

193. In the case of  Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins77, the Supreme  

Court of the United States, while evaluating the legal relevance of sex  

stereotyping,  observed thus:-   

"...we are beyond the day when an employer could  evaluate employees by assuming or insisting that they  matched the stereotype associated with their group, for,  "'[i]n forbidding employers to discriminate against  individuals because of their sex, Congress intended to  strike at the entire spectrum of disparate treatment of  men and women resulting from sex stereotypes.""    

194. In the case of Kimberly Hively v. Ivy Tech Community  

College of Indiana78, while holding that discrimination amongst  

employees based on their sexual orientation amounts to  

discrimination based on sex, the Court observed as under:-  

"We would be remiss not to consider the EEOC's recent  decision in which it concluded that "sexual orientation is  inherently a 'sex-based consideration,' and an allegation  of discrimination based on sexual orientation is  necessarily an allegation of sex discrimination under Title  VII." Baldwin v. Foxx, EEOC Appeal No. 0120133080,  2015 WL 4397641, at *5, *10 (July 16, 2015). The EEOC,  the body charged with enforcing Title VII, came to this  conclusion for three primary reasons. First, it concluded  that "sexual orientation discrimination is sex  discrimination because it necessarily entails treating an  employee less favorably because of the employee's sex."  Id. at *5 (proffering the example of a woman who is  suspended for placing a photo of her female spouse on  her desk, and a man who faces no consequences for the  

                                                           77490 U.S. 228 (1989)  78

830 F.3d 698 (7th Cir. 2016)

121

121  

same act). Second, it explained that "sexual orientation  discrimination is also sex discrimination because it is  associational discrimination on the basis of sex," in which  an employer discriminates against lesbian, gay, or  bisexual employees based on who they date or marry. Id.  at *6-7. Finally, the EEOC described sexual orientation  discrimination as a form of discrimination based on  gender stereotypes in which employees are harassed or  punished for failing to live up to societal norms about  appropriate masculine and feminine behaviors,  mannerisms, and appearances. Id. In coming to these  conclusions, the EEOC noted critically that "courts have  attempted to distinguish discrimination based on sexual  orientation from discrimination based on sex, even while  noting that the "borders [between the two classes] are  imprecise." Id. at *8 (quoting Simonton, 232 F.3d at 35).  

[Underlining is ours]  

195. In the case of Lawrence v. Texas79,  while dealing with the  

issue of decriminalization of sexual conduct between homosexuals,  

the U.S. Supreme Court observed that the said issue neither involved  

minors nor persons who might be injured or coerced or who are  

situated in relationships where consent might not easily be refused  

nor did it  involve public conduct or prostitution nor the question  

whether the government must give formal recognition to any  

relationship that homosexual persons seek to enter. The Court further  

observed that the issue related to two adults who, with full and mutual  

consent of each other, engaged in sexual practices common to a  

                                                           79 539 U.S. 558 (2003)

122

122  

homosexual lifestyle. The Court declared that the petitioners were  

entitled to respect for their private lives and that the State could not  

demean their existence or control their destiny by making their private  

sexual conduct a crime, for their right to liberty under the Due  

Process Clause gives them the full right to engage in their conduct  

without the intervention of the State.  

196. In Roberts v. United States Jaycees80, the Supreme Court of  

the United States observed:-  

"Our decisions have referred to constitutionally  protected "freedom of association" in two distinct  senses. In one line of decisions, the Court has  concluded that choices to enter into and maintain  certain intimate human relationships must be secured  against undue intrusion by the State because of the  role of such relationships in safeguarding the individual  freedom that is central to our constitutional scheme. In  this respect, freedom of association receives protection  as a fundamental element of personal liberty. In  another set of decisions, the Court has recognized a  right to associate for the purpose of engaging in those  activities protected by the First Amendment ~ speech,  assembly, petition for the redress of grievances, and  the exercise of religion. The Constitution guarantees  freedom of association of this kind as an indispensable  means of preserving other individual liberties. The  intrinsic and instrumental features of constitutionally  protected association may, of course, coincide."  

[Emphasis added]   

                                                           80468 U.S. 609 (1984)

123

123  

(ii) Canada  

197.  The Supreme Court of Canada, in Delwin Vriend and others  

v. Her Majesty the Queen in Right of Alberta and others81, while  

interpreting a breach of Section 15(1) of the Canadian Charter of  

Rights and Freedoms, arrived at the conclusion that 'sex' includes  

sexual orientation. Section 15(1) of the Charter reads thus:-  

 "Every individual is equal before and under the law and  has the right to the equal protection and equal benefit  of the law without discrimination and, in particular,  without discrimination based on race, national or ethnic  origin, colour, religion, sex, age or physical disability."   

 198.  In Delwin Vriend, the Supreme Court of Canada, relying on the  

reasoning adopted by it in Egan v. Canada (supra), applied its well-

known test of grounds analogous to those specified textually. The  

Egan test is:-  

"In Egan, it was said that there are two aspects which  are relevant in determining whether the distinction  created by the law constitutes discrimination. First,  "whether the equality right was denied on the basis of  a personal characteristic which is either enumerated in  s. 15(1) or which is analogous to those enumerated".  Second "whether that distinction has the effect on the  claimant of imposing a burden, obligation or  disadvantage not imposed upon others or of  withholding or limiting access to benefits or  advantages which are available to others" (para. 131).  

                                                           81

[1998] 1 SCR 493

124

124  

A discriminatory distinction was also described as one  which is "capable of either promoting or perpetuating  the view that the individual adversely affected by this  distinction is less capable, or less worthy of recognition  or value as a human being or as a member of  Canadian society, equally deserving of concern,  respect, and consideration" (Egan, at para. 56, per  L'Heureux - Dube J.). It may as well be appropriate to  consider whether the unequal treatment is based on  "the stereotypical application of presumed group or  personal characteristics" (Miron, at para. 128, per  McLachlin J.)  

 

In Egan, it was held, on the basis of "historical social,  political and economic disadvantage suffered by  homosexuals" and the emerging consensus among  legislatures (at para. 176), as well as previous judicial  decisions (at para. 177), that sexual orientation is a  ground analogous to those listed in s. 15(1). Sexual  orientation is "a deeply personal characteristic that is  either unchangeable or changeable only at  unacceptable personal costs" (para. 5). It is analogous  to the other personal characteristics enumerated in s.  15(1); and therefore this step of the test is satisfied."    

199. Thereafter, the Court in Delwin Vriend (supra) observed that  

perhaps the most important outcome is the psychological harm which  

may ensue from the state of affairs as the fear of discrimination (by  

LGBT) would logically lead them to concealment of true identity and  

this is harmful to their personal confidence and self-esteem. The  

Court held that this is a clear example of a distinction which demeans  

the individual and strengthens and perpetrates the view that gays and

125

125  

lesbians are less worthy of protection as individuals in Canada‘s  

society and the potential harm to the dignity and perceived worth of  

gay and lesbian individuals constitutes a particularly cruel form of  

discrimination.  

(iii) South Africa  

200. The Constitutional Court of South Africa in National Coalition  

for Gay & Lesbian Equality (supra) made the following relevant  

observations:-  

"Its symbolic effect is to state that in the eyes of our  legal system all gay men are criminals. The stigma  thus attached to a significant proportion of our  population is manifest. But the harm imposed by the  criminal law is far more than symbolic. As a result of  the criminal offence, gay men are at risk of arrest,  prosecution and conviction of the offence of sodomy  simply because they seek to engage in sexual conduct  which is part of their experience of being human. Just  as apartheid legislation rendered the lives of couples of  different racial groups perpetually at risk, the sodomy  offence builds insecurity and vulnerability into the daily  lives of gay men. There can be no doubt that the  existence of a law which punishes a form of sexual  expression for gay men degrades and devalues gay  men in our broader society. As such it is a palpable  invasion of their dignity and a breach of section 10 of  the Constitution."  

 

126

126  

 (iv) United Kingdom    201.  In Euan Sutherland v. United Kingdom82, the issue before  

the European Commission of Human Rights was whether the  

difference in age limit for consent for sexual activities for  

homosexuals and heterosexuals, the age limit being 16 years in  

the case of heterosexuals and 18 years in the case of  

homosexuals, is justified.  While considering the same, the  

Commission observed that no objective and reasonable  

justification exists for the maintenance of a higher minimum age of  

consent in case of male homosexuals as compared to  

heterosexuals and that the application discloses discriminatory  

treatment in the exercise of the applicant's right to respect for  

private life under Article 8 of the Convention. The Commission  

further observed that sexual orientation was usually established  

before the age of puberty in both boys and girls and referred to  

evidence that reducing the age of consent would unlikely affect the  

majority of men engaging in homosexual activity, either in general  

or within specific age groups. The Council of the British Medical  

Association (BMA) concluded in its Report that the age of consent  

                                                           82

2001 ECHR 234  

127

127  

for homosexual men should be set at 16 since the then existing  

law might inhibit efforts to improve the sexual health of young  

homosexual and bisexual men. An equal age of consent was also  

supported by the Royal College of Psychiatrists, the Health  

Education Authority and the National Association of Probation  

Officers as well as by other bodies and organizations concerned  

with health and social welfare. It is further noted that equality of  

treatment in respect of the age of consent is now recognized by  

the great majority of Member States of the Council of Europe.  

(v) Other Courts/Jurisdictions    202. In Ang Ladlad LGBT Party v. Commission of Elections83, the  

Supreme Court of the Republic of the Philippines observed:-  

"Freedom of expression constitutes one of the  essential foundations of a democratic society, and this  freedom applies not only to those that are favorably  received but also to those that offend, shock, or disturb.  Any restriction imposed in this sphere must be  proportionate to the legitimate aim pursued. Absent  any compelling state interest, it is not for the  COMELEC or this Court to impose its views on the  populace.‖    

 Elaborating further, the Court held:-    

―It follows that both expressions concerning one's  homosexuality and the activity of forming a political  

                                                           83

G. R. No.190582, Supreme Court of Philippines (2010)

128

128  

association that supports LGBT individuals are  protected as well.‖    

The Court navigated through European and United Nations  

Judicial decisions and held:-  

―In the area of freedom of expression, for instance,  United States courts have ruled that existing free  speech doctrines protect gay and lesbian rights to  expressive conduct. In order to justify the prohibition of  a particular expression of opinion, public institutions  must show that their actions were caused by  "something more than a mere desire to avoid the  discomfort and unpleasantness that always  accompany an unpopular viewpoint."    

203. Further, in Toonen‘s case, the Human Rights Committee made  

the following relevant observations:-  

"I concur with this view, as the common denominator  for the grounds "race, colour and sex" are biological or  genetic factors. This being so, the criminalization of  certain behaviour operating under Sections 122(a), (c)  and 123 of the Tasmanian Criminal Code must be  considered incompatible with article 26 of the  Covenant.    

Firstly, these provisions of the Tasmanian  Criminal Code prohibit sexual intercourse between  men and between women, thereby making a distinction  between heterosexuals and homosexuals. Secondly,  they criminalize other sexual contacts between  consenting men without at the same time criminalizing  such contacts between women. These provisions  therefore set aside the principle of equality before the  law. It should be emphasized that it is the  criminalization as such that constitutes discrimination  of which individuals may claim to be victims, and thus

129

129  

violates article 26, notwithstanding the fact that the law  has not been enforced over a considerable period of  time: the designated behaviour none the less remains  a criminal offence."  

 204. In Dudgeon (supra), the European Court of Human Rights  

made the following observations with respect to homosexuality:-  

"It cannot be maintained in these circumstances that  there is a "pressing social need" to make such acts  criminal offences, there being no sufficient justification  provided by the risk of harm to vulnerable sections of  society requiring protection or by the effects on the  public. On the issue of proportionality, the Court  considers that such justifications as there are for  retaining the law in force unamended are outweighed  by the detrimental effects which the very existence of  the legislative provisions in question can have on the  life of a person of homosexual orientation like the  applicant. Although members of the public who regard  homosexuality as immoral may be shocked, offended  or disturbed by the commission by others of private  homosexual acts, this cannot on its own warrant the  application of penal sanctions when it is consenting  adults alone who are involved."  

[Emphasis supplied]  

O. Comparative analysis of Section 375 and Section 377 IPC    205. Let us, in the obtaining situation, conduct a comparative  

analysis of the offence of rape and unnatural offences as defined  

under Section 375 and Section 377 of the IPC respectively. Section  

375 IPC defines the offence of rape and reads as under:-  

130

130  

Section 375. Rape-A man is said to commit "rape" if  

he —  

(a) penetrates his penis, to any extent, into the vagina,  

mouth, urethra or anus of a woman or makes her to do  

so with him or any other person; or  

 

(b) inserts, to any extent, any object or a part of the  

body, not being the penis, into the vagina, the urethra  

or anus of a woman or makes her to do so with him or  

any other person; or  

 

(c) manipulates any part of the body of a woman so as  

to cause penetration into the vagina, urethra, anus or  

any part of body of such woman or makes her to do so  

with him or any other person; or  

 

(d) applies his mouth to the vagina, anus, urethra of a  

woman or makes her to do so with him or any other  

person, under the circumstances falling under any of  

the following seven descriptions: —  

 

First. —Against her will.  

 

Secondly. —Without her consent.  

 

Thirdly. —With her consent, when her consent has  

been obtained by putting her or any person in whom  

she is interested, in fear of death or of hurt.  

 

Fourthly. —With her consent, when the man knows  

that he is not her husband and that her consent is  

given because she believes that he is another man to  

whom she is or believes herself to be lawfully married.  

 

Fifthly. —With her consent when, at the time of giving  

such consent, by reason of unsoundness of mind or  

intoxication or the administration by him personally or  

through another of any stupefying or unwholesome

131

131  

substance, she is unable to understand the nature and  

consequences of that to which she gives consent.  

 

Sixthly. —With or without her consent, when she is  

under eighteen years of age.  

 

Seventhly. —When she is unable to communicate  

consent.  

 

Explanation I.—For the purposes of this section,  

"vagina" shall also include labia majora.  

 

Explanation 2. — Consent means an unequivocal  

voluntary agreement when the woman by words,  

gestures or any form of verbal or non-verbal  

communication, communicates willingness to  

participate in the specific sexual act:  

 

Provided that a woman who does not physically resist  

to the act of penetration shall not by the reason only of  

that fact, be regarded as consenting to the sexual  

activity.  

 

Exception I.—A medical procedure or intervention shall  

not constitute rape.  

 

Exception 2. —Sexual intercourse or sexual acts by a  

man with his own wife, the wife not being under fifteen  

years of age, is not rape.'.  

 206. A cursory reading of Section 375 IPC divulges that it is a  

gender specific provision for the protection of women as only a man  

can commit the offence of rape. The Section has been divided into  

two parts. The former part, comprising of Clauses (a) to (d), simply

132

132  

describes what acts committed by a man with a woman would  

amount to rape provided that the said acts are committed in the  

circumstances falling under any of the seven descriptions as  

stipulated by the latter part of the Section.   

207. It is in this way that the latter part of Section 375 IPC becomes  

important as it lays down the circumstances, either of which must be  

present, for an act committed by a man with a woman to come within  

the sweep of the offence of rape. To put it differently, for completing  

the offence of rape, any of the circumstances described in the latter  

part of Section 375 must be present. Let us now dissect each of the  

seven descriptions appended to Section 375 IPC which specify the  

absence of a willful and informed consent for constituting the offence  

of rape.  

208. The first description provides that any of the acts described in  

the former part of Section 375 IPC would amount to rape if such acts  

are committed against the will of the woman. The second description  

stipulates that the acts described in the former part would amount to  

rape if such acts are committed without the consent of the woman. As  

per the third description, the acts would amount to rape even if the  

woman has given her consent but the said consent has been

133

133  

obtained by putting her or any person in whom she is interested, in  

fear of death or of hurt. As per the fourth description, the acts would  

amount to rape when the woman has given her consent but the same  

was given by her under the belief that she is or believes herself to be  

lawfully married to the man committing the acts stated in the former  

part of the Section. The fifth description provides that the acts  

described in the former part would amount to rape if the woman gives  

her consent but at the time of giving such consent, she is unable to  

understand the nature and consequences of the acts to which she  

consents due to the reason of unsoundness of mind or intoxication or  

the administration of any stupefying or unwholesome substance  

either by the man who commits the acts or through another third  

person. The sixth description is plain and simple as it stipulates that  

the acts described in the former part of the Section would amount to  

rape, irrespective of the fact whether the woman has given her  

consent or not, if, at the time when the acts were committed, the  

woman was below the age of eighteen years. Coming to the seventh  

and the last description, it provides that the acts prescribed in the  

former part would amount to rape if the woman is unable to  

communicate her consent.  

134

134  

209. Explanation 2 to Section 375 IPC gives the definition of consent  

for the purpose of Section 375 to the effect that consent means an  

unequivocal voluntary agreement by the woman through words,  

gestures or any form of verbal or non-verbal communication whereby  

she communicates her willingness to participate in any of the sexual  

acts described in the former part of Section 375 IPC.   

210. We have scrutinized the anatomy of the seven descriptions  

contained in the latter part of Section 375 IPC along with Explanation  

2 to Section 375 IPC to emphasize and accentuate that the element  

of absence of consent is firmly ingrained in all the descriptions  

contained in the latter part of Section 375 IPC and the absence of a  

willful and informed consent is sine qua non to designate the acts  

contained in the former part of Section 375 IPC as rape.   

211.  Presently, we proceed to scan the anatomy of Section 377 of  

IPC and x-ray the provision to study its real nature and content.  It  

reads thus:-   

―Section 377. Unnatural offences.—Whoever  voluntarily has carnal intercourse against the order of  nature with any man, woman or animal, shall be  punished with imprisonment for life, or with       imprisonment of either description for a term which  may extend to ten years, and shall also be liable to  fine.  

135

135  

Explanation.—Penetration is sufficient to constitute the  

carnal intercourse necessary to the offence described  

in this section.‖  

 

212. Section 377 IPC, unlike Section 375, is a gender-neutral  

provision as it uses the word ‗whoever‘. The word ‗carnal‘, as per the  

Black‘s Law Dictionary84, means of the body, relating to the body,  

fleshy or sexual. ‗Sexual intercourse‘ has been defined in Black‘s Law  

Dictionary as a contact between a male and a female‘s organ.   

213. Another expression which has been employed in Section 377 is  

‗against the order of nature‘. The phrase ‗against the order of nature‘  

has neither been defined in Section 377 IPC nor in any other  

provision of the IPC.  The foundation on which Section 377 IPC  

makes carnal intercourse an offence is the precept that such carnal  

intercourse is against the order of nature. This brings us to the  

important question as to what is ‗against the order of nature‘?  

214. In Khanu (supra), where the question before the Court was  

whether coitus per os (mouth contact with the male genitals) amounts  

to carnal intercourse against the order of nature, the Court ruled in  

the affirmative observing that the natural object of intercourse is that  

there should be the possibility of conception of human beings which  

                                                           84

Black’s Law Dictionary, 2 nd

edn.  

136

136  

in the case of coitus per os is impossible. Thus, the most common  

argument against homosexuality and criminalization of carnal  

intercourse even between consenting adults of opposite sex is that  

traditionally, the essential purpose of sex is to procreate.  

215. With the passage of time and evolution of the society,  

procreation is not the only reason for which people choose to come  

together, have live-in relationships, perform coitus or even marry.  

They do so for a whole lot of reasons including emotional  

companionship. Homer Clark writes:-  

―But the fact is that the most significant function of  marriage today seems to be that it furnishes emotional  satisfactions to be found in no other relationships. For  many people it is the refuge from the coldness and  impersonality of contemporary existence.‖    

216. In the contemporary world where even marriage is now not  

equated to procreation of children, the question that would arise is  

whether homosexuality and carnal intercourse between consenting  

adults of opposite sex can be tagged as ‗against the order of nature‘.  

It is the freedom of choice of two consenting adults to perform sex for  

procreation or otherwise and if their choice is that of the latter, it  

cannot be said to be against the order of nature. Therefore, sex, if  

performed differently, as per the choice of the consenting adults,

137

137  

does not per se make it against the order of nature.  

217. Section 377 criminalises even voluntary carnal intercourse not  

only between homosexuals but also between heterosexuals. The  

major difference between the language of Section 377 and Section  

375 is that of the element of absence consent which has been  

elaborately incorporated in the seven descriptions contained in the  

latter part of Section 375 IPC. It is the absence of willful and informed  

consent embodied in the seven descriptions to Section 375 which  

makes the offence of rape criminal.  

218.  On the other hand, Section 377 IPC contains no such  

descriptions/exceptions embodying the absence of willful and  

informed consent and criminalises even voluntary carnal intercourse  

both between homosexuals as well as between heterosexuals.  While  

saying so, we gain strength and support from the fact that the  

legislature, in its wisdom, while enacting Section 375 IPC in its  

amended form after the Criminal Law (Amendment) Act, 2013, has  

not employed the words ―subject to any other provision of the IPC‖.   

The implication of the absence of these words simply  indicates that  

Section 375 IPC which does not criminalize consensual carnal  

intercourse between heterosexuals is not subject to Section 377 IPC.

138

138  

219.  Section 377, so far as it criminalises carnal intercourse  

between heterosexuals is legally unsustainable in its present form for  

the simple reason that Section 375 IPC clearly stipulates that carnal  

intercourse between a man and a woman with the willful and  

informed consent of the woman does not amount to rape and is not  

penal.   

220. Despite the Criminal Law (Amendment) Act, 2013 coming into  

force, by virtue of which Section 375 was amended, whereby the  

words ‗sexual intercourse‘ in Section 375 were replaced by four  

elaborate clauses from (a) to (d) giving a wide definition to the  

offence of rape, Section 377 IPC still remains in the statute book in  

the same form. Such an anomaly, if allowed to persist, may result in a  

situation wherein a heterosexual couple who indulges in carnal  

intercourse with the willful and informed consent of each other may  

be held liable for the offence of unnatural sex under Section 377 IPC,  

despite the fact that such an act would not be rape within the  

definition as provided under Section 375 IPC.  

221. Drawing an analogy, if consensual carnal intercourse between  

a heterosexual couple does not amount to rape, it definitely should  

not be labelled and designated as unnatural offence under Section

139

139  

377 IPC. If any proclivity amongst the heterosexual population  

towards consensual carnal intercourse has been allowed due to the  

Criminal Law (Amendment) Act, 2013, such kind of proclivity amongst  

any two persons including LGBT community cannot be treated as  

untenable so long as it is consensual and it is confined within their  

most private and intimate spaces.   

222. There is another aspect which needs to be discussed, which is  

whether criminalisation of carnal intercourse under Section 377  

serves any useful purpose under the prevalent criminal law.  

Delineating on this aspect, the European Commission of Human  

Rights in Dudgeon (supra) opined thus:-  

―The 1967 Act, which was introduced into Parliament  as a Private Member‘s Bill, was passed to give effect  to the recommendations concerning homosexuality  made in 1957 in the report of the Departmental  Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution  established under the chairman ship of Sir John  Wolfenden (the ―Wolfenden Committee‖ and  ―Wolfenden report‖). The Wolfenden Committee  regarded the function of the criminal law in this field as:  

 ―to preserve public order and decency, to  protect the citizen from what is offensive  or  injurious, and to provide sufficient safeguards  against exploitation and corruption of  others,  particularly those who are specially vulnerable  because they are young, weak  in body or  mind, inexperienced, or in a state of special  physical, official, or economic  dependence‖,  

140

140  

but not     

―to intervene in the private lives of citizens, or  to seek to enforce any particular  pattern of  behaviour, further than is necessary to carry  out the purposes we have  outlined‖.  

 The Wolfenden Committee concluded that homosexual  behaviour between consenting adults in private was  part of the ―realm of private morality and immorality  which is, in brief and crude terms, not the law‘s  business‖ and should no longer be criminal‖  

[Underlining is ours]  

223. At the very least, it can be said that criminalisation of  

consensual carnal intercourse, be it amongst homosexuals,  

heterosexuals, bi-sexuals or transgenders, hardly serves any  

legitimate public purpose or interest. Per contra, we are inclined to  

believe that if Section 377 remains in its present form in the statute  

book, it will allow the harassment and exploitation of the LGBT  

community to prevail. We must make it clear that freedom of choice  

cannot be scuttled or abridged on the threat of criminal prosecution  

and made paraplegic on the mercurial stance of majoritarian  

perception.    

P.  The litmus test for survival of Section 377 IPC    224.  Having discussed the various principles and concepts and  

bearing in mind the sacrosanctity of the fundamental rights which

141

141  

guides the constitutional courts, we shall now proceed to deal with  

the constitutionality of Section 377 IPC on the bedrock of the  

principles enunciated in Articles 14, 19 and 21 of the Constitution.  

225. It is axiomatic that the expression ‗life or personal liberty‘ in  

Article 21 embodies within itself a variety of rights. In Maneka  

Gandhi (supra), Bhagwati, J. (as he then was) observed:-  

―The expression 'personal liberty' in Article 21 is of the  widest amplitude and it covers a variety of rights which  go to constitute the personal liberty of man and some  of them have been raised to the status of distinct  fundamental rights and given additional protection  under Article 19...‖    

226. In Anuj Garg (supra), while dealing with the constitutional  

validity of Section 30 of the Punjab Excise Act, 1914 prohibiting  

employment of ―any man under the age of 25 years‖ or ―any woman‖,   

the Court, holding it ultra vires, ruled thus:-   

―31. … It is their life; subject to constitutional, statutory  and social interdicts—a citizen of India should be  allowed to live her life on her own terms.‖  

  And again:-   

―35. Privacy rights prescribe autonomy to choose  profession whereas security concerns texture  methodology of delivery of this assurance. But it is a  reasonable proposition that the measures to safeguard  such a guarantee of autonomy should not be so strong

142

142  

that the essence of the guarantee is lost. State  protection must not translate into censorship.‖     

227. In Common Cause (A Regd. Society) (supra), the Court,  in  

the context of right to dignity, observed:-   

―Right to life and liberty as envisaged under Article 21  is meaningless unless it encompasses within its  sphere individual dignity and right to dignity includes  the right to carry such functions and activities as would  constitute the meaningful expression of the human  self.‖    

228. In Puttaswamy (supra), the right to privacy has been declared  

to be a fundamental right by this Court as being a facet of life and  

personal liberty protected under Article 21 of the Constitution.   

229. In view of the above authorities, we have no hesitation to say  

that Section 377 IPC, in its present form, abridges both human dignity  

as well as the fundamental right to privacy and choice of the citizenry,  

howsoever small.  As sexual orientation is an essential and innate  

facet of privacy, the right to privacy takes within its sweep the right of  

every individual including that of the LGBT to express their choices in  

terms of sexual inclination without the fear of persecution or criminal  

prosecution.  

230.  The sexual autonomy of an individual to choose his/her sexual  

partner is an important pillar and an insegregable facet of individual

143

143  

liberty. When the liberty of even a single person of the society is  

smothered under some vague and archival stipulation that it is  

against the order of nature or under the perception that the majority  

population is peeved when such an individual exercises his/her liberty  

despite the fact that  the exercise of such liberty is within the confines  

of his/her private space, then the signature of life melts and living  

becomes a bare subsistence and resultantly, the fundamental right of  

liberty of such an individual is abridged.   

231.  While saying so, we are absolutely conscious of the fact that  

the citizenry may be deprived of their right to life and personal liberty  

if the conditions laid down in Article 21 are fulfilled and if, at the same  

time, the procedure established by law as laid down in Maneka  

Gandhi (supra) is satisfied. Article 21 requires that for depriving a  

person of his right to life and personal liberty, there has to be a law  

and the said law must prescribe a fair procedure.  The seminal point  

is to see whether Section 377 withstands the sanctity of dignity of an  

individual, expression of choice, paramount concept of life and  

whether it allows an individual to lead to a life that one‘s natural  

orientation commands.  That apart, more importantly, the question is  

whether such a gender-neutral offence, with the efflux of time, should

144

144  

be allowed to remain in the statute book especially when there is  

consent and such consent elevates the status of bodily autonomy.  

Hence, the provision has to be tested on the principles evolved under  

Articles 14, 19 and 21 of the Constitution.  

232. In Sunil Batra v. Delhi Administration and others85, Krishna  

Iyer, J. opined that what is punitively outrageous, scandalizingly  

unusual or cruel and rehabilitatively counterproductive, is unarguably  

unreasonable and arbitrary and is shot down by Article 14 and 19 and  

if inflicted with procedural unfairness, falls foul of Article 21.  

233. We, first, must test the validity of Section 377 IPC on the anvil  

of Article 14 of the Constitution. What Article 14 propounds is that ‗all  

like should be treated alike‘. In other words, it implies equal treatment  

for all equals. Though the legislature is fully empowered to enact laws  

applicable to a particular class, as in the case at hand in which  

Section 377 applies to citizens who indulge in carnal intercourse, yet  

the classification, including the one made under Section 377 IPC, has  

to satisfy the twin conditions to the effect that the classification must  

be founded on an intelligible differentia and the said differentia must  

                                                           85AIR 1978 SC 1675 : (1978) 4 SCC 494

145

145  

have a rational nexus with the object sought to be achieved by the  

provision, that is, Section 377 IPC.   

234. In M. Nagaraj and others v. Union of India and others86, it  

has been held:-  

―The gravamen of Article 14 is equality of treatment.  Article 14 confers a personal right by enacting a  prohibition which is absolute. By judicial decisions, the  doctrine of classification is read into Article 14. Equality  of treatment under Article 14 is an objective test. It is  not the test of intention. Therefore, the basic principle  underlying Article 14 is that the law must operate  equally on all persons under like circumstances.‖  

 235. In E.P. Royappa v. State of Tamil Nadu and another87, this  

Court observed that equality is a dynamic concept with many aspects  

and dimensions and it cannot be "cribbed, cabined and confined"  

within traditional and doctrinaire limits. It was further held that equality  

is antithetic to arbitrariness, for equality and arbitrariness are sworn  

enemies; one belongs to the rule of law in a republic while the other,  

to the whim and caprice of an absolute monarch.  

236. In Budhan Choudhry v. The State of Bihar 88 , while  

delineating on the concept of reasonable classification, the Court  

observed thus:-  

                                                           86

AIR 2007 SC 71 : (2006) 8 SCC 212  87

AIR 1974 SC 555 : (1974) 4 SCC 3  88

AIR 1955 SC 191

146

146  

―It is now well-established that while article 14 forbids  class legislation, it does not forbid reasonable  classification for the purposes of legislation. In order,  however, to pass the test of permissible classification  two conditions must be fulfilled, namely, (i) that the  classification must be founded on an intelligible  differentia which distinguishes persons or things that  are grouped together from others left out of the group  and (ii) that differentia must have a rational relation to  the object sought to be achieved by the statute in  question. The classification may be founded on  different bases; namely, geographical, or according to  objects or occupations or the like. What is necessary is  that there must be a nexus between the basis of  classification and the object of the Act under  consideration. It is also well established by the  decisions of this Court that article 14 condemns  discrimination not only by a substantive law but also by  a law of procedure.‖    

237.  A perusal of Section 377 IPC reveals that it classifies and  

penalizes persons who indulge in carnal intercourse with the object to  

protect women and children from being subjected to carnal  

intercourse.  That being so, now it is to be ascertained whether this  

classification has a reasonable nexus with the object sought to be  

achieved.  The answer is in the negative as the non-consensual acts  

which have been criminalized by virtue of Section 377 IPC have  

already been designated as penal offences under Section 375 IPC  

and under the POCSO Act. Per contra, the presence of this Section  

in its present form has resulted in a distasteful and objectionable

147

147  

collateral effect whereby even ‗consensual acts‘, which are neither  

harmful to children nor women and are performed by a certain class  

of people (LGBTs) owning to some inherent characteristics defined  

by their identity and individuality, have been woefully targeted. This  

discrimination and unequal treatment meted out to the LGBT  

community as a separate class of citizens is unconstitutional for being  

violative of Article 14 of the Constitution.   

238. In Shayara Bano (supra), the Court observed that manifest  

arbitrariness of a provision of law can also be a ground for declaring a  

law as unconstitutional. Opining so, the Court observed thus:-  

―The test of manifest arbitrariness, therefore, as laid  down in the aforesaid judgments would apply to  invalidate legislation as well as subordinate legislation  under Article 14. Manifest arbitrariness, therefore, must  be something done by the legislature capriciously,  irrationally and/or without adequate determining  principle. Also, when something is done which is  excessive and disproportionate, such legislation would  be manifestly arbitrary. We are, therefore, of the view  that arbitrariness in the sense of manifest arbitrariness  as pointed out by us above would apply to negate  legislation as well under Article 14.‖    

239.  In view of the law laid down in Shayara Bano (supra) and  

given the fact that Section 377 criminalises even consensual sexual  

acts between adults, it fails to make a distinction between  

consensual and non-consensual sexual acts between competent

148

148  

adults. Further, Section 377 IPC fails to take into account that  

consensual sexual acts between adults in private space are neither  

harmful nor contagious to the society. On the contrary, Section 377  

trenches a discordant note in respect of the liberty of persons  

belonging to the LGBT community by subjecting them to societal  

pariah and dereliction. Needless to say, the Section also interferes  

with consensual acts of competent adults in private space. Sexual  

acts cannot be viewed from the lens of social morality or that of  

traditional precepts wherein sexual acts were considered only for the  

purpose of procreation. This being the case, Section 377 IPC, so  

long as it criminalises consensual sexual acts of whatever nature  

between competent adults, is manifestly arbitrary.  

240.  The LGBT community possess the same human, fundamental  

and constitutional rights as other citizens do since these rights inhere  

in individuals as natural and human rights. We must remember that  

equality is the edifice on which the entire non-discrimination  

jurisprudence rests. Respect for individual choice is the very essence  

of liberty under law and, thus, criminalizing carnal intercourse under  

Section 377 IPC is irrational, indefensible and manifestly arbitrary.  It  

is true that the principle of choice can never be absolute under a

149

149  

liberal Constitution and the law restricts one individual‘s choice to  

prevent harm or injury to others. However, the organisation of  

intimate relations is a matter of complete personal choice especially  

between consenting adults. It is a vital personal right falling within the  

private protective sphere and realm of individual choice and  

autonomy. Such progressive proclivity is rooted in the constitutional  

structure and is an inextricable part of human nature.   

241. In the adverting situation, we must also examine whether  

Section 377, in its present form, stands the test of Article 19 of the  

Constitution in the sense of whether it is unreasonable and, therefore,  

violative of Article 19. In Chintaman Rao v. State of Madhya  

Pradesh89, this Court, in the context of reasonable restrictions under  

Article 19, opined thus:-  

"The phrase "reasonable restriction" connotes that the  limitation imposed on a person in enjoyment of the  right should not be arbitrary or of an excessive nature,  beyond what is required in the interests of the public.  The word "reasonable" implies intelligent care and  deliberation, that is, the choice of a course which  reason dictates. Legislation which arbitrarily or  excessively invades the right cannot be said to contain  the quality of reasonableness and unless it strikes a  proper balance between the freedom guaranteed in  article 19(1)(g) and the social control permitted by  

                                                           89

AIR 1951 SC 118

150

150  

clause (6) of article 19, it must be held to be wanting in  that quality."    

242. In S. Rangarajan v. P. Jagjivan Ram and others90, the Court  

observed, though in a different context, thus:-  

" ... Our commitment of freedom of expression  demands that it cannot be suppressed unless the  situations created by allowing the freedom are  pressing and the community interest is endangered.  The anticipated danger should not be remote,  conjectural or far-fetched. It should have proximate  and direct nexus with the expression.‖    

243. In S. Khushboo (supra), this Court, while observing that  

‗morality and decency‘ on the basis of which reasonable restrictions  

can be imposed on the rights guaranteed under Article 19 should not  

be amplified  beyond a rational and logical limit, ruled that even  

though the constitutional freedom of speech and expression is not  

absolute and can be subjected to reasonable restrictions on grounds  

such as `decency and morality' among others, yet it is necessary to  

tolerate unpopular views in the socio-cultural space.  

244. In the case of Shreya Singhal v. Union of India91, this Court,  

while striking down Section 66A of the Information Technology Act,  

2000, had observed that when a provision is vague and overboard in  

                                                           90

(1989) 2 SCC 574  91

(2015) 5 SCC 1

151

151  

the sense that it criminalises protected speech and speech of  

innocent nature, resultantly, it has a chilling effect and is liable to be  

struck down. The Court opined:-   

―We, therefore, hold that the Section is unconstitutional  also on the ground that it takes within its sweep  protected speech and speech that is innocent in nature  and is liable therefore to be used in such a way as to  have a chilling effect on free speech and would,  therefore, have to be struck down on the ground of  overbreadth.‖    

245. In the obtaining situation, we need to check whether public  

order, decency and morality as grounds to limit the fundamental right  

of expression including choice can be accepted as reasonable  

restrictions to uphold the validity of Section 377 IPC. We are of the  

conscious view that Section 377 IPC takes within its fold private acts  

of adults including the LGBT community which are not only  

consensual but are also innocent, as such acts neither cause  

disturbance to the public order nor are they injurious to public  

decency or morality. The law is et domus sua cuique est tutissimum  

refugium – A man‘s house is his castle. Sir Edward Coke92 said:-  

―The house of everyone is to him as his castle and  fortress, as well for his defence against injury and  violence as for his repose.‖    

                                                           92

Semayne’s Case, 77 Eng. Rep. 194, 195; 5 Co. Rep. 91, 195 (K.B. 1604)

152

152  

246. That apart, any display of affection amongst the members  of  

the LGBT community towards their partners in the public so long as it  

does not amount to indecency or has the potentiality to disturb public  

order cannot be bogged down by majority perception. Section 377  

IPC amounts to unreasonable restriction as it makes carnal  

intercourse between consenting adults within their castle a criminal  

offence which is manifestly not only overboard and vague but also  

has a chilling effect on an individual‘s freedom of choice.   

247.  In view of the test laid down in the aforesaid authorities, Section  

377 IPC does not meet the criteria of proportionality and is violative of  

the fundamental right of freedom of expression including the right to  

choose a sexual partner. Section 377 IPC also assumes the  

characteristic of unreasonableness, for it becomes a weapon in the  

hands of the majority to seclude, exploit and harass the LGBT  

community. It shrouds the lives of the LGBT community in criminality  

and constant fear mars their joy of life. They constantly face social  

prejudice, disdain and are subjected to the shame of being their very  

natural selves. Thus, an archaic law which is incompatible with  

constitutional values cannot be allowed to be preserved.   

248. Bigoted and homophobic attitudes dehumanize the

153

153  

transgenders by denying them their dignity, personhood and above  

all, their basic human rights. It is important to realize that identity and  

sexual orientation cannot be silenced by oppression. Liberty, as the  

linchpin of our constitutional values, enables individuals to define and  

express their identity and individual identity has to be acknowledged  

and respected.  

249.  The very existence of Section 377 IPC criminalising  

transgenders casts a great stigma on an already oppressed and  

discriminated class of people. This stigma, oppression and prejudice  

has to be eradicated and the transgenders have to progress from  

their narrow claustrophobic spaces of mere survival in hiding with  

their isolation and fears to enjoying the richness of living out of the  

shadows with full realization of their potential and equal opportunities  

in all walks of life. The ideals and objectives enshrined in our  

benevolent Constitution can be achieved only when each and every  

individual is empowered and enabled to participate in the social  

mainstream and in the journey towards achieving equality in all  

spheres, equality of opportunities in all walks of life, equal freedoms  

and rights and, above all, equitable justice.  This can be achieved  

only by inclusion of all and exclusion of none from the mainstream.

154

154  

250.  We must realize that different hues and colours together make  

the painting of humanity beautiful and this beauty is the essence of  

humanity.  We need to respect the strength of our diversity so as to  

sustain our unity as a cohesive unit of free citizens by fostering  

tolerance and respect for each others‘ rights thereby progressing  

towards harmonious and peaceful co-existence in the supreme bond  

of humanity. Attitudes and mentality have to change to accept the  

distinct identity of individuals and respect them for who they are  

rather than compelling them to ‗become‘ who they are not. All human  

beings possess the equal right to be themselves instead of  

transitioning or conditioning themselves as per the perceived  

dogmatic notions of a group of people. To change the societal bias  

and root out the weed, it is the foremost duty of each one of us to  

―stand up and speak up‖ against the slightest form of discrimination  

against transgenders that we come across. Let us move from  

darkness to light, from bigotry to tolerance and from the winter of  

mere survival to the spring of life ― as the herald of a New India ― to  

a more inclusive society.  

251. It is through times of grave disappointment, denunciation,  

adversity,  grief, injustice and despair that the transgenders have

155

155  

stood firm with their formidable spirit, inspired commitment, strong  

determination and infinite hope and  belief that has made them look  

for the rainbow in every cloud and lead the way to a future that would  

be the harbinger of liberation and emancipation from a certain  

bondage indescribable in words – towards the basic recognition of  

dignity and humanity of all and towards leading a life without pretence  

eschewing duality and ambivalence. It is their momentous ―walk to  

freedom‖ and journey to a constitutional ethos of dignity, equality and  

liberty and this freedom can only be fulfilled in its truest sense when  

each of us realize that the LGBT community possess equal rights as  

any other citizen in the country under the magnificent charter of rights  

– our Constitution.   

252.  Thus analysed, Section 377 IPC, so far as it penalizes any  

consensual sexual activity between two adults, be it homosexuals  

(man and a man), heterosexuals (man and a woman) and lesbians  

(woman and a woman), cannot be regarded as constitutional.  

However, if anyone, by which we mean both a man and a woman,  

engages in any kind of sexual activity with an animal, the said aspect  

of Section 377 IPC is constitutional and it shall remain a penal  

offence under Section 377 IPC. Any act of the description covered

156

156  

under Section 377 IPC done between the individuals without the  

consent of any one of them would invite penal liability under Section  

377 IPC.  

Q. Conclusions  

253. In view of the aforesaid analysis, we record our conclusions in  

seriatim:-  

(i) The eminence of identity which has been luculently stated in  

the NALSA case very aptly connects human rights and the  

constitutional guarantee of right to life and liberty with dignity.  

With the same spirit, we must recognize that the concept of  

identity which has a constitutional tenability cannot be  

pigeon-holed singularly to one‘s orientation as it may keep  

the individual choice at bay. At the core of the concept of  

identity lies self-determination, realization of one‘s own  

abilities visualizing the opportunities and rejection of external  

views with a clear conscience that is in accord with  

constitutional norms and values or principles that are, to put  

in a capsule, ―constitutionally permissible‖.   

(ii) In Suresh Koushal (supra), this Court overturned the  

decision of the Delhi High Court in Naz Foundation (supra)

157

157  

thereby upholding the constitutionality of Section 377 IPC  

and stating a ground that the LGBT community comprised  

only a minuscule fraction of the total population and that the  

mere fact that the said Section was being misused is not a  

reflection of the vires of the Section. Such a view is  

constitutionally impermissible.    

(iii) Our Constitution is a living and organic document capable of  

expansion with the changing needs and demands of the  

society. The Courts must commemorate that it is the  

Constitution and its golden principles to which they bear their  

foremost allegiance and they must robe themselves with the  

armoury of progressive and pragmatic interpretation to  

combat the evils of inequality and injustice that try to creep  

into the society. The role of the Courts gains more  

importance when the rights which are affected belong to a  

class of persons or a minority group who have been  

deprived of even their basic rights since time immemorial.      

(iv) The primary objective of having a constitutional democracy  

is to transform the society progressively and inclusively. Our  

Constitution has been perceived to be transformative in the

158

158  

sense that the interpretation of its provisions should not be  

limited to the mere literal meaning of its words; instead they  

ought to be given a meaningful construction which is  

reflective of their intent and purpose in consonance with the  

changing times. Transformative constitutionalism not only  

includes within its wide periphery the recognition of the rights  

and dignity of individuals but also propagates the fostering  

and development of an atmosphere wherein every individual  

is bestowed with adequate opportunities to develop socially,  

economically and politically. Discrimination of any kind  

strikes at the very core of any democratic society. When  

guided by transformative constitutionalism, the society is  

dissuaded from indulging in any form of discrimination so  

that the nation is guided towards a resplendent future.    

(v) Constitutional morality embraces within its sphere several  

virtues, foremost of them being the espousal of a pluralistic  

and inclusive society. The concept of constitutional morality  

urges the organs of the State, including the Judiciary, to  

preserve the heterogeneous nature of the society and to  

curb any attempt by the majority to usurp the rights and

159

159  

freedoms of a smaller or minuscule section of the populace.  

Constitutional morality cannot be martyred at the altar of  

social morality and it is only constitutional morality that can  

be allowed to permeate into the Rule of Law.  The veil of  

social morality cannot be used to violate fundamental rights  

of even a single individual, for the foundation of  

constitutional morality rests upon the recognition of diversity  

that pervades the society.  

(vi) The right to live with dignity has been recognized as a  

human right on the international front and by number of  

precedents of this Court and, therefore, the constitutional  

courts must strive to protect the dignity of every individual,  

for without the right to dignity, every other right would be  

rendered meaningless. Dignity is an inseparable facet of  

every individual that invites reciprocative respect from others  

to every aspect of an individual which he/she perceives as  

an essential attribute of his/her individuality, be it an  

orientation or an optional expression of choice. The  

Constitution has ladened the judiciary with the very important  

duty to protect and ensure the right of every individual

160

160  

including the right to express and choose without any  

impediments so as to enable an individual to fully realize  

his/her fundamental right to live with dignity.   

(vii) Sexual orientation is one of the many biological phenomena  

which is natural and inherent in an individual and is  

controlled by neurological and biological factors. The science  

of sexuality has theorized that an individual exerts little or no  

control over who he/she gets attracted to. Any discrimination  

on the basis of one‘s sexual orientation would entail a  

violation of the fundamental right of freedom of expression.   

(viii) After the privacy judgment in Puttaswamy (supra), the right  

to privacy has been raised to the pedestal of a fundamental  

right. The reasoning in Suresh Koushal (supra), that only a  

minuscule fraction of the total population comprises of LGBT  

community and that the existence of Section 377 IPC  

abridges the fundamental rights of a very minuscule  

percentage of the total populace, is found to be a discordant  

note.  The said reasoning in Suresh Koushal (supra), in our  

opinion, is fallacious, for the framers of our Constitution  

could have never intended that the fundamental rights shall

161

161  

be extended for the benefit of the majority only and that the  

Courts ought to interfere only when the fundamental rights of  

a large percentage of the total populace is affected. In fact,  

the said view would be completely against the constitutional  

ethos, for the language employed in Part III of the  

Constitution as well as the intention of the framers of our  

Constitution mandates that the Courts must step in  

whenever there is a violation of the fundamental rights, even  

if the right/s of a single individual is/are in peril.   

(ix) There is a manifest ascendance of rights under the  

Constitution which paves the way for the doctrine of  

progressive realization of rights as such rights evolve with  

the evolution of the society. This doctrine, as a natural  

corollary, gives birth to the doctrine of non-retrogression, as  

per which there must not be atavism of constitutional rights.  

In the light of the same, if we were to accept the view in  

Suresh Koushal (supra), it would tantamount to a  

retrograde step in the direction of the progressive  

interpretation of the Constitution and denial of progressive  

realization of rights.

162

162  

(x) Autonomy is individualistic. Under the autonomy principle,  

the individual has sovereignty over his/her body. He/she can  

surrender his/her autonomy wilfully to another individual and  

their intimacy in privacy is a matter of their choice.  Such  

concept of identity is not only sacred but is also in  

recognition of the quintessential facet of humanity in a  

person‘s nature. The autonomy establishes identity and the  

said identity, in the ultimate eventuate, becomes a part of  

dignity in an individual.  

(xi) A cursory reading of both Sections 375 IPC and 377 IPC  

reveals that although the former Section gives due  

recognition to the absence of ‗wilful and informed consent‘  

for an act to be termed as rape, per contra, Section 377  

does not contain any such qualification embodying in itself  

the absence of ‗wilful and informed consent‘ to criminalize  

carnal intercourse which consequently results in  

criminalizing even voluntary carnal intercourse between  

homosexuals, heterosexuals, bisexuals and transgenders.  

Section 375 IPC, after the coming into force of the Criminal  

Law (Amendment) Act, 2013, has not used the words

163

163  

‗subject to any other provision of the IPC‘. This indicates that  

Section 375 IPC is not subject to Section 377 IPC.  

(xii) The expression ‗against the order of nature‘ has neither  

been defined in Section 377 IPC nor in any other provision of  

the IPC. The connotation given to the expression by various  

judicial pronouncements includes all sexual acts which are  

not intended for the purpose of procreation. Therefore, if  

coitus is not performed for procreation only, it does not per  

se make it ‗against the order of nature‘.  

(xiii) Section 377 IPC, in its present form, being violative of the  

right to dignity and the right to privacy, has to be tested, both,  

on the pedestal of Articles 14 and 19 of the Constitution as  

per the law laid down in Maneka Gandhi (supra) and other  

later authorities.   

(xiv) An examination of Section 377 IPC on the anvil of Article 14  

of the Constitution reveals that the classification adopted  

under the said Section has no reasonable nexus with its  

object as other penal provisions such as Section 375 IPC  

and the POCSO Act already penalize non-consensual carnal  

intercourse. Per contra, Section 377 IPC in its present form

164

164  

has resulted in an unwanted collateral effect whereby even  

‗consensual sexual acts‘, which are neither harmful to  

children nor women, by the LGBTs have been woefully  

targeted thereby resulting in discrimination and unequal  

treatment to the LGBT community and is, thus, violative of  

Article 14 of the Constitution.   

(xv) Section 377 IPC, so far as it criminalises even consensual  

sexual acts between competent adults, fails to make a  

distinction between non-consensual and consensual sexual  

acts of competent adults in private space which are neither  

harmful nor contagious to the society. Section 377 IPC  

subjects the LGBT community to societal pariah and  

dereliction and is, therefore, manifestly arbitrary, for it has  

become an odious weapon for the harassment of the LGBT  

community by subjecting them to discrimination and unequal  

treatment.  Therefore, in view of the law laid down in  

Shayara Bano (supra), Section 377 IPC is liable to be  

partially struck down for being violative of Article 14 of the  

Constitution.  

165

165  

(xvi) An examination of Section 377 IPC on the anvil of Article  

19(1)(a) reveals that it amounts to an unreasonable  

restriction, for public decency and morality cannot be  

amplified beyond a rational or logical limit and cannot be  

accepted as reasonable grounds for curbing the fundamental  

rights of freedom of expression and choice of the LGBT  

community. Consensual carnal intercourse among adults, be  

it homosexual or heterosexual, in private space, does not in  

any way harm the public decency or morality. Therefore,  

Section 377 IPC in its present form violates Article 19(1)(a)  

of the Constitution.  

(xvii) Ergo, Section 377 IPC, so far as it penalizes any consensual  

sexual relationship between two adults, be it homosexuals  

(man and a man), heterosexuals (man and a woman) or  

lesbians (woman and a woman), cannot be regarded as  

constitutional.  However, if anyone, by which we mean both  

a man and a woman, engages in any kind of sexual activity  

with an animal, the said aspect of Section 377 is  

constitutional and it shall remain a penal offence under  

Section 377 IPC.  Any act of the description covered under

166

166  

Section 377 IPC done between two individuals without the  

consent of any one of them would invite penal liability under  

Section 377 IPC.  

(xviii) The decision in Suresh Koushal (supra), not being in  

consonance with what we have stated hereinabove, is  

overruled.    

254. The Writ Petitions are, accordingly, disposed of.  There shall be  

no order as to costs.  

      ……………………………….CJI        (Dipak Misra)                   …………………………….…..J.        (A.M. Khanwilkar)     New Delhi;  September 6, 2018   

167

1  

 

REPORTABLE  

 IN THE SUPREME COURT OF INDIA  

 CRIMINAL/CIVIL ORIGINAL JURISDICTION  

 WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO. 76 OF 2016  

   

NAVTEJ SINGH JOHAR & ORS.     …PETITIONERS    

VERSUS    

UNION OF INDIA      …RESPONDENT    

WITH  

WRIT PETITION (CIVIL) NO.572 OF 2016  

WITH  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO.88 OF 2018  

WITH  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO.100 OF 2018  

WITH  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO.101 OF 2018  

WITH  

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO.121 OF 2018  

 

 

 

 

 

 

168

2  

 

J U D G M E N T  

 

R.F. Nariman, J.    

1. “The love that dare not speak its name” is how the love  

that exists between same-sex couples was described by Lord  

Alfred Douglas, the lover of Oscar Wilde, in his poem Two  

Loves published in 1894 in Victorian England.  

2. The word “homosexual” is not derived from “homo”  

meaning man, but from “homo” meaning same.1 The word  

“lesbian” is derived from the name of the Greek island of  

Lesbos, where it was rumored that female same-sex couples  

proliferated. What we have before us is a relook at the  

constitutional validity of Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code  

which was enacted in the year 1860 (over 150 years ago)  

insofar as it criminalises consensual sex between adult same-

sex couples.    

3. These cases have had a chequered history. Writ petitions  

were filed before the Delhi High Court challenging the  

                                                           1 Homo in Greek means ‘same’ – the Nicene creed that was accepted by the Catholic Church after the  Council at Nicaea, held by Emperor Constantine in 325 AD, was formulated with the word ‘homo’ at the  forefront.  When coupled with ‘sios’ it means same substance, meaning thereby that Jesus Christ was  divine as he was of the same substance as God.  

169

3  

 

constitutional validity of Section 377 of the Penal Code insofar  

as it criminalizes consensual sex between adult same-sex  

couples within the confines of their homes or other private  

places.  A Division Bench of the Delhi High Court in Naz  

Foundation v. Government of NCT of Delhi (“Naz  

Foundation”), 111 DRJ 1 (2009), after considering wide-

ranging arguments on both sides, finally upheld the plea of the  

petitioners in the following words:  

“132. We declare that Section 377 IPC, insofar it  criminalises consensual sexual acts of adults in  private, is violative of Articles 21, 14 and 15 of the  Constitution. The provisions of Section 377 IPC will  continue to govern non-consensual penile non- vaginal sex and penile non-vaginal sex involving  minors. By ‘adult’ we mean everyone who is 18  years of age and above. A person below 18 would  be presumed not to be able to consent to a sexual  act. This clarification will hold till, of course,  Parliament chooses to amend the law to effectuate  the recommendation of the Law Commission of  India in its 172nd Report which we believe removes  a great deal of confusion. Secondly, we clarify that  our judgment will not result in the re-opening of  criminal cases involving Section 377 IPC that have  already attained finality.   We allow the writ petition in the above terms.”  

  

4. Despite the fact that no appeal was filed by the Union of  

India, in appeals filed by private individuals and groups, the

170

4  

 

Supreme Court in Suresh Kumar Koushal and Anr. v. Naz  

Foundation and Ors. (“Suresh Kumar Koushal”), (2014) 1  

SCC 1, reversed the judgment of the High Court. Reviews that  

were filed against the aforesaid judgment, including by the  

Union of India, were dismissed by this Court.    

5. Meanwhile, the Supreme Court delivered an important  

judgment reported as National Legal Services Authority v.  

Union of India (“NALSA”), (2014) 5 SCC 438, which  

construed Articles 15 and 21 of the Constitution of India as  

including the right to gender identity and sexual orientation, and  

held that just like men and women, transgenders could enjoy all  

the fundamental rights that other citizens of India could enjoy.   

Thereafter, in Justice K.S. Puttaswamy (Retd.) and Anr. v.  

Union of India and Ors. (“Puttaswamy”), (2017) 10 SCC 1, a  

nine-Judge Bench of this Court unanimously declared that there  

is a fundamental right of privacy which enured in favour of all  

persons, the concomitant of which was that the right to make  

choices that were fundamental to a person’s way of living could  

not be interfered with by the State without compelling necessity  

and/or harm caused to other individuals.   

171

5  

 

6. The impetus of this decision is what led to a three-Judge  

Bench order of 08.01.2018, which referred to the judgment of  

Puttaswamy (supra) and other arguments made by Shri Datar,  

to refer the correctness of Suresh Kumar Koushal’s case  

(supra) to a larger Bench. This is how the matter has come to  

us.  

History of Section 377   

7. In the western world, given the fact that both Judaism and  

Christianity outlawed sexual intercourse by same-sex couples,  

offences relating thereto were decided by ecclesiastical courts.  

It is only as a result of Henry VIII of England breaking with the  

Roman Catholic Church that legislation in his reign, namely the  

Buggery Act of 1533, prohibited “the detestable and  

abominable offence” of buggery committed with mankind or  

beast.   

8. Between 1806, when reliable figures begin, and 1900,  

8,921 men were indicted for sodomy, gross indecency or other  

‘unnatural misdemeanours’ in England and Wales. Ninety men  

per year were, on average, indicted for homosexual offences in

172

6  

 

this period. About a third as many were arrested and their case  

considered by magistrates. Most of the men convicted were  

imprisoned, but between 1806 and 1861, when the death  

penalty for sodomy was finally abolished, 404 men were  

sentenced to death. Fifty-six were executed, and the remainder  

were either imprisoned or transported to Australia for life. Two  

such men, James Pratt and John Smith, were the last to be  

executed in Britain for sodomy on 27 November, 1835.  

9. During the reign of the East India Company in India,  

Parliament established what was called the Indian Law  

Commission. In 1833, Thomas Babington Macaulay was  

appointed to chair the Commission.2    

10. The Indian Law Commission, with Macaulay as its head,  

submitted the Draft Penal Code to the Government of India on  

14.10.1837.  This draft consisted of 488 clauses.  After the First  

Report submitted on 23.07.1846, the Second Report of Her  

Majesty’s Commissioners for revising and consolidating the law  

was submitted by C.H. Cameron and D. Eliott on 24.06.1847.                                                              2 Thomas Babington Macaulay was a Whig liberal who was a precocious genius. Apart from having a  photographic memory with which he astounded persons around him, one incident which took place when  Macaulay was only 5 years old told the world what was in store for it when Macaulay would reach  adulthood. A lady dropped some hot coffee on the five-year old child and expressed great sorrow for  doing so. The child riposted, after letting out a scream, “Madam, the agony has abated”.   

173

7  

 

These Commissioners concluded that the Draft Penal Code  

was sufficiently complete, and, with slight modifications, fit to be  

acted upon. The revised edition of the Penal Code was then  

forwarded to the Judges of the Supreme Court at Calcutta on  

30.05.1851, and also to the Judges of the Sudder Court at  

Calcutta.   

11. The revised edition of the Penal Code as prepared by Mr.  

Bethune, the Legislative member of the Legislative Council of  

India, together with the views of the Chief Justice and Mr.  

Justice Buller of the Supreme Court at Calcutta, as well as  

those of Mr. Justice Colvile were sent to the Company in  

London.  The Court of Directors in London were anxious to see  

the Penal Code enacted as early as possible. They, therefore,  

constituted a Council in which Sir Barnes Peacock was made  

the fourth member.   

12. This Council or Committee prepared a revised Penal  

Code which was then referred to a Select Committee in 1857.  

Given the Indian Mutiny of 1857, the Code was passed soon  

thereafter in October, 1860 and brought into force on  

01.01.1862. Sir James Fitzjames Stephen proclaimed that:

174

8  

 

“The Indian Penal Code is to the English criminal  law what a manufactured article ready for use is to  the materials out of which it is made. It is to the  French Penal Code and, I may add, to the North  Germany Code of 1871, what a finished picture is to  a sketch. It is far simpler, and much better  expressed, than Livingston’s Code for Louisiana;  and its practical success has been complete”.     

13. He further described the Penal Code as:-  

“the criminal law of England freed from all  technicalities and superfluities, systematically  arranged and modified in some few particulars (they  are surprisingly few), to suit circumstances of British  India.”     

14. According to Lord Macaulay, a good Code should have  

the qualities of precision and comprehensibility. In a letter to  

Lord Auckland, the Governor General of India in Council, which  

accompanied his draft Penal Code, he stated:  

“There are two things which a legislator should  always have in view while he is framing laws: the  one is that they should be as far as possible  precise; the other that they should be easily  understood. That a law, and especially a penal law,  should be drawn in words which convey no meaning  to the people who are to obey it, is an evil. On the  other hand, a loosely worded law is no law, and to  whatever extent a legislature uses vague  expressions, to that extent it abdicates its functions,  and resigns the power of making law to the Courts  of Justice.”  

175

9  

 

15. Stung to the quick, when criticized as to the delay in  

bringing out the Code, he observed in a Minute to Lord  

Auckland as follows:   

“…when I remember the slow progress of law  reforms at home and when I consider that our Code  decides hundreds of questions… every one of which  if stirred in England would give occasion to  voluminous controversy and to many animated  debates, I must acknowledge that I am inclined to  fear that we have been guilty rather of precipitation  than of delay.”   

 

16. Earlier, he had described the core objective of his project  

in his 04.06.1835 Minute to the Council which could be  

paraphrased as follows:-  

It should be more than a mere digest of existing  laws, covering all contingencies, and ‘nothing that is  not in the Code ought to be law’.  

It should suppress crime with the least infliction of  suffering and allow for the ascertaining of the truth  at the smallest possible cost of time and money.  

Its language should be clear, unequivocal and  concise. Every criminal act should be separately  defined, its language followed precisely in  indictment and conduct found to fall clearly within  the definition.  

Uniformity was to be the chief end and special  definitions, procedures or other exceptions to  account for different races or sects should not be  included without clear and strong reasons.

176

10  

 

 

17. It is interesting to note that Lord Macaulay’s Draft was  

substantially different from what was enacted as Section 377.   

Macaulay’s original draft read:-  

“361. Whoever, intending to gratify unnatural lust,  touches for that purpose any person, or any animal,  or is by his own consent touched by any person, for  the purpose of gratifying unnatural lust, shall be  punished with imprisonment of either description for  a term which may extend to fourteen years and  must not be less than two years, and shall be liable  to fine.   

362. Whoever, intending to gratify unnatural lust,  touches for that purpose any person without that  person’s free and intelligent consent, shall be  punished with imprisonment of either description for  a term which may extend to life and must not be  less than seven years, and shall also be liable to  fine.”  

 

18. What is remarkable for the time in which he lived is the  

fact that Lord Macaulay would punish touching another person  

for the purpose of gratifying “unnatural lust” without their “free  

and intelligent consent” with a term of imprisonment extendable  

to life (but not less than seven years) while the penalty for the  

same offence, when consensual, would be imprisonment for a  

maximum term of fourteen years (but not less than two years).  

Even in this most prudish of all periods of English history, Lord

177

11  

 

Macaulay recognized a lesser sentence for the crime of  

“unnatural lust”, if performed with consent. Living in the era in  

which he lived, he clearly eschewed public discussion on this  

subject, stating:-   

“Clause 361 and 362 relate to an odious class of  offences respecting which it is desirable that as little  as possible should be said. We leave, without  comment, to the judgment of his Lordship in Council  the two clauses which we have provided for these  offences. We are unwilling to insert, either in the text  or in the notes, anything which could give rise to  public discussion on this revolting subject; as we are  decidedly of the opinion that the injury which would  be done to the morals of the community by such  discussion would far more than compensate for any  benefits which might be derived from legislative  measures framed with the greatest precision.”    

 

19. At what stage of the proceedings before the various  

persons and committees after 1837, Section 377 finally took  

shape, is not clear. What is clear is that it is the Committee of  

Sir Barnes Peacock which finally sent the draft equivalent of  

Section 377 for enactment.   

20. The Indian Penal Code, given its long life of over 150  

years, has had surprisingly few amendments made to it.  The  

42nd Law Commission Report, early in this country’s history, did  

not recommend the amendment or deletion of Section 377.  But

178

12  

 

B. P. Jeevan Reddy, J.’s Law Commission Report of the year  

2000 (the 172nd Report) recommended its deletion consequent  

to changes made in the preceding sections, which made it clear  

that anal sex between consenting adults, whether same-sex or  

otherwise, would not be penalized.   

Law in the United Kingdom   

21. As has been mentioned earlier in this judgment, the first  

enactment prohibiting same-sex intercourse was passed in the  

year 1533 in the reign of Henry VIII.  The death penalty was  

prescribed even for consenting adults who indulged in this  

“abomination”.  The trial of persons such as Oscar Wilde is  

what led to law reform in the U.K., albeit 60 years later.   

22. The Marquess of Queensberry’s son, Lord Alfred  

Douglas, was having an affair with Oscar Wilde, which the  

Marquess discovered. At Oscar Wilde’s club, the Marquess left  

a note describing Oscar Wilde as a “somdomite” which led to  

one of the most celebrated defamation actions in England. In  

the course of his cross-examination of Oscar Wilde, Sir Edward  

Carson was able to draw from his famous witness the fact that

179

13  

 

boys could be plain or ugly, which would have led to the truth of  

establishing the charge against Oscar Wilde. Rather than go on  

with the trial, Oscar Wilde hastily withdrew his action for  

defamation. But that was not the end.  A prosecution under the  

Criminal Law Amendment Act of 1885 followed, in which Oscar  

Wilde was convicted and sent to jail for a period of two years.  

He never quite recovered, for after his jail sentence was served  

out, he died a broken and impoverished man in Paris at the  

early age of 46.3    

23. The winds of change slowly blew over the British Isles  

and finally, post the Second World War, what is known as the  

Wolfenden Committee was appointed on 24.08.1954, inter alia  

to consider the law and practice relating to homosexual  

offences and the treatment of persons convicted of such  

offences by the courts.  The Committee Report, even though it  

is of a vintage of September 1957, makes interesting reading.  

In paragraphs 31 and 32 of the Report, the Committee opined:-  

                                                           3 Much more could have come from the pen of this genius. In fact, when crossing the U.S. Customs and  being asked whether he had anything to declare, his famous answer was said to have been, “I have  nothing to declare except my genius.” But even unjust jail sentences can produce remarkable things –  The Ballad of Reading Gaol is a masterpiece of English poetry which the world would never have  received had he not been incarcerated in Reading Gaol.

180

14  

 

“31. Even if it could be established that  homosexuality were a disease, it is clear that many  individuals, however their state is reached, present  social rather than medical problems and must be  dealt with by social, including penological, methods.  This is especially relevant when the claim that  homosexuality is an illness is taken to imply that its  treatment should be a medical responsibility. Much  more important than the academic question whether  homosexuality is a disease is the practical question  whether a doctor should carry out any part or all of  the treatment. Psychiatrists deal regularly with  problems of personality which are not regarded as  diseases, and conversely the treatment of cases of  recognized psychiatric illness may not be strictly  medical but may best be carried out by non-medical  supervision or environmental change. Examples  would be certain cases of senile dementia or  chronic schizophrenia which can best be managed  at home. In fact, the treatment of behavior  disorders, even when medically supervised, is rarely  confined to psychotherapy or to treatment of a  strictly medical kind. This is not to deny that expert  advice should be sought in very many homosexual  cases. We shall have something more to say on  these matters in connection with the treatment of  offenders.   

32. The claim that homosexuality is an illness  carries the further implication that the sufferer  cannot help it and therefore carries a diminished  responsibility for his actions. Even if it were  accepted that homosexuality could properly be  described as a “disease”, we should not accept this  corollary. There are no prima facie grounds for  supposing that because a particular person’s sexual  propensity happens to lie in the direction of persons  of his or her own sex it is any less controllable than  that of those whose propensity is for persons of the  opposite sex. We are informed that patients in  mental hospitals, with few exceptions, show clearly

181

15  

 

by their behavior that they can and do exercise a  high degree of responsibility and self-control; for  example, only a small minority need to be kept in  locked wards. The existence of varying degrees of  self-control is a matter of daily experience - the  extent to which coughing can be controlled is an  example - and the capacity for self-control can vary  with the personality structure or with temporary  physical or emotional conditions. The question  which is important for us here is whether the  individual suffers from a condition which causes  diminished responsibility. This is a different question  from the question whether he was responsible in the  past for the causes or origins of his present  condition. That is an interesting enquiry and may be  of relevance in other connections; but our concern is  with the behavior which flows from the individual’s  present condition and with the extent to which he is  responsible for that behavior, whatever may have  been the causes of the condition from which it  springs. Just as expert opinion can give valuable  assistance in deciding on the appropriate ways of  dealing with a convicted person, so can it help in  assessing the additional factors that may affect his  present responsibility?”   

 

24. It then went on to note in paragraph 36 that the evidence  

before them showed that homosexuality existed in all levels of  

society and was prevalent in all trades and professions. In  

paragraph 53, the main arguments for retention of the existing  

law were set out. Insofar as societal health was concerned, the  

Committee rejected this for lack of evidence.  It went on to  

state:-  

182

16  

 

“54. As regards the first of these arguments, it is  held that conduct of this kind is a cause of the  demoralization and decay of civilisations, and that  therefore, unless we wish to see our nation  degenerate and decay, such conduct must be  stopped, by every possible means. We have found  no evidence to support this view, and we cannot feel  it right to frame the laws which should govern this  country in the present age by reference to  hypothetical explanations of the history of other  peoples in ages distant in time and different in  circumstances from our own. In so far as the basis  of this argument can be precisely formulated, it is  often no more than the expression of revulsion  against what is regarded as unnatural, sinful or  disgusting. Many people feel this revulsion, for one  or more of these reasons. But moral conviction or  instinctive feeling, however strong, is not a valid  basis for overriding the individual’s privacy and for  bringing within the ambit of the criminal law private  sexual behaviour of this kind. It is held also that if  such men are employed in certain professions or  certain branches of the public service their private  habits may render them liable to threats of blackmail  or to other pressures which may make them “bad  security risks.” If this is true, it is true also of some  other categories of persons: for example, drunkards,  gamblers and those who become involved in  compromising situations of a heterosexual kind; and  while it may be a valid ground for excluding from  certain forms of employment men who indulge in  homosexual behaviour, it does not, in our view,  constitute a sufficient reason for making their private  sexual behaviour an offence in itself.”    

                                                (Emphasis supplied)  

183

17  

 

25. Insofar as the damaging effects on family life were  

concerned, this was rejected by stating:-   

“55. The second contention, that homosexual  behaviour between males has a damaging effect on  family life, may well be true. Indeed, we have had  evidence, that it often is; cases in which  homosexual behaviour on the part of the husband  has broken up a marriage are by no means rare,  and there are also cases in which a man in whom  the homosexual component is relatively weak  nevertheless derives such satisfaction from  homosexual outlets that he does not enter upon a  marriage which might have been successfully and  happily consummated. We deplore this damage to  what we regard as the basic unit of society; but  cases are also frequently encountered in which a  marriage has been broken up by homosexual  behaviour on the part of the wife, and no doubt  some women, too, derive sufficient satisfaction from  homosexual outlets to prevent their marrying. We  have had no reasons shown to us which would lead  us to believe that homosexual behaviour between  males inflicts any greater damage on family life than  adultery, fornication or lesbian behaviour. These  practices are all reprehensible from the point of view  of harm to the family, but it is difficult to see why on  this ground male homosexual behaviour alone  among them should be a criminal offence. This  argument is not to be taken as saying that society  should condone or approve male homosexual  behaviour. But where adultery, fornication and  lesbian behaviour are not criminal offences there  seems to us to be no valid ground, on the basis of  damage to the family, for so regarding homosexual  behaviour between men. Moreover, it has to be  recognized that the mere existence of the condition  of homosexuality in one of the partners can result in  an unsatisfactory marriage, so that for a

184

18  

 

homosexual to marry simply for the sake of  conformity with the accepted structure of society or  in the hope of curing his condition may result in  disaster.”   

 

26. And in rejecting the allegation that men indulging in such  

practices with other men may turn their attention to boys, the  

Committee said:-  

“56. We have given anxious consideration to the  third argument, that an adult male who has sought  as his partner another adult male may turn from  such a relationship and seek as his partner a boy or  succession of boys. We should certainly not wish to  countenance any proposal which might tend to  increase offences against minors. Indeed, if we  thought that any recommendation for a change in  the law would increase the danger to minors, we  should not make it. But in this matter, we have been  much influenced by our expert witnesses. They are  in no doubt that whatever may be the origins of the  homosexual condition, there are two recognisably  different categories among adult male homosexuals.  There are those who seek as partners other adult  males, and there are paedophiliacs, that is to say  men who seek as partners boys who have not  reached puberty.   57. We are authoritatively informed that a man who  has homosexual relations with an adult partner  seldom turns to boys, and vice-versa, though it is  apparent from the police reports we have seen and  from other evidence submitted to us that such cases  do happen.”    

27. Finally, the Committee stated:  

“60. We recognise that a proposal to change a law  which has operated for many years so as to make

185

19  

 

legally permissible acts which were formerly  unlawful, is open to criticisms which might not be  made in relation to a proposal to omit, from a code  of laws being formulated de novo, any provision  making these acts illegal. To reverse a long- standing tradition is a serious matter and not to be  suggested lightly. But the task entrusted to us, as  we conceive it, is to state what we regard as a just  and equitable law. We therefore do not think it  appropriate that consideration of this question  should be unduly influenced by a regard for the  present law, much of which derives from traditions  whose origins are obscure.     61. Further, we feel bound to say this. We have  outlined the arguments against a change in the law,  and we recognise their weight. We believe,  however, that they have been met by the counter- arguments we have already advanced. There  remains one additional counter-argument which we  believe to be decisive, namely, the importance  which society and the law ought to give to individual  freedom of choice and action in matters of private  morality. Unless a deliberate attempt is to be made  by society, acting through the agency of the law, to  equate the sphere of crime with that of sin, there  must remain a realm of private morality and  immorality which is, in brief and crude terms, not the  law’s business. To say this is not to condone or  encourage private immorality. On the contrary, to  emphasise the personal and private responsibility of  the individual for his own actions, and that is a  responsibility which a mature agent can properly be  expected to carry for himself without the threat of  punishment from the law.   

62. We accordingly recommend that homosexual  behaviour between consenting adults in private  should no longer be a criminal offence.”   

186

20  

 

28. Change came slowly. It was only in 1967 that the  

Wolfenden Committee Report was acted upon by the British  

Parliament by enacting the Sexual Offences Act, 1967, which  

abolished penal offences involving consenting same-sex adults.   

29. In 2017, the United Kingdom passed the Policing and  

Crimes Act which served as an amnesty law to pardon persons  

who were cautioned or convicted under legislations that  

outlawed homosexual acts.4   

The Law in the United States   

30. At the time that the United States achieved independence  

in 1776, the law in all the States insofar as same-sex offences  

were concerned, was the English law.  This state of affairs  

continued until challenges were made in the last century to  

state statutes which criminalized sodomy. One such case,  

namely, Bowers v. Hardwick (“Bowers”), 92 L. Ed. 2d 140  

(1986), reached the United States Supreme Court in the year  

1986.  By a 5:4 decision, the United States Supreme Court  

upheld a Georgia statute criminalizing sodomy and its                                                              4 The impetus for this law was the prosecution of Alan Turing in 1952. Alan Turing was instrumental in  cracking intercepted code messages that enabled the Allies to defeat Germany in many crucial  engagements in the War. Turing accepted chemical castration treatment as an alternative to prison upon  conviction, but committed suicide just before his 42nd birthday in 1954.  

187

21  

 

applicability to the commission of that act with another adult  

male in the bedroom of the respondent’s home.  Justice White,  

who spoke for the majority of the Court, did this on several  

grounds.   

31. First and foremost, he stated that there was no right to  

privacy that extended to homosexual sodomy. No connection  

between family, marriage, or procreation and homosexuality  

had been demonstrated to the court. The next ground for  

upholding such law was that proscriptions against such conduct  

had ancient roots. Stanley v. Georgia (“Stanley”), 22 L. Ed.  

2d 542 (1969), where the Court held that the First Amendment  

prohibits conviction for possessing and reading obscene  

material in the privacy of one’s home, was brushed aside  

stating that Stanley itself recognized that its holding offered no  

protection for possession of drugs, firearms or stolen goods in  

the home. Therefore, such a claimed fundamental right could  

not possibly exist when adultery, incest and other sexual crimes  

are punished, even though they may be committed in the home.  

Another important rationale was that the Georgia law was  

based on a notion of morality, which is a choice that could

188

22  

 

legitimately be exercised by a State Legislature.  Chief Justice  

Burger, concurring, again relied heavily on ‘ancient roots’,  

stating that throughout the history of western civilization,  

homosexual sodomy was outlawed in the Judeo-Christian  

tradition, which the Georgia legislature could well follow.   

Justice Powell, concurring with the majority, found that to  

imprison a person upto 20 years for a single, private,  

consensual act of sodomy within the home would be a cruel  

and unusual punishment within the meaning of the Eighth  

Amendment. However, since no trial had taken place on the  

facts, and since the respondent did not raise any such Eighth  

Amendment issue, Justice Powell concurred with the majority.   

 32. The dissenting opinion of four Justices makes interesting  

reading. Justice Blackmun, who spoke for four dissenters,  

began with the classical definition of the old privacy right which  

is the “right to be let alone”, and quoted from Justice Holmes’  

article The Path of the Law, stating:-  

“[i]t is revolting to have no better reason for a rule of  law than that so it was laid down in the time of  Henry IV. It is still more revolting if the grounds upon  which it was laid down have vanished long since,

189

23  

 

and the rule simply persists from blind imitation of  the past.”    

33. So much, then, for history and its “ancient roots”. Justice  

Blackmun’s dissent then went on to consider the famous  

judgment in Wisconsin v. Yoder, 32 L. Ed. 2d 15 (1972), in  

which the Court had upheld the fundamental right of the Amish  

community not to send their children to schools, stating that a  

way of life that is odd or even erratic but interferes with no  

rights or interests of others is not to be condemned because it  

is different. Referring to Judeo-Christian values, the Court said  

that the fact that certain religious groups condemn the behavior  

of sodomy gives the State no licence to impose their moral  

judgment on the entire citizenry of the United States. Ending  

with a John Stuart Mill type of analysis, the dissent stated:-  

“44. This case involves no real interference with the  rights of others, for the mere knowledge that other  individuals do not adhere to one’s value system  cannot be a legally cognizable interest, cf. Diamond  v. Charles, 476 U.S. 54, 65-66, 106 S. Ct. 1697,  1705, 90 L.Ed.2d 48 (1986), let alone an interest  that can justify invading the houses, hearts, and  minds of citizens who choose to live their lives  differently.”  

190

24  

 

34. Justice Stevens, also in a powerfully worded dissent,  

specifically stated that the protection of privacy extends to  

intimate choices made by unmarried as well as married  

persons.   

35. It took the United States 17 years to set aside this view of  

the law and to accept the dissenting judgments in Bowers  

(supra).    

36. In Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003), by a  

majority of 6:3, Justice Anthony Kennedy, speaking for the  

majority, set aside the judgment in Bowers (supra), accepting  

that the dissenting judgments in that case were correct. In a tilt  

at the history analysis of the majority judgment in Bowers  

(supra), the Court found that earlier sodomy laws were not  

directed at homosexuals at large, but instead sought to prohibit  

non-procreative sexual activity more generally, and were not  

enforced against consenting adults acting in private. After citing  

from Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey  

(“Casey”), 505 U.S. 833 (1992), the majority held – “our  

obligation is to define the liberty of all, not to mandate our own  

moral code.” The majority judgment then referred to a Model

191

25  

 

Penal Code that the American Law Institute took out in 1955,  

making it clear that it did not provide for criminal penalties for  

consensual same-sex relationships conducted in private. The  

judgment then went on to refer to the Wolfenden Committee  

Report and the Sexual Offences Act,1967 in the United  

Kingdom and referred to the European Court’s decision in  

Dudgeon v. United Kingdom, 45 Eur. Ct. H. R. (1981). It then  

referred to Romer v. Evans (“Romer”), 517 U.S. 620 (1996),  

where the Court struck down a class-based legislation which  

deprived homosexuals of State anti-discrimination laws as a  

violation of the Equal Protection Clause. The majority then  

found that the 1986 decision of Bowers (supra), had “sustained  

serious erosion” through their recent decisions in Casey (supra)  

and Romer (supra), and had, therefore, to be revisited.5 Justice  

                                                           5 The majority’s decision echoes what had happened earlier in what is referred to as the celebrated flag  salute case, namely, West Virginia State Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943). The  U.S. Supreme Court had overruled its recent judgment in Minersville School District v. Gobitis, 310  U.S. 586 (1940). Justice Jackson speaking for the majority of the Court found:-  

“The freedom asserted by these appellees does not bring them into collision with rights  asserted by any other individual. It is such conflicts which most frequently require  intervention of the State to determine where the rights of one end and those of another  begin. But the refusal of these persons to participate in the ceremony does not interfere  with or deny rights of others to do so. Nor is there any question in this case that their  behavior is peaceable and orderly.”  

The learned Judge then went on to find:  “The very purpose of a Bill of Rights was to withdraw certain subjects from the  vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond the reach of majorities and  officials and to establish them as legal principles to be applied by the courts. One's right  to life, liberty, and property, to free speech, a free press, freedom of worship and

192

26  

 

O’Connor concurred in the judgment but side-stepped rather  

than overruled Bowers (supra). Justice Scalia, with whom the  

Chief Justice and Justice Thomas joined, found no reason to  

undo the Bowers (supra) verdict stating that stare decisis  

should carry the day. An interesting passage in Justice Scalia’s  

judgment reads as follows:-  

“Let me be clear that I have nothing against  homosexuals, or any other group, promoting their  agenda through normal democratic means. Social  perceptions of sexual and other morality change  over time, and every group has the right to  persuade its fellow citizens that its view of such  matters is the best. That homosexuals have  achieved some success in that enterprise is attested  to by the fact that Texas is one of the few remaining  States that criminalize private, consensual  homosexual acts. But persuading one’s fellow  citizens is one thing, and imposing one’s views in  absence of democratic majority will is something  else. I would no more require a State to criminalize  homosexual acts—or, for that matter, display any  moral disapprobation of them—than I would forbid it  to do so. What Texas has chosen to do is well within  the range of traditional democratic action, and its  hand should not be stayed through the invention of  a brand-new “constitutional right” by a Court that is  impatient of democratic change. It is indeed true  that “later generations can see that laws once  

                                                                                                                                                                                           assembly, and other fundamental rights may not be submitted to vote; they depend on  the outcome of no elections.”  

And finally, it was held:-  “If there is any fixed star in our constitutional constellation, it is that no official, high or  petty, can prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other  matters of opinion or force citizens to confess by word or act their faith therein. If there  are any circumstances which permit an exception, they do not now occur to us.”

193

27  

 

thought necessary and proper in fact serve only to  oppress,” [ante, at 579]; and when that happens,  later generations can repeal those laws. But it is the  premise of our system that those judgments are to  be made by the people, and not imposed by a  governing caste that knows best.”  

 

37. Before coming to our own judgments, we may quickly  

survey some of the judgments of the courts of other democratic  

nations. The European Community decisions, beginning with  

Dudgeon v. United Kingdom (supra) and continuing with  

Norris v. Ireland, Application no. 10581/83,  and Modinos v.  

Cyprus, 16 EHRR 485 (1993), have all found provisions similar  

to Section 377 to  be violative of Article 8 of the European  

Human Rights Convention, 1948 in which everyone has the  

right to respect for his private and family life, his home and his  

correspondence, and no interference can be made with these  

rights unless the law is necessary in a democratic society inter  

alia for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of  

health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and  

freedoms of others.   

38. In El-Al Israel Airlines Ltd. v. Jonathan Danielwitz,  

H.C.J. 721/94, the Supreme Court of Israel, speaking through

194

28  

 

Barak, J., recognized a same-sex relationship so that a male  

companion could be treated as being a companion for the  

receipt of a free or discounted aeroplane ticket. The Court  

held:-  

“14.….The principle of equality demands that the  existence of a rule that treats people differently is  justified by the nature and substance of the issue.  The principle of equality therefore presumes the  existence of objective reasons that justify a  difference (a distinction, dissimilarity). Discrimination  — which is the opposite of equality — exists  therefore in those situations where a different law  for people who are (de facto) different from one  another is based on reasons that are insufficient to  justify a distinction between them in a free and  democratic society. In Justice Or’s words,  discrimination is ‘different treatment without an  objective justification’ (Hoppert v. ‘Yad VaShem’  Holocaust Martyrs and Heroes Memorial Authority  [12], at p. 360). President Agranat discussed this  and pointed out:  

‘The principle of equality, which is merely  the opposite of discrimination and which,  for reasons of justice and fairness, the  law of every democratic country aspires  to achieve, means that people must be  treated equally for a particular purpose,  when no real differences that are relevant  to this purpose exist between them. If  they are not treated equally, we have a  case of discrimination. However, if the  difference or differences between  different people are relevant for the  purpose under discussion, it is a  permitted distinction to treat them  differently for that purpose, provided that

195

29  

 

those differences justify this. In this  context, the concept of “equality”  therefore means “relevant equality”, and it  requires, with regard to the purpose  under discussion, “equality of treatment”  for those persons in this state. By  contrast, it will be a permitted distinction if  the different treatment of different  persons derives from their being for the  purpose of the treatment, in a state of  relevant inequality, just as it will be  discrimination if it derives from their being  in a state of inequality that is not relevant  to the purpose of the treatment’ (FH  10/69 Boronovski v. Chief Rabbis [16], at  p. 35).  

Therefore, a particular law will create discrimination  when two individuals, who are different from one  another (factual inequality), are treated differently by  the law, even though the factual difference between  them does not justify different treatment in the  circumstances. Discrimination is therefore based on  the factors of arbitrariness, injustice and  unreasonableness.  

XXX  

17. We have seen, therefore, that giving a benefit to  a (permanent) employee for a spouse or recognized  companion of the opposite sex and not giving the  same benefit for a same-sex companion amounts to  a violation of equality. What is the nature of this  discrimination? Indeed, all discrimination is  prohibited, but among the different kinds of  discrimination, there are varying degrees. The  severity of the discrimination is determined by the  severity of the violation of the principle of equality.  Thus, for example, we consider discrimination on  the basis of race, religion, nationality, language,  ethnic group and age to be particularly serious. In

196

30  

 

this framework, the Israeli legal system attaches  great importance to the need to guarantee equality  between the sexes and to prevent discrimination on  the basis of sex (see HCJ 153/87 Shakdiel v.  Minister of Religious Affairs [19]; Poraz v. Mayor of  Tel Aviv-Jaffa [6]).”  

(Emphasis supplied)    

39. An instructive recent judgment from Trinidad and Tobago  

in Jason Jones v. Attorney General of Trinidad and Tobago,  

Claim No. CV 2017-00720, followed our judgment in  

Puttaswamy (supra) in order to strike down Section 13 of the  

Sexual Offences Act, 1986 on the ground that the State cannot  

criminalise sexual relations of the same sex between  

consenting adults. The court concluded:-  

“168. Having regard to the evidence and  submissions before this court on all sides, there is  no cogent evidence that the legislative objective is  sufficiently important to justify limiting the claimant’s  rights. Mr. Hosein’s stated objectives of:  

168.1. Maintaining traditional family and values that  represent society;  

168.2. Preserving the legislation as it is and  clarifying the law; and  

168.3. Extending the offence in section 16 to women  and reduce it to serious indecency from gross  indecency;  

do not counterbalance the claimant’s limit of his  fundamental right of which he has given evidence.

197

31  

 

Instead, the court accepts the claimant’s position  that the law as it stands is not sufficiently important  to justify limiting his fundamental rights and that he  has proven it on a balance of probabilities.”  

 

40. To similar effect is the judgment of the High Court of Fiji in  

Dhirendra Nadan v. State, Case No. HAA0085 of 2005, where  

a Section similar to Section 377 was held to be inconsistent  

with the constitutional right of privacy and invalid to the extent  

that the law criminalises acts constituting private consensual  

sexual conduct “against the course of nature” between adults.   

41. The South African Supreme Court, by a decision of 1999  

in The National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v.  

The Minister of Home Affairs, Case CCT 10/99, after referring  

to various judgments of other courts, also found a similar  

section to be inconsistent with the fundamental rights under its  

Constitution.   

42. Another important decision is that of the United Nations  

Human Rights Committee in Toonen v. Australia,  

Communication No. 488/1992, U.N. Doc  

CCPR/C/50/D/488/1992 (1994), dated 31.03.1994. The  

Committee was called upon to determine whether Mr. Nicholas

198

32  

 

Toonen, who resided in the state of Tasmania, had been the  

victim of arbitrary interference with his privacy, and whether he  

had been discriminated against on the basis of his sexual  

orientation of being a homosexual. The Committee found:-  

“8.2 Inasmuch as Article 17 is concerned, it is  undisputed that adult consensual sexual activity in  private is covered by the concept of “privacy”, and  that Mr. Toonen is actually and currently affected by  the continued existence of the Tasmanian laws. The  Committee considers that Sections 122 (a), (c) and  123 of the Tasmanian Criminal Code “interfere” with  the author's privacy, even if these provisions have  not been enforced for a decade. In this context, it  notes that the policy of the Department of Public  Prosecutions not to initiate criminal proceedings in  respect of private homosexual conduct does not  amount to a guarantee that no actions will be  brought against homosexuals in the future,  particularly in the light of undisputed statements of  the Director of Public Prosecutions of Tasmania in  1988 and those of members of the Tasmanian  Parliament. The continued existence of the  challenged provisions therefore continuously and  directly “interferes” with the author's privacy.  

8.3 The prohibition against private homosexual  behaviour is provided for by law, namely, Sections  122 and 123 of the Tasmanian Criminal Code. As to  whether it may be deemed arbitrary, the Committee  recalls that pursuant to its General Comment 16 on  article 17, the "introduction of the concept of  arbitrariness is intended to guarantee that even  interference provided for by the law should be in  accordance with the provisions, aims and objectives  of the Covenant and should be, in any event,  reasonable in the circumstances”.(4) The

199

33  

 

Committee interprets the requirement of  reasonableness to imply that any interference with  privacy must be proportional to the end sought and  be necessary in the circumstances of any given  case.  

XXX  

8.5 As far as the public health argument of the  Tasmanian authorities is concerned, the Committee  notes that the criminalization of homosexual  practices cannot be considered a reasonable means  or proportionate measure to achieve the aim of  preventing the spread of AIDS/HIV. The Australian  Government observes that statutes criminalizing  homosexual activity tend to impede public health  programmes “by driving underground many of the  people at the risk of infection”. Criminalization of  homosexual activity thus would appear to run  counter to the implementation of effective education  programmes in respect of the HIV/AIDS prevention.  Secondly, the Committee notes that no link has  been shown between the continued criminalization  of homosexual activity and the effective control of  the spread of the HIV/AIDS virus.  

XXX  

8.7 The State party has sought the Committee's  guidance as to whether sexual orientation may be  considered an “other status” for the purposes of  article 26. The same issue could arise under article  2, paragraph 1, of the Covenant. The Committee  confines itself to noting, however, that in its view the  reference to "sex" in articles 2, paragraph 1, and 26  is to be taken as including sexual orientation.  

XXX  

10. Under article 2(3)(a) of the Covenant, the  author, victim of a violation of articles 17, paragraph  1, juncto 2, paragraph 1, of the Covenant, is entitled  to a remedy. In the opinion of the Committee, an

200

34  

 

effective remedy would be the repeal of Sections  122(a), (c) and 123 of the Tasmanian Criminal  Code.”  

 

43.  As a result of these findings, the Australian Parliament, on  

19.12.1994, passed the Human Rights (Sexual Conduct) Act,  

1994, Section 4 of which reads as under:-  

“4.  Arbitrary interferences with privacy   

(1) Sexual conduct involving only consenting  adults acting in private is not to be subject, by or  under any law of the Commonwealth, a State or a  Territory, to any arbitrary interference with privacy  within the meaning of Article 17 of the International  Covenant on Civil and Political Rights.   

(2)   For the purposes of this section, an adult is a  person who is 18 years old or more.”  

 

Recent Judgments of this Court  

44. Anuj Garg and Ors. v. Hotel Association of India and  

Ors., (2008) 3 SCC 1, is an important decision of this Court,  

which dealt with the constitutional validity of another pre-

constitution enactment, namely, Section 30 of the Punjab  

Excise Act of 1914, which prohibited employment of any  

woman in any part of premises in which liquor is consumed by  

the public.  Sinha, J. adverted to the fact that when the original

201

35  

 

Act was enacted, the concept of equality between the two  

sexes was unknown. The Constitution changed all that when it  

enacted Articles 14 and 15.  What is of importance is that when  

discrimination is made between two sets of persons, the  

classification must be founded on some rational criteria having  

regard to the societal conditions as they exist presently, and not  

as they existed in the early 20th century or even earlier. This  

was felicitously stated by the learned Judge as follows:-  

“7. The Act is a pre-constitutional legislation.  Although it is saved in terms of Article 372 of the  Constitution, challenge to its validity on the  touchstone of Articles 14, 15 and 19 of the  Constitution of India, is permissible in law. While  embarking on the questions raised, it may be  pertinent to know that a statute although could have  been held to be a valid piece of legislation keeping  in view the societal condition of those times, but  with the changes occurring therein both in the  domestic as also international arena, such a law  can also be declared invalid.  

8. In John Vallamattom v. Union of India, (2003) 6  SCC 611, this Court, while referring to an  amendment made in UK in relation to a provision  which was in pari materia with Section 118 of Indian  Succession Act, observed (SCC p. 624, para 28):  

“28…The constitutionality of a provision, it  is trite, will have to be judged keeping in  view the interpretative changes of the  statute affected by passage of time.”

202

36  

 

Referring to the changing legal scenario and having  regard to the Declaration on the Right to  Development adopted by the World Conference on  Human Rights as also Article 18 of the United  Nations Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,  1966, it was held (John Vallamattom case, SCC p.  625, para 33):  

“33. It is trite that having regard to Article  13(1) of the Constitution, the  constitutionality of the impugned  legislation is required to be considered on  the basis of laws existing on 26-1-1950,  but while doing so the court is not  precluded from taking into consideration  the subsequent events which have taken  place thereafter. It is further trite that the  law although may be constitutional when  enacted but with passage of time the  same may be held to be unconstitutional  in view of the changed situation.”  

          XXX  

26. When a discrimination is sought to be made on  the purported ground of classification, such  classification must be founded on a rational criteria.  The criteria which in absence of any constitutional  provision and, it will bear repetition to state, having  regard to the societal conditions as they prevailed in  early 20th century, may not be a rational criteria in  the 21st century. In the early 20th century, the  hospitality sector was not open to women in  general. In the last 60 years, women in India have  gained entry in all spheres of public life. They have  also been representing people at grass root  democracy. They are now employed as drivers of  heavy transport vehicles, conductors of service  carriages, pilots, et. al. Women can be seen to be  occupying Class IV posts to the post of a Chief  Executive Officer of a Multinational Company. They

203

37  

 

are now widely accepted both in police as also army  services.”  

 

45. The Court went on to hold that “proportionality” should be  

a standard capable of being called reasonable in a modern  

democratic society (See paragraph 36).  

In a significant paragraph, the learned Judge held:-  

“43. Instead of prohibiting women employment in  the bars altogether the State should focus on  factoring in ways through which unequal  consequences of sex differences can be eliminated.  It is the State’s duty to ensure circumstances of  safety which inspire confidence in women to  discharge the duty freely in accordance to the  requirements of the profession they choose to  follow. Any other policy inference (such as the one  embodied under Section 30) from societal  conditions would be oppressive on the women and  against the privacy rights.”  

 

46. The learned Judge then went on to further hold that the  

standard of judicial scrutiny of legislations, which on their face  

effect discrimination, is as follows:-  

“46. It is to be borne in mind that legislations with  pronounced “protective discrimination” aims, such  as this one, potentially serve as double-edged  swords. Strict scrutiny test should be employed  while assessing the implications of this variety of  legislations. Legislation should not be only

204

38  

 

assessed on its proposed aims but rather on the  implications and the effects. The impugned  legislation suffers from incurable fixations of  stereotype morality and conception of sexual role.  The perspective thus arrived at is outmoded in  content and stifling in means.  

47. No law in its ultimate effect should end up  perpetuating the oppression of women. Personal  freedom is a fundamental tenet which cannot be  compromised in the name of expediency until and  unless there is a compelling State purpose.  Heightened level of scrutiny is the normative  threshold for judicial review in such cases.”  

 47. Finally, the Court held:-  

“50. The test to review such a protective  discrimination statute would entail a two-pronged  scrutiny:  

(a) the legislative interference (induced by  sex discriminatory legislation in the  instant case) should be justified in  principle,  

(b) the same should be proportionate in  measure.  

51. The Court’s task is to determine whether the  measures furthered by the State in the form of  legislative mandate, to augment the legitimate aim  of protecting the interests of women are  proportionate to the other bulk of well-settled gender  norms such as autonomy, equality of opportunity,  right to privacy, et al. The bottomline in this behalf  would be a functioning modern democratic society  which ensures freedom to pursue varied  opportunities and options without discriminating on  the basis of sex, race, caste or any other like basis.

205

39  

 

In fine, there should be a reasonable relationship of  proportionality between the means used and the  aim pursued.”  

 

48. The Section which had been struck down by the High  

Court was held to be arbitrary and unreasonable by this Court  

as well.  

49. Close on the heels of this Court’s judgment in Suresh  

Kumar Koushal (supra) is this Court’s judgment in NALSA  

(supra).  In this case, the Court had to grapple with the trauma,  

agony and pain of the members of the transgender community.   

The Court referred to Section 377 in the following words:  

“19. Section 377 IPC found a place in the Penal  Code, 1860, prior to the enactment of the Criminal  Tribes Act that criminalised all penile non-vaginal  sexual acts between persons, including anal sex  and oral sex, at a time when transgender persons  were also typically associated with the proscribed  sexual practices. Reference may be made to the  judgment of the Allahabad High Court in Queen  Empress v. Khairati, ILR (1884) 6 All 204, wherein a  transgender person was arrested and prosecuted  under Section 377 on the suspicion that he was a  “habitual sodomite” and was later acquitted on  appeal. In that case, while acquitting him, the  Sessions Judge stated as follows: (ILR pp. 204-05)  

“… ‘This case relates to a person named  Khairati, over whom the police seem to  have exercised some sort of supervision,  whether strictly regular or not, as a

206

40  

 

eunuch. The man is not a eunuch in the  literal sense, but he was called for by the  police when on a visit to his village, and  was found singing dressed as a woman  among the women of a certain family.  Having been subjected to examination by  the Civil Surgeon (and a subordinate  medical man), he is shown to have the  characteristic mark of a habitual  catamite—the distortion of the orifice of  the anus into the shape of a trumpet— and also to be affected with syphilis in the  same region in a manner which distinctly  points to unnatural intercourse within the  last few months.’”  

Even though, he was acquitted on appeal, this case  would demonstrate that Section 377, though  associated with specific sexual acts, highlighted  certain identities, including hijras and was used as  an instrument of harassment and physical abuse  against hijras and transgender persons.”  

 

50. The Court went on to explain the concepts of gender  

identity and sexual orientation, and relied heavily upon  

Yogyakarta Principles on the Application of International  

Human Rights Law in Relation to Sexual Orientation and  

Gender Identity. The Court then went on to hold:  

“60. The principles discussed hereinbefore on TGs  and the international conventions, including  Yogyakarta Principles, which we have found not  inconsistent with the various fundamental rights  guaranteed under the Indian Constitution, must be  recognised and followed, which has sufficient legal  and historical justification in our country.”

207

41  

 

51. Insofar as Articles 15 and 16 of the Constitution were  

concerned, the Court held:  

“66. Articles 15 and 16 sought to prohibit  discrimination on the basis of sex, recognising that  sex discrimination is a historical fact and needs to  be addressed. The Constitution-makers, it can be  gathered, gave emphasis to the fundamental right  against sex discrimination so as to prevent the  direct or indirect attitude to treat people differently,  for the reason of not being in conformity with  stereotypical generalisations of binary genders.  Both gender and biological attributes constitute  distinct components of sex. The biological  characteristics, of course, include genitals,  chromosomes and secondary sexual features, but  gender attributes include one's self-image, the deep  psychological or emotional sense of sexual identity  and character. The discrimination on the ground of  “sex” under Articles 15 and 16, therefore, includes  discrimination on the ground of gender identity. The  expression “sex” used in Articles 15 and 16 is not  just limited to biological sex of male or female, but  intended to include people who consider themselves  to be neither male nor female.”  

 

52. Insofar as Article 19(1)(a) of the Constitution and  

transgenders were concerned, the Court held:  

“72. Gender identity, therefore, lies at the core of  one's personal identity, gender expression and  presentation and, therefore, it will have to be  protected under Article 19(1)(a) of the Constitution  of India. A transgender's personality could be  expressed by the transgender's behaviour and  presentation. State cannot prohibit, restrict or

208

42  

 

interfere with a transgender's expression of such  personality, which reflects that inherent personality.  Often the State and its authorities either due to  ignorance or otherwise fail to digest the innate  character and identity of such persons. We,  therefore, hold that values of privacy, self-identity,  autonomy and personal integrity are fundamental  rights guaranteed to members of the transgender  community under Article 19(1)(a) of the Constitution  of India and the State is bound to protect and  recognise those rights.”   

 

53. In a significant paragraph relating to the personal  

autonomy of an individual, this Court held:  

“75. Article 21, as already indicated, guarantees the  protection of “personal autonomy” of an individual.  In Anuj Garg v. Hotel Assn. of India [(2008) 3 SCC  1] (SCC p. 15, paras 34-35), this Court held that  personal autonomy includes both the negative right  of not to be subject to interference by others and the  positive right of individuals to make decisions about  their life, to express themselves and to choose  which activities to take part in. Self-determination of  gender is an integral part of personal autonomy and  self-expression and falls within the realm of  personal liberty guaranteed under Article 21 of the  Constitution of India.”      

54. The conclusion therefore was:-  

“83. We, therefore, conclude that discrimination on  the basis of sexual orientation or gender identity  includes any discrimination, exclusion, restriction or  preference, which has the effect of nullifying or  transposing equality by the law or the equal  protection of laws guaranteed under our

209

43  

 

Constitution, and hence we are inclined to give  various directions to safeguard the constitutional  rights of the members of the TG community.”       

55. Dr. A.K. Sikri, J., in a separate concurring judgment,  

spoke of the fundamental and universal principle of the right of  

choice given to every individual, which is an inseparable part of  

human rights.  He then went on to hold:-  

“116.1. Though in the past TGs in India were treated  with great respect, that does not remain the  scenario any longer. Attrition in their status was  triggered with the passing of the Criminal Tribes Act,  1871 which deemed the entire community of hijra  persons as innately “criminal” and “adapted to the  systematic commission of non-bailable offences”.  This dogmatism and indoctrination of the Indian  people with aforesaid presumption, was totally  capricious and nefarious. There could not have  been more harm caused to this community with the  passing of the aforesaid brutal legislation during the  British Regime with the vicious and savage mind- set. To add insult to the irreparable injury caused,  Section 377 of the Penal Code was misused and  abused as there was a tendency, in the British  period, to arrest and prosecute TG persons under  Section 377 merely on suspicion. To undergo this  sordid historical harm caused to TGs of India, there  is a need for incessant efforts with effervescence.”  

 

56. And in paragraphs 125 and 129, he outlined the role of  

our Court as follows:-

210

44  

 

“125. The role of the Court is to understand the  central purpose and theme of the Constitution for  the welfare of the society. Our Constitution, like the  law of the society, is a living organism. It is based  on a factual and social reality that is constantly  changing. Sometimes a change in the law precedes  societal change and is even intended to stimulate it.  Sometimes, a change in the law is the result in the  social reality. When we discuss about the rights of  TGs in the constitutional context, we find that in  order to bring about complete paradigm shift, the  law has to play more predominant role. As TGs in  India, are neither male nor female, treating them as  belonging to either of the aforesaid categories, is  the denial of these constitutional rights. It is the  denial of social justice which in turn has the effect of  denying political and economic justice.  

XXX  

129. As we have pointed out above, our Constitution  inheres liberal and substantive democracy with the  rule of law as an important and fundamental pillar. It  has its own internal morality based on dignity and  equality of all human beings. The rule of law  demands protection of individual human rights.  Such rights are to be guaranteed to each and every  human being. These TGs, even though insignificant  in numbers, are still human beings and therefore  they have every right to enjoy their human rights.”  

 

57. In an unusual final order, the Court declared:-  

“135. We, therefore, declare:  

135.1. Hijras, eunuchs, apart from binary genders,  be treated as “third gender” for the purpose of  safeguarding their rights under Part III of our  Constitution and the laws made by Parliament and  the State Legislature.

211

45  

 

135.2. Transgender persons' right to decide their  self-identified gender is also upheld and the Centre  and State Governments are directed to grant legal  recognition of their gender identity such as male,  female or as third gender.  

135.3. We direct the Centre and the State  Governments to take steps to treat them as Socially  and Educationally Backward Classes of citizens and  extend all kinds of reservation in cases of admission  in educational institutions and for public  appointments.  

135.4. The Centre and State Governments are  directed to operate separate HIV serosurveillance  centres since hijras/transgenders face several  sexual health issues.  

135.5. The Centre and State Governments should  seriously address the problems being faced by  hijras/transgenders such as fear, shame, gender  dysphoria, social pressure, depression, suicidal  tendencies, social stigma, etc. and any insistence  for SRS for declaring one's gender is immoral and  illegal.  

135.6. The Centre and State Governments should  take proper measures to provide medical care to  TGs in the hospitals and also provide them separate  public toilets and other facilities.  

135.7. The Centre and State Governments should  also take steps for framing various social welfare  schemes for their betterment.  

135.8. The Centre and State Governments should  take steps to create public awareness so that TGs  will feel that they are also part and parcel of the  social life and be not treated as untouchables.  

135.9. The Centre and the State Governments  should also take measures to regain their respect

212

46  

 

and place in the society which once they enjoyed in  our cultural and social life.”  

 

58. Puttaswamy (supra) is the next important nail in the  

coffin of section 377 insofar as it pertains to consensual sex  

between same-sex adults. In this judgment, Chandrachud, J.  

referred approvingly to the NALSA (supra) judgment in  

paragraph 96 and went on to hold that privacy is intrinsic to  

freedom and liberty.  In referring to Suresh Kumar Koushal  

(supra), Chandrachud, J. referred to the judgment as “another  

discordant note” which directly bears upon the evolution of  

constitutional jurisprudence on the right to privacy.   

Chandrachud, J. went on to castigate the judgment in Suresh  

Kumar Koushal (supra), and held:-  

“144. Neither of the above reasons can be regarded  as a valid constitutional basis for disregarding a  claim based on privacy under Article 21 of the  Constitution. That “a miniscule fraction of the  country's population constitutes lesbians, gays,  bisexuals or transgenders” (as observed in the  judgment of this Court) is not a sustainable basis to  deny the right to privacy. The purpose of elevating  certain rights to the stature of guaranteed  fundamental rights is to insulate their exercise from  the disdain of majorities, whether legislative or  popular. The guarantee of constitutional rights does  not depend upon their exercise being favourably  regarded by majoritarian opinion. The test of

213

47  

 

popular acceptance does not furnish a valid basis to  disregard rights which are conferred with the  sanctity of constitutional protection. Discrete and  insular minorities face grave dangers of  discrimination for the simple reason that their views,  beliefs or way of life does not accord with the  “mainstream”. Yet in a democratic Constitution  founded on the Rule of Law, their rights are as  sacred as those conferred on other citizens to  protect their freedoms and liberties. Sexual  orientation is an essential attribute of privacy.  Discrimination against an individual on the basis of  sexual orientation is deeply offensive to the dignity  and self-worth of the individual. Equality demands  that the sexual orientation of each individual in  society must be protected on an even platform. The  right to privacy and the protection of sexual  orientation lie at the core of the fundamental rights  guaranteed by Articles 14, 15 and 21 of the  Constitution.  

145. The view in Koushal [Suresh Kumar Koushal v.  Naz Foundation, (2014) 1 SCC 1 : (2013) 4 SCC  (Cri) 1] that the High Court had erroneously relied  upon international precedents “in its anxiety to  protect the so-called rights of LGBT persons” is  similarly, in our view, unsustainable. The rights of  the lesbian, gay, bisexual and transgender  population cannot be construed to be “so-called  rights”. The expression “so-called” seems to  suggest the exercise of a liberty in the garb of a  right which is illusory. This is an inappropriate  construction of the privacy-based claims of the  LGBT population. Their rights are not “so-called” but  are real rights founded on sound constitutional  doctrine. They inhere in the right to life. They dwell  in privacy and dignity. They constitute the essence  of liberty and freedom. Sexual orientation is an  essential component of identity. Equal protection  demands protection of the identity of every  individual without discrimination.

214

48  

 

146. The decision in Koushal [Suresh Kumar  Koushal v. Naz Foundation, (2014) 1 SCC 1 :  (2013) 4 SCC (Cri) 1] presents a de minimis  rationale when it asserts that there have been only  two hundred prosecutions for violating Section 377.  The de minimis hypothesis is misplaced because  the invasion of a fundamental right is not rendered  tolerable when a few, as opposed to a large number  of persons, are subjected to hostile treatment. The  reason why such acts of hostile discrimination are  constitutionally impermissible is because of the  chilling effect which they have on the exercise of the  fundamental right in the first place. For instance,  pre-publication restraints such as censorship are  vulnerable because they discourage people from  exercising their right to free speech because of the  fear of a restraint coming into operation. The chilling  effect on the exercise of the right poses a grave  danger to the unhindered fulfilment of one's sexual  orientation, as an element of privacy and dignity.  The chilling effect is due to the danger of a human  being subjected to social opprobrium or disapproval,  as reflected in the punishment of crime. Hence the  Koushal [Suresh Kumar Koushal v. Naz Foundation,  (2014) 1 SCC 1 : (2013) 4 SCC (Cri) 1] rationale  that prosecution of a few is not an index of violation  is flawed and cannot be accepted. Consequently,  we disagree with the manner in which Koushal  [Suresh Kumar Koushal v. Naz Foundation, (2014)  1 SCC 1 : (2013) 4 SCC (Cri) 1] has dealt with the  privacy-dignity based claims of LGBT persons on  this aspect.  

147. Since the challenge to Section 377 is pending  consideration before a larger Bench of this Court,  we would leave the constitutional validity to be  decided in an appropriate proceeding.”  

    

215

49  

 

59. In an important paragraph, the learned Judge finally held:  

“323. Privacy includes at its core the preservation of  personal intimacies, the sanctity of family life,  marriage, procreation, the home and sexual  orientation. Privacy also connotes a right to be left  alone. Privacy safeguards individual autonomy and  recognises the ability of the individual to control vital  aspects of his or her life. Personal choices  governing a way of life are intrinsic to privacy.  Privacy protects heterogeneity and recognises the  plurality and diversity of our culture. While the  legitimate expectation of privacy may vary from the  intimate zone to the private zone and from the  private to the public arenas, it is important to  underscore that privacy is not lost or surrendered  merely because the individual is in a public place.  Privacy attaches to the person since it is an  essential facet of the dignity of the human being.”  

 

60. Nariman, J., in his judgment, which was concurred in by  

three other learned Judges, recognized the privacy of choice  

which protects an individual’s autonomy over fundamental  

personal choices as follows:-  

“521. In the Indian context, a fundamental right to  privacy would cover at least the following three  aspects:  

• Privacy that involves the person i.e. when there is  some invasion by the State of a person's rights  relatable to his physical body, such as the right to  move freely;  

• Informational privacy which does not deal with a  person's body but deals with a person's mind, and  therefore recognises that an individual may have

216

50  

 

control over the dissemination of material that is  personal to him. Unauthorised use of such  information may, therefore lead to infringement of  this right; and  

• The privacy of choice, which protects an  individual's autonomy over fundamental personal  choices.  

For instance, we can ground physical privacy or  privacy relating to the body in Articles 19(1)(d) and  (e) read with Article 21; ground personal information  privacy under Article 21; and the privacy of choice in  Articles 19(1)(a) to (c), 20(3), 21 and 25. The  argument based on “privacy” being a vague and  nebulous concept need not, therefore, detain us.”  

 

61. Kaul, J., in a separate judgment, also joined  

Chandrachud, J. in castigating Suresh Kumar Koushal’s  

judgment as follows:  

“647. There are two aspects of the opinion of Dr  D.Y. Chandrachud, J., one of which is common to  the opinion of Rohinton F. Nariman, J., needing  specific mention. While considering the evolution of  constitutional jurisprudence on the right to privacy  he has referred to the judgment in Suresh Kumar  Koushal v. Naz Foundation [Suresh Kumar Koushal  v. Naz Foundation, (2014) 1 SCC 1 : (2013) 4 SCC  (Cri) 1]. In the challenge laid to Section 377 of the  Penal Code before the Delhi High Court, one of the  grounds of challenge was that the said provision  amounted to an infringement of the right to dignity  and privacy. The Delhi High Court, inter alia,  observed [Naz Foundation v. Govt. (NCT of Delhi),  2009 SCC OnLine Del 1762 : 2010 Cri LJ 94] that  the right to live with dignity and the right to privacy  both are recognised as dimensions of Article 21 of

217

51  

 

the Constitution of India. The view of the High Court,  however did not find favour with the Supreme Court  and it was observed that only a miniscule fraction of  the country's population constitutes lesbians, gays,  bisexuals or transgenders and thus, there cannot be  any basis for declaring the section ultra vires of  provisions of Articles 14, 15 and 21 of the  Constitution. The matter did not rest at this, as the  issue of privacy and dignity discussed by the High  Court was also observed upon. The sexual  orientation even within the four walls of the house  thus became an aspect of debate. I am in  agreement with the view of Dr D.Y. Chandrachud,  J., who in paras 144 to 146 of his judgment, states  that the right to privacy cannot be denied, even if  there is a miniscule fraction of the population which  is affected. The majoritarian concept does not apply  to constitutional rights and the courts are often  called up on to take what may be categorised as a  non-majoritarian view, in the check and balance of  power envisaged under the Constitution of India.  One's sexual orientation is undoubtedly an attribute  of privacy. The observations made in Mosley v.  News Group Papers Ltd. [Mosley v. News Group  Papers Ltd., 2008 EWHC 1777 (QB)], in a broader  concept may be usefully referred to:  

“130. … It is not simply a matter of  personal privacy versus the public interest.  The modern perception is that there is a  public interest in respecting personal  privacy. It is thus a question of taking  account of conflicting public interest  considerations and evaluating them  according to increasingly well-recognised  criteria.  

131. When the courts identify an  infringement of a person's Article 8 rights,  and in particular in the context of his  freedom to conduct his sex life and

218

52  

 

personal relationships as he wishes, it is  right to afford a remedy and to vindicate  that right. The only permitted exception is  where there is a countervailing public  interest which in the particular  circumstances is strong enough to  outweigh it; that is to say, because one at  least of the established “limiting principles”  comes into play. Was it necessary and  proportionate for the intrusion to take  place, for example, in order to expose  illegal activity or to prevent the public from  being significantly misled by public claims  hitherto made by the individual concerned  (as with Naomi Campbell's public denials  of drug-taking)? Or was it necessary  because the information, in the words of  the Strasbourg Court in Von Hannover  [Von Hannover v. Germany, (2004) 40  EHRR 1] at pp. 60 and 76, would make a  contribution to “a debate of general  interest”? That is, of course, a very high  test, it is yet to be determined how far that  doctrine will be taken in the courts of this  jurisdiction in relation to photography in  public places. If taken literally, it would  mean a very significant change in what is  permitted. It would have a profound effect  on the tabloid and celebrity culture to which  we have become accustomed in recent  years.”  

 62. Close upon the heels of these three judgments are three  

other important recent decisions.  In Common Cause v. Union  

of India, 2018 5 SCC 1, a case dealing with euthanasia, Dipak  

Misra, C.J., states as under:-

219

53  

 

“166. The purpose of saying so is only to highlight  that the law must take cognizance of the changing  society and march in consonance with the  developing concepts. The need of the present has  to be served with the interpretative process of law.  However, it is to be seen how much strength and  sanction can be drawn from the Constitution to  consummate the changing ideology and convert it  into a reality. The immediate needs are required to  be addressed through the process of interpretation  by the Court unless the same totally falls outside the  constitutional framework or the constitutional  interpretation fails to recognise such dynamism. The  Constitution Bench in Gian Kaur [Gian Kaur v. State  of Punjab, (1996) 2 SCC 648 : 1996 SCC (Cri) 374],  as stated earlier, distinguishes attempt to suicide  and abetment of suicide from acceleration of the  process of natural death which has commenced.  The authorities, we have noted from other  jurisdictions, have observed the distinctions  between the administration of lethal injection or  certain medicines to cause painless death and non- administration of certain treatment which can  prolong the life in cases where the process of dying  that has commenced is not reversible or withdrawal  of the treatment that has been given to the patient  because of the absolute absence of possibility of  saving the life. To explicate, the first part relates to  an overt act whereas the second one would come  within the sphere of informed consent and  authorised omission. The omission of such a nature  will not invite any criminal liability if such action is  guided by certain safeguards. The concept is based  on non-prolongation of life where there is no cure for  the state the patient is in and he, under no  circumstances, would have liked to have such a  degrading state. The words “no cure” have to be  understood to convey that the patient remains in the  same state of pain and suffering or the dying  process is delayed by means of taking recourse to

220

54  

 

modern medical technology. It is a state where the  treating physicians and the family members know  fully well that the treatment is administered only to  procrastinate the continuum of breath of the  individual and the patient is not even aware that he  is breathing. Life is measured by artificial heartbeats  and the patient has to go through this undignified  state which is imposed on him. The dignity of life is  denied to him as there is no other choice but to  suffer an avoidable protracted treatment thereby  thus indubitably casting a cloud and creating a dent  in his right to live with dignity and face death with  dignity, which is a preserved concept of bodily  autonomy and right to privacy. In such a stage, he  has no old memories or any future hopes but he is  in a state of misery which nobody ever desires to  have. Some may also silently think that death, the  inevitable factum of life, cannot be invited. To meet  such situations, the Court has a duty to interpret  Article 21 in a further dynamic manner and it has to  be stated without any trace of doubt that the right to  life with dignity has to include the smoothening of  the process of dying when the person is in a  vegetative state or is living exclusively by the  administration of artificial aid that prolongs the life  by arresting the dignified and inevitable process of  dying. Here, the issue of choice also comes in. Thus  analysed, we are disposed to think that such a right  would come within the ambit of Article 21 of the  Constitution.  

L. Right of self-determination and individual  autonomy  

167. Having dealt with the right to acceleration of  the process of dying a natural death which is  arrested with the aid of modern innovative  technology as a part of Article 21 of the Constitution,  it is necessary to address the issues of right of self- determination and individual autonomy.

221

55  

 

168. John Rawls says that the liberal concept of  autonomy focuses on choice and likewise, self- determination is understood as exercised through  the process of choosing [Rawls, John, Political  Liberalism, 32, 33 (New York: Columbia University  Press, 1993)]. The respect for an individual human  being and in particular for his right to choose how he  should live his own life is individual autonomy or the  right of self-determination. It is the right against non- interference by others, which gives a competent  person who has come of age the right to make  decisions concerning his or her own life and body  without any control or interference of others. Lord  Hoffman, in Reeves v. Commr. of Police of the  Metropolis [Reeves v. Commr. of Police of the  Metropolis, (2000) 1 AC 360 : (1993) 3 WLR 363  (HL)] has stated: (AC p. 369 B)   

“… Autonomy means that every individual  is sovereign over himself and cannot be  denied the right to certain kinds of  behaviour, even if intended to cause his  own death.”  

XXX  

202.8. An inquiry into Common Law jurisdictions  reveals that all adults with capacity to consent have  the right of self-determination and autonomy. The  said rights pave the way for the right to refuse  medical treatment which has acclaimed universal  recognition. A competent person who has come of  age has the right to refuse specific treatment or all  treatment or opt for an alternative treatment, even if  such decision entails a risk of death. The  “Emergency Principle” or the “Principle of Necessity”  has to be given effect to only when it is not  practicable to obtain the patient's consent for  treatment and his/her life is in danger. But where a  patient has already made a valid Advance Directive  which is free from reasonable doubt and specifying

222

56  

 

that he/she does not wish to be treated, then such  directive has to be given effect to.”  

 63. In the same case, Chandrachud J. went on to hold:   

 “437. Under our Constitution, the inherent value  which sanctifies life is the dignity of existence.  Recognising human dignity is intrinsic to preserving  the sanctity of life. Life is truly sanctified when it is  lived with dignity. There exists a close relationship  between dignity and the quality of life. For, it is only  when life can be lived with a true sense of quality  that the dignity of human existence is fully realised.  Hence, there should be no antagonism between the  sanctity of human life on the one hand and the  dignity and quality of life on the other hand. Quality  of life ensures dignity of living and dignity is but a  process in realising the sanctity of life.  

438. Human dignity is an essential element of a  meaningful existence. A life of dignity comprehends  all stages of living including the final stage which  leads to the end of life. Liberty and autonomy are  essential attributes of a life of substance. It is liberty  which enables an individual to decide upon those  matters which are central to the pursuit of a  meaningful existence. The expectation that the  individual should not be deprived of his or her  dignity in the final stage of life gives expression to  the central expectation of a fading life: control over  pain and suffering and the ability to determine the  treatment which the individual should receive. When  society assures to each individual a protection  against being subjected to degrading treatment in  the process of dying, it seeks to assure basic  human dignity. Dignity ensures the sanctity of life.  The recognition afforded to the autonomy of the  individual in matters relating to end-of-life decisions

223

57  

 

is ultimately a step towards ensuring that life does  not despair of dignity as it ebbs away.  

XXX  

441. The protective mantle of privacy covers certain  decisions that fundamentally affect the human life  cycle. [Richard Delgado, “Euthanasia  Reconsidered—The Choice of Death as an Aspect  of the Right of Privacy”, Arizona Law Review (1975),  Vol. 17, at p. 474.] It protects the most personal and  intimate decisions of individuals that affect their life  and development. [Ibid.] Thus, choices and  decisions on matters such as procreation,  contraception and marriage have been held to be  protected. While death is an inevitable end in the  trajectory of the cycle of human life of individuals  are often faced with choices and decisions relating  to death. Decisions relating to death, like those  relating to birth, sex, and marriage, are protected by  the Constitution by virtue of the right of privacy. The  right to privacy resides in the right to liberty and in  the respect of autonomy. [T.L. Beauchamp, “The  Right to Privacy and the Right to Die”, Social  Philosophy and Policy (2000), Vol. 17, at p. 276.]  The right to privacy protects autonomy in making  decisions related to the intimate domain of death as  well as bodily integrity. Few moments could be of as  much importance as the intimate and private  decisions that we are faced regarding death. [Ibid.]  Continuing treatment against the wishes of a patient  is not only a violation of the principle of informed  consent, but also of bodily privacy and bodily  integrity that have been recognised as a facet of  privacy by this Court.”  

 

64. Similarly, in Shafin Jahan v. Asokan K.M., 2018 SCC  

Online 343, this Court was concerned with the right of an adult

224

58  

 

citizen to make her own marital choice. The learned Chief  

Justice referred to Articles 19 and 21 of the Constitution of India  

as follows:-  

“28. Thus, the pivotal purpose of the said writ is to  see that no one is deprived of his/her liberty without  sanction of law. It is the primary duty of the State to  see that the said right is not sullied in any manner  whatsoever and its sanctity is not affected by any  kind of subterfuge. The role of the Court is to see  that the detenue is produced before it, find out about  his/her independent choice and see to it that the  person is released from illegal restraint. The issue  will be a different one when the detention is not  illegal. What is seminal is to remember that the song  of liberty is sung with sincerity and the choice of an  individual is appositely respected and conferred its  esteemed status as the Constitution guarantees. It  is so as the expression of choice is a fundamental  right under Articles 19 and 21 of the Constitution, if  the said choice does not transgress any valid legal  framework. Once that aspect is clear, the enquiry  and determination have to come to an end.  

XXX  

54. It is obligatory to state here that expression of  choice in accord with law is acceptance of individual  identity. Curtailment of that expression and the  ultimate action emanating therefrom on the  conceptual structuralism of obeisance to the societal  will destroy the individualistic entity of a person. The  social values and morals have their space but they  are not above the constitutionally guaranteed  freedom. The said freedom is both a constitutional  and a human right. Deprivation of that freedom  which is ingrained in choice on the plea of faith is  impermissible. Faith of a person is intrinsic to

225

59  

 

his/her meaningful existence. To have the freedom  of faith is essential to his/her autonomy; and it  strengthens the core norms of the Constitution.  Choosing a faith is the substratum of individuality  and sans it, the right of choice becomes a shadow.  It has to be remembered that the realization of a  right is more important than the conferment of the  right. Such actualization indeed ostracises any kind  of societal notoriety and keeps at bay the patriarchal  supremacy. It is so because the individualistic faith  and expression of choice are fundamental for the  fructification of the right. Thus, we would like to call  it indispensable preliminary condition.”  

 

65. In another recent judgment of a three-Judge Bench, in  

Shakti Vahini v. Union of India, 2018 SCC Online SC 275,  

which dealt with honour killings, this Court held:-  

“44. Honour killing guillotines individual liberty,  freedom of choice and one's own perception of  choice. It has to be sublimely borne in mind that  when two adults consensually choose each other as  life partners, it is a manifestation of their choice  which is recognized under Articles 19 and 21 of the  Constitution. Such a right has the sanction of the  constitutional law and once that is recognized, the  said right needs to be protected and it cannot  succumb to the conception of class honour or group  thinking which is conceived of on some notion that  remotely does not have any legitimacy.  

45. The concept of liberty has to be weighed and  tested on the touchstone of constitutional sensitivity,  protection and the values it stands for. It is the  obligation of the Constitutional Courts as the  sentinel on qui vive to zealously guard the right to  liberty of an individual as the dignified existence of

226

60  

 

an individual has an inseparable association with  liberty. Without sustenance of liberty, subject to  constitutionally valid provisions of law, the life of a  person is comparable to the living dead having to  endure cruelty and torture without protest and  tolerate imposition of thoughts and ideas without a  voice to dissent or record a disagreement. The  fundamental feature of dignified existence is to  assert for dignity that has the spark of divinity and  the realization of choice within the parameters of  law without any kind of subjugation. The purpose of  laying stress on the concepts of individual dignity  and choice within the framework of liberty is of  paramount importance. We may clearly and  emphatically state that life and liberty sans dignity  and choice is a phenomenon that allows hollowness  to enter into the constitutional recognition of identity  of a person.  

46. The choice of an individual is an inextricable  part of dignity, for dignity cannot be thought of  where there is erosion of choice. True it is, the same  is bound by the principle of constitutional limitation  but in the absence of such limitation, none, we  mean, no one shall be permitted to interfere in the  fructification of the said choice. If the right to  express one's own choice is obstructed, it would be  extremely difficult to think of dignity in its sanctified  completeness. When two adults marry out of their  volition, they choose their path; they consummate  their relationship; they feel that it is their goal and  they have the right to do so. And it can  unequivocally be stated that they have the right and  any infringement of the said right is a constitutional  violation. The majority in the name of class or  elevated honour of clan cannot call for their  presence or force their appearance as if they are  the monarchs of some indescribable era who have  the power, authority and final say to impose any  sentence and determine the execution of the same  in the way they desire possibly harbouring the

227

61  

 

notion that they are a law unto themselves or they  are the ancestors of Caesar or, for that matter,  Louis the XIV. The Constitution and the laws of this  country do not countenance such an act and, in fact,  the whole activity is illegal and punishable as  offence under the criminal law.”  

 

Mental Healthcare Act, 2017  

66. Parliament is also alive to privacy interests and the fact  

that persons of the same-sex who cohabit with each other are  

entitled to equal treatment.    

67. A recent enactment, namely the Mental Healthcare Act,  

2017, throws a great deal of light on recent parliamentary  

legislative understanding and acceptance of constitutional  

values as reflected by this Court’s judgments. Section 2(s) of  

the Act defines mental illness, which reads as under:  

“2(s) “mental illness” means a substantial disorder  of thinking, mood, perception, orientation or memory  that grossly impairs judgment, behaviour, capacity  to recognise reality or ability to meet the ordinary  demands of life, mental conditions associated with  the abuse of alcohol and drugs, but does not include  mental retardation which is a condition of arrested  or incomplete development of mind of a person,  specially characterised by subnormality of  intelligence;”  

228

62  

 

68. This definition throws to the winds all earlier  

misconceptions of mental illness including the fact that same-

sex couples who indulge in anal sex are persons with mental  

illness.  At one point of time, the thinking in Victorian England  

and early on in America was that homosexuality was to be  

considered as a mental disorder.  The amicus curiae brief of the  

American Psychiatric Association in support of the petitioners in  

Lawrence v. Texas (supra) has put paid to this notion.  This  

brief set out the research that has been done in this area as  

follows:  

“D. The Recognition That Homosexuality Is Not  A “Mental Disorder”   

The American mental health professions concluded  more than a quarter-century ago that homosexuality  is not a mental disorder. That conclusion was  reached after decades of study of homosexuality by  independent researchers, as well as numerous  attempts by practitioners in the mental-health  professions to effectuate a change in individuals’  sexual orientation. During the first half of the 20th  century, many mental health professionals regarded  homosexuality as a pathological condition, but that  perspective reflected untested assumptions  supported largely by clinical impressions of patients  seeking therapy and individuals whose conduct  brought them into the criminal justice system. See  J.C. Gonsiorek, The Empirical Basis for the Demise  of the Illness Model of Homosexuality, in  Homosexuality: Research Implications for Public

229

63  

 

Policy 115 (J.C. Gonsiorek & J.D. Weinrich eds.,  1991). Those assumptions were not subjected to  rigorous scientific scrutiny with nonclinical,  nonincarcerated samples until the latter half of the  century. Once the notion that homosexuality is  linked to mental illness was empirically tested, it  proved to be based on untenable assumptions and  value judgments.   

In one of the first rigorous examinations of the  mental health status of homosexuality, Dr. Evelyn  Hooker administered a battery of standard  psychological tests to homosexual and heterosexual  men who were matched for age, IQ, and education.  See Evelyn Hooker, The Adjustment of the Male  Overt Homosexual, 21 J. Projective Techniques 17- 31 (1957). None of the men was in therapy at the  time of the study. Based on the ratings of expert  judges who were kept unaware of the men’s sexual  orientation, Hooker determined that homosexual  and heterosexual men could not be distinguished  from one another on the basis of the psychological  testing, and that a similar majority of the two groups  appeared to be free of psychopathology. She  concluded from her data that homosexuality is not  inherently associated with psychopathology and that  “homosexuality as a clinical entity does not exist.”  Id. at 18-19. Hooker’s findings were followed over  the next two decades by numerous studies, using a  variety of research techniques, which similarly  concluded that homosexuality is not related to  psychopathology or social maladjustment.  

In 1973, in recognition that scientific data do not  indicate that a homosexual orientation is inherently  associated with psychopathology, amicus American  Psychiatric Association’s Board of Trustees voted to  remove homosexuality from the Psychiatric  Association’s Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of  Mental Disorders. That resolution stated that  “homosexuality per se implies no impairment in

230

64  

 

judgment, stability, reliability, or general social or  vocational capabilities.” Am. Psychiatric Ass’n,  Position Statement on Homosexuality and Civil  Rights (Dec. 15, 1973), printed in 131 Am. J.  Psychiatry 497 (1974). That decision was upheld by  a vote of the Psychiatric Association’s membership  the following year. After a thorough review of the  scientific evidence, amicus American Psychological  Association adopted the same position in 1975, and  urged all mental health professionals to help dispel  the stigma of mental illness that had long been  associated with homosexual orientation. See Am.  Psychol. Ass’n, Minutes of the Annual Meeting of  the Council of Representatives, 30 Am.  Psychologist 620, 633 (1975). Amicus National  Association of Social Workers (NASW) has adopted  a similar policy. See NASW, Policy Statement on  Lesbian and Gay Issues (Aug. 1993) (approved by  NASW Delegate Assembly), reprinted in NASW,  Social Work Speaks: NASW Policy Statements 162  (3d ed. 1994).   

Of course, as is the case for heterosexuals, some  homosexuals have mental illnesses, psychological  disturbances, or poor social adjustment. Gay men,  lesbians, and bisexuals also may be at somewhat  greater risk for some kinds of psychological  problems because of stresses associated with the  experiences of social stigma and prejudice (see pp.  23-27, infra). But research conducted over four  decades has established that “homosexuality in and  of itself bears no necessary relationship to  psychological adjustment.” The efforts to “cure”  homosexuality that were prevalent in earlier  generations—which included hypnosis,  administration of hormones, aversive conditioning  with electric shock or nausea-inducing drugs,  lobotomy, electroshock, and castration—are now  regarded by the mental-health professions as  regrettable.”

231

65  

 

 

69. It also outlined the prejudice, discrimination and violence  

that has been encountered by gay people, as follows:  

“A. Discrimination, Prejudice, And Violence  Encountered By Gay People   

Lesbians and gay men in the United States  encounter extensive prejudice, discrimination, and  violence because of their sexual orientation. Intense  prejudice against gay men and lesbians was  widespread throughout much of the 20th century;  public opinion studies routinely showed that, among  large segments of the public, gay people were the  target of strong antipathy. Although a shift in public  opinion concerning homosexuality occurred in the  1990s, hostility toward gay men and lesbians  remains common in contemporary American  society. Prejudice against bisexuals appears to exist  at comparable levels. Discrimination against gay  people in employment and housing also appears to  remain widespread.  

The severity of this anti-gay prejudice is reflected in  the consistently high rate of anti-gay harassment  and violence in American society. Numerous  surveys indicate that verbal harassment and abuse  are nearly universal experiences of gay people.  Although physical violence is less common,  substantial numbers of gay people report having  experienced crimes against their person or property  because of their sexual orientation. In 2001, the  most recent year for which FBI statistics are  available, there were 1,375 reported bias motivated  incidents against gay men, lesbians, and bisexuals.  That figure likely represents only a fraction of such  crimes, because reporting of hate crimes by law  enforcement agencies is voluntary, the  thoroughness of police statistics differs widely

232

66  

 

among jurisdictions, and many victims do not report  their experiences to police because they fear further  harassment or lack confidence that the assailants  will be caught.   

Although homosexuality is not a mental disorder,  this societal prejudice against gay men and lesbians  can cause them real and substantial psychological  harm. Research indicates that experiencing  rejection, discrimination, and violence is associated  with heightened psychological distress among gay  men and lesbians. These problems are exacerbated  by the fact that, because of anti-gay stigma, gay  men and lesbians have less access to social  support and other resources that assist  heterosexuals in coping with stress. Although many  gay men and lesbians learn to cope with the social  stigma against homosexuality, efforts to avoid that  social stigma through attempts to conceal or  dissimulate sexual orientation can be seriously  damaging to the psychological well-being of gay  people. Lesbians and gay men have been found to  manifest better mental health to the extent that they  feel positively about their sexual orientation and  have integrated it into their lives through “coming  out” and participating in the gay community. Being  able to disclose one’s sexual orientation to others  also increases the availability of social support,  which is crucial to mental health.”  

 

70. Expressing its approval of the position taken by the  

American Psychiatric Association, the Indian Psychiatric  

Society in its recent Position Statement on Homosexuality  

dated 02.07.2018 has stated:-  

233

67  

 

“In the opinion of the Indian Psychiatric Society  (IPS) homosexuality is not a psychiatric disorder.   

This is in line with the position of American  Psychiatric Association and The International  Classification of Diseases of the World health  Organization which removed homosexuality from  the list of psychiatric disorders in 1973 and 1992  respectively.   

The I.P.S recognizes same-sex sexuality as a  normal variant of human sexuality much like  heterosexuality and bisexuality. There is no  scientific evidence that sexual orientation can be  altered by any treatment and that any such attempts  may in fact lead to low self-esteem and  stigmatization of the person.  

The Indian Psychiatric Society further supports de- criminalization of homosexual behavior.”  

 

71. The US Supreme Court, in its decision in Obergefell et  

al. v. Hodges, Director, Ohio Department of Health, et al.,  

576 US (2015), also took note of the enormous sufferings of  

homosexual persons in the time gap between Bowers (supra)  

and Lawrence v. Texas (supra), in the following words:-  

“This is not the first time the Court has been asked  to adopt a cautious approach to recognizing and  protecting fundamental rights. In Bowers, a bare  majority upheld a law criminalizing same-sex  intimacy. See 478 U.S., at 186, 190–195. That  approach might have been viewed as a cautious  endorsement of the democratic process, which had  only just begun to consider the rights of gays and  lesbians. Yet, in effect, Bowers upheld state action

234

68  

 

that denied gays and lesbians a fundamental right  and caused them pain and humiliation. As  evidenced by the dissents in that case, the facts and  principles necessary to a correct holding were  known to the Bowers Court. See id., at 199  (Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, Marshall, and  Stevens, JJ., dissenting); id., at 214 (Stevens, J.,  joined by Brennan and Marshall, JJ., dissenting).  That is why Lawrence held Bowers was “not correct  when it was decided.” 539 U.S., at 578. Although  Bowers was eventually repudiated in Lawrence,  men and women were harmed in the interim, and  the substantial effects of these injuries no doubt  lingered long after Bowers was overruled. Dignitary  wounds cannot always be healed with the stroke of  a pen.”  

 

72. The present definition of mental illness in the 2017  

Parliamentary statute makes it clear that homosexuality is not  

considered to be a mental illness. This is a major advance in  

our law which has been recognized by the Parliament itself.   

Further, this is buttressed by Section 3 of the Act which reads  

as follows:-  

“3. Determination of Mental Illness. (1) Mental  illness shall be determined in accordance with such  nationally or internationally accepted medical  standards (including the latest edition of the  International Classification of Disease of the World  Health Organisation) as may be notified by the  Central Government.   

(2) No person or authority shall classify a person as  a person with mental illness, except for purposes

235

69  

 

directly relating to the treatment of the mental illness  or in other matters as covered under this Act or any  other law for the time being in force.   

(3) Mental illness of a person shall not be  determined on the basis of––   

(a) political, economic or social status or  membership of a cultural, racial or religious  group, or for any other reason not directly  relevant to mental health status of the person;   

(b) non-conformity with moral, social, cultural,  work or political values or religious beliefs  prevailing in a person’s community.   

(4) Past treatment or hospitalisation in a mental  health establishment though relevant, shall not  by itself justify any present or future  determination of the person’s mental illness.   

(5) The determination of a person’s mental  illness shall alone not imply or be taken to  mean that the person is of unsound mind  unless he has been declared as such by a  competent court.”  

 

73. Mental illness in our statute has to keep pace with  

international notions and accepted medical standards including  

the latest edition of the International Classification of Diseases  

of the World Health Organization under Section 3(1) of the Act.   

Under Section 3(3), mental illness shall not be determined on  

the basis of social status or membership of a cultural group or  

for any other reason not directly relevant to the mental health of

236

70  

 

the person. More importantly, mental illness shall not be  

determined on the basis of non-conformity with moral, social,  

cultural, work or political values or religious beliefs prevailing in  

a person’s community.  It is thus clear that Parliament has  

unequivocally declared that the earlier stigma attached to  

same-sex couples, as persons who are regarded as mentally ill,  

has gone for good.  This is another very important step forward  

taken by the legislature itself which has undermined one of the  

basic underpinnings of the judgment in Suresh Kumar  

Koushal (supra).    

Section 21(1)(a) is important and set out hereinbelow:  

“21. Right to equality and non-discrimination. (1)  Every person with mental illness shall be treated as  equal to persons with physical illness in the  provision of all healthcare which shall include the  following, namely:–  

(a) there shall be no discrimination on any basis  including gender, sex, sexual orientation,  religion, culture, caste, social or political  beliefs, class or disability;”  

 

74. This Section is parliamentary recognition of the fact that  

gay persons together with other persons are liable to be  

affected with mental illness, and shall be treated as equal to the

237

71  

 

other persons with such illness as there is to be no  

discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation.  Section 30 is  

extremely important and reads as under:  

“30. Creating awareness about mental health  and illness and reducing stigma associated with  mental illness.   The appropriate Government shall take all  measures to ensure that,—  (a) the provisions of this Act are given wide publicity  through public media, including television, radio,  print and online media at regular intervals;  (b) the programmes to reduce stigma associated  with mental illness are planned, designed, funded  and implemented in an effective manner;  (c) the appropriate Government officials including  police officers and other officers of the appropriate  Government are given periodic sensitisation and  awareness training on the issues under this Act.”    

75. Section 115 largely does away with one other outmoded  

Section of the Indian Penal Code, namely, Section 309. This  

Section reads as follows.   

“115. Presumption of severe stress in case of  attempt to commit suicide. (1) Notwithstanding  anything contained in section 309 of the Indian  Penal Code any person who attempts to commit  suicide shall be presumed, unless proved otherwise,  to have severe stress and shall not be tried and  punished under the said Code.  

(2) The appropriate Government shall have a duty  to provide care, treatment and rehabilitation to a  person, having severe stress and who attempted to

238

72  

 

commit suicide, to reduce the risk of recurrence of  attempt to commit suicide.”  

 

76. Instead of the inhumane Section 309 which has remained  

on the statute book for over 150 years, Section 115 makes it  

clear that Section 309 is rendered largely ineffective, and on the  

contrary, instead of committing a criminal offence, any person  

who attempts to commit suicide shall be presumed to have  

severe stress and shall not be tried and punished under Section  

309 of the Indian Penal Code.  More importantly, the  

Government has an affirmative duty to provide care, treatment  

and rehabilitation to such a person to reduce the risk of  

recurrence of that person’s attempt to commit suicide. This  

parliamentary declaration under Section 115 again is in keeping  

with the present constitutional values, making it clear that  

humane measures are to be taken by the Government in  

respect of a person who attempts to commit suicide instead of  

prosecuting him for the offence of attempt to commit suicide.    

77. And finally, Section 120 of the Act reads as under:-  

“120. Act to have overriding effect. The provisions  of this Act shall have overriding effect  notwithstanding anything inconsistent therewith

239

73  

 

contained in any other law for the time being in force  or in any instrument having effect by virtue of any  law other than this Act.”  

 

78. The Latin maxim cessant ratione legis, cessat ipsa lex,  

meaning when the reason for a law ceases, the law itself  

ceases, is a rule of law which has been recognized by this  

Court in H.H. Shri Swamiji of Shri Amar Mutt v.  

Commissioner, Hindu Religious and Charitable  

Endowments Dept, 1979 4 SCC 642 at paragraph 29, and  

State of Punjab v. Devans Modern Breweries Ltd., (2004) 11  

SCC 26 at paragraph 335.  It must not be forgotten that Section  

377 was the product of the Victorian era, with its attendant  

puritanical moral values. Victorian morality must give way to  

constitutional morality as has been recognized in many of our  

judgments. Constitutional morality is the soul of the  

Constitution, which is to be found in the Preamble of the  

Constitution, which declares its ideals and aspirations, and is  

also to be found in Part III of the Constitution, particularly with  

respect to those provisions which assure the dignity of the  

individual.  The rationale for Section 377, namely Victorian  

morality, has long gone and there is no reason to continue with

240

74  

 

- as Justice Holmes said in the lines quoted above in this  

judgment - a law merely for the sake of continuing with the law  

when the rationale of such law has long since disappeared.   

79. Given our judgment in Puttaswamy (supra), in particular,  

the right of every citizen of India to live with dignity and the right  

to privacy including the right to make intimate choices regarding  

the manner in which such individual wishes to live being  

protected by Articles 14, 19 and 21, it is clear that Section 377,  

insofar as it applies to same-sex consenting adults, demeans  

them by having them prosecuted instead of understanding their  

sexual orientation and attempting to correct centuries of the  

stigma associated with such persons.   

80. The Union of India, seeing the writing on the wall, has  

filed an affidavit in which it has not opposed the Petitioners but  

left the matter to be considered by the wisdom of this Court.   

Some of the intervenors have argued in favour of the retention  

of Section 377 qua consenting adults on the grounds that  

homosexual acts are not by themselves proscribed by Section  

377.  Unless there is penetration in the manner pointed out by  

the explanation to the Section, no offence takes place. They

241

75  

 

have also added that the Section needs to be retained given  

the fact that it is only a parliamentary reflection of the prevailing  

social mores of today in large segments of society. According to  

them, this furthers a compelling state interest to reinforce  

morals in public life which is not disproportionate in nature.  We  

are afraid that, given the march of events in constitutional law  

by this Court, and parliamentary recognition of the plight of  

such persons in certain provisions of the Mental Healthcare Act,  

2017, it will not be open for a constitutional court to substitute  

societal morality with constitutional morality, as has been stated  

by us hereinabove. Further, as stated in S. Khushboo v.  

Kanniammal and Anr., (2010) 5 SCC 600, at paragraphs 46  

and 50, this Court made it clear that notions of social morality  

are inherently subjective and the criminal law cannot be used  

as a means to unduly interfere with the domain of personal  

autonomy. Morality and criminality are not co-extensive - sin is  

not punishable on earth by Courts set up by the State but  

elsewhere; crime alone is punishable on earth. To confuse the  

one with the other is what causes the death knell of Section  

377, insofar as it applies to consenting homosexual adults.

242

76  

 

81. Another argument raised on behalf of the intervenors is  

that change in society, if any, can be reflected by amending  

laws by the elected representatives of the people. Thus, it  

would be open to the Parliament to carve out an exception from  

Section 377, but this Court should not indulge in taking upon  

itself the guardianship of changing societal mores. Such an  

argument must be emphatically rejected. The very purpose of  

the fundamental rights chapter in the Constitution of India is to  

withdraw the subject of liberty and dignity of the individual and  

place such subject beyond the reach of majoritarian  

governments so that constitutional morality can be applied by  

this Court to give effect to the rights, among others, of ‘discrete  

and insular’ minorities.6  One such minority has knocked on the  

doors of this Court as this Court is the custodian of the  

fundamental rights of citizens. These fundamental rights do not  

depend upon the outcome of elections. And, it is not left to  

majoritarian governments to prescribe what shall be orthodox in  

matters concerning social morality. The fundamental rights  

chapter is like the north star in the universe of constitutionalism  

                                                           6 This phrase occurs in one of the most celebrated footnotes in the US Supreme Court’s constitutional  history – namely, Footnote 4 of United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144 (1938).

243

77  

 

in India.7 Constitutional morality always trumps any imposition  

of a particular view of social morality by shifting and different  

majoritarian regimes.   

82. Insofar as Article 14 is concerned, this Court in Shayara  

Bano v. Union of India, (2017) 9 SCC 1, has stated, in  

paragraph 101, that a statutory provision can be struck down on  

the ground of manifest arbitrariness, when the provision is  

capricious, irrational and/or without adequate determining  

principle, as also if it is excessive or disproportionate. We find  

that Section 377, in penalizing consensual gay sex, is  

manifestly arbitrary. Given modern psychiatric studies and  

legislation which recognizes that gay persons and transgenders  

are not persons suffering from mental disorder and cannot  

therefore be penalized, the Section must be held to be a  

provision which is capricious and irrational. Also, roping in such  

persons with sentences going upto life imprisonment is clearly  

excessive and disproportionate, as a result of which, when  

applied to such persons, Articles 14 and 21 of the Constitution                                                              7 In William Shakespeare’s Julius Caesar (Act III, Scene 1), Caesar tells Cassius-   

“I could be well moved, if I were as you;  If I could pray to move, prayers would move me:  

But I am constant as the Northern Star,  Of whose true-fixed and resting quality  

There is no fellow in the firmament.”

244

78  

 

would clearly be violated. The object sought to be achieved by  

the provision, namely to enforce Victorian mores upon the  

citizenry of India, would be out of tune with the march of  

constitutional events that has since taken place, rendering the  

said object itself discriminatory when it seeks to single out  

same-sex couples and transgenders for punishment.   

83. As has been stated in the judgment of Nariman, J. in  

Shreya Singhal v. Union of India, (2015) 5 SCC 1, the chilling  

effect caused by such a provision would also violate a privacy  

right under Article 19(1)(a), which can by no stretch of  

imagination be said to be a reasonable restriction in the interest  

of decency or morality (See paragraphs 87 to 94).   

84. We may hasten to add, that the Yogyakarta Principles on  

the Application of International Human Rights Law in relation to  

Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity discussed below, which  

were also referred to by Radhakrishnan, J. in NALSA  (supra),  

conform to our constitutional view of the fundamental rights of  

the citizens of India and persons who come to this Court.

245

79  

 

85. The International Commission of Jurists and the  

International Service for Human Rights, on behalf of a coalition  

of human rights organisations, had undertaken a project to  

develop a set of international legal principles on the application  

of international law to human rights violations based on sexual  

orientation and gender identity to bring greater clarity and  

coherence to States’ human rights obligations.  

86. A distinguished group of human rights experts drafted,  

developed, discussed and refined these Principles. Following  

an experts’ meeting held at Gadjah Mada University in  

Yogyakarta, Indonesia from 6th to 9th November, 2006, 29  

distinguished experts from 25 countries with diverse  

backgrounds and expertise relevant to issues of human rights  

law unanimously adopted the Yogyakarta Principles on the  

Application of International Human Rights Law in relation to  

Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity.   

87. A few relevant extracts from the Yogyakarta Principles  

and its Preamble are as follows:-  

246

80  

 

“Preamble  

WE, THE INTERNATIONAL PANEL OF EXPERTS IN  INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS LAW AND ON SEXUAL  ORIENTATION AND GENDER IDENTITY,  

XX  

XX  

UNDERSTANDING ‘sexual orientation’ to refer to each  person’s capacity for profound emotional, affectional  and sexual attraction to, and intimate and sexual  relations with, individuals of a different gender or the  same gender or more than one gender;  

XX  

XX  

FOLLOWING AN EXPERTS’ MEETING HELD IN  YOGYAKARTA, INDONESIA FROM 6 TO 9 NOVEMBER  2006, HEREBY ADOPT THESE PRINCIPLES:  

1. The right to the universal enjoyment of human  rights.—All human beings are born free and equal  in dignity and rights. Human beings of all sexual  orientations and gender identities are entitled to the  full enjoyment of all human rights.  

 

States shall:  

(a) embody the principles of the universality,  interrelatedness, interdependence and indivisibility  of all human rights in their national constitutions or  other appropriate legislation and ensure the  practical realisation of the universal enjoyment of all  human rights;  

(b) amend any legislation, including criminal law, to  ensure its consistency with the universal enjoyment  of all human rights;  

(c) undertake programmes of education and  awareness to promote and enhance the full

247

81  

 

enjoyment of all human rights by all persons,  irrespective of sexual orientation or gender identity;  

(d) integrate within State policy and decision making  a pluralistic approach that recognises and affirms  the interrelatedness and indivisibility of all aspects  of human identity including sexual orientation and  gender identity.  

 

2. The rights to equality and non- discrimination.—Everyone is entitled to enjoy all  human rights without discrimination on the basis of  sexual orientation or gender identity. Everyone is  entitled to equality before the law and the equal  protection of the law without any such discrimination  whether or not the enjoyment of another human  right is also affected. The law shall prohibit any such  discrimination and guarantee to all persons equal  and effective protection against any such  discrimination.  

Discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation or  gender identity includes any distinction, exclusion,  restriction or preference based on sexual orientation  or gender identity which has the purpose or effect of  nullifying or impairing equality before the law or the  equal protection of the law, or the recognition,  enjoyment or exercise, on an equal basis, of all  human rights and fundamental freedoms.  Discrimination based on sexual orientation or  gender identity may be, and commonly is,  compounded by discrimination on other grounds  including gender, race, age, religion, disability,  health and economic status.  

 

States shall:  

(a) embody the principles of equality and non- discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation and  gender identity in their national constitutions or other  appropriate legislation, if not yet incorporated  therein, including by means of amendment and

248

82  

 

interpretation, and ensure the effective realisation of  these principles;  

(b) repeal criminal and other legal provisions that  prohibit or are, in effect, employed to prohibit  consensual sexual activity among people of the  same-sex who are over the age of consent, and  ensure that an equal age of consent applies to both  same-sex and different-sex sexual activity;  

(c) adopt appropriate legislative and other measures  to prohibit and eliminate discrimination in the public  and private spheres on the basis of sexual  orientation and gender identity;  

(d) take appropriate measures to secure adequate  advancement of persons of diverse sexual  orientations and gender identities as may be  necessary to ensure such groups or individuals  equal enjoyment or exercise of human rights. Such  measures shall not be deemed to be discriminatory;  

(e) in all their responses to discrimination on the  basis of sexual orientation or gender identity, take  account of the manner in which such discrimination  may intersect with other forms of discrimination;  

(f) take all appropriate action, including programmes  of education and training, with a view to achieving  the elimination of prejudicial or discriminatory  attitudes or behaviours which are related to the idea  of the inferiority or the superiority of any sexual  orientation or gender identity or gender expression.  

 

3. The right to recognition before the law.— Everyone has the right to recognition everywhere as  a person before the law. Persons of diverse sexual  orientations and gender identities shall enjoy legal  capacity in all aspects of life. Each person's self- defined sexual orientation and gender identity is  integral to their personality and is one of the most  basic aspects of self-determination, dignity and  freedom. No one shall be forced to undergo medical  procedures, including sex reassignment surgery,

249

83  

 

sterilisation or hormonal therapy, as a requirement  for legal recognition of their gender identity. No  status, such as marriage or parenthood, may be  invoked as such to prevent the legal recognition of a  person's gender identity. No one shall be subjected  to pressure to conceal, suppress or deny their  sexual orientation or gender identity.  

 

States shall:  

(a) ensure that all persons are accorded legal  capacity in civil matters, without discrimination on  the basis of sexual orientation or gender identity,  and the opportunity to exercise that capacity,  including equal rights to conclude contracts, and to  administer, own, acquire (including through  inheritance), manage, enjoy and dispose of  property;  

(b) take all necessary legislative, administrative and  other measures to fully respect and legally  recognise each person's self-defined gender  identity;  

(c) take all necessary legislative, administrative and  other measures to ensure that procedures exist  whereby all State-issued identity papers which  indicate a person's gender/sex—including birth  certificates, passports, electoral records and other  documents—reflect the person's profound self- defined gender identity;  

(d) ensure that such procedures are efficient, fair  and non-discriminatory, and respect the dignity and  privacy of the person concerned;  

(e) ensure that changes to identity documents will  be recognised in all contexts where the identification  or disaggregation of persons by gender is required  by law or policy;  

(f) undertake targeted programmes to provide social  support for all persons experiencing gender  transitioning or reassignment.  

250

84  

 

XXX  

 

4. The right to life.—Everyone has the right to life.  No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of life, including  by reference to considerations of sexual orientation  or gender identity. The death penalty shall not be  imposed on any person on the basis of consensual  sexual activity among persons who are over the age  of consent or on the basis of sexual orientation or  gender identity.  

 

States shall:  

(a) repeal all forms of crime that have the purpose  or effect of prohibiting consensual sexual activity  among persons of the same-sex who are over the  age of consent and, until such provisions are  repealed, never impose the death penalty on any  person convicted under them;  

(b) remit sentences of death and release all those  currently awaiting execution for crimes relating to  consensual sexual activity among persons who are  over the age of consent;  

(c) cease any State-sponsored or State-condoned  attacks on the lives of persons based on sexual  orientation or gender identity, and ensure that all  such attacks, whether by government officials or by  any individual or group, are vigorously investigated,  and that, where appropriate evidence is found,  those responsible are prosecuted, tried and duly  punished.  

 

XXX  

 

6. The right to privacy.—Everyone, regardless of  sexual orientation or gender identity, is entitled to  the enjoyment of privacy without arbitrary or  unlawful interference, including with regard to their  family, home or correspondence as well as to  protection from unlawful attacks on their honour and

251

85  

 

reputation. The right to privacy ordinarily includes  the choice to disclose or not to disclose information  relating to one's sexual orientation or gender  identity, as well as decisions and choices regarding  both one's own body and consensual sexual and  other relations with others.  

 

States shall:  

(a) take all necessary legislative, administrative and  other measures to ensure the right of each person,  regardless of sexual orientation or gender identity,  to enjoy the private sphere, intimate decisions, and  human relations, including consensual sexual  activity among persons who are over the age of  consent, without arbitrary interference;  

(b) repeal all laws that criminalise consensual  sexual activity among persons of the same-sex who  are over the age of consent, and ensure that an  equal age of consent applies to both same-sex and  different-sex sexual activity;  

(c) ensure that criminal and other legal provisions of  general application are not applied de facto to  criminalise consensual sexual activity among  persons of the same-sex who are over the age of  consent;  

(d) repeal any law that prohibits or criminalises the  expression of gender identity, including through  dress, speech or mannerisms, or that denies to  individuals the opportunity to change their bodies as  a means of expressing their gender identity;  

(e) release all those held on remand or on the basis  of a criminal conviction, if their detention is related  to consensual sexual activity among persons who  are over the age of consent, or is related to gender  identity;  

(f) ensure the right of all persons ordinarily to  choose when, to whom and how to disclose  information pertaining to their sexual orientation or  gender identity, and protect all persons from

252

86  

 

arbitrary or unwanted disclosure, or threat of  disclosure of such information by others.  

 

XXX  

 

18. Protection from medical abuses.—No person  may be forced to undergo any form of medical or  psychological treatment, procedure, testing, or be  confined to a medical facility, based on sexual  orientation or gender identity. Notwithstanding any  classifications to the contrary, a person's sexual  orientation and gender identity are not, in and of  themselves, medical conditions and are not to be  treated, cured or suppressed.  

 

States shall:  

(a) take all necessary legislative, administrative and  other measures to ensure full protection against  harmful medical practices based on sexual  orientation or gender identity, including on the basis  of stereotypes, whether derived from culture or  otherwise, regarding conduct, physical appearance  or perceived gender norms;  

(b) take all necessary legislative, administrative and  other measures to ensure that no child's body is  irreversibly altered by medical procedures in an  attempt to impose a gender identity without the full,  free and informed consent of the child in  accordance with the age and maturity of the child  and guided by the principle that in all actions  concerning children, the best interests of the child  shall be a primary consideration;  

(c) establish child protection mechanisms whereby  no child is at risk of, or subjected to, medical abuse;  

(d) ensure protection of persons of diverse sexual  orientations and gender identities against unethical  or involuntary medical procedures or research,  including in relation to vaccines, treatments or  microbicides for HIV/AIDS or other diseases;

253

87  

 

(e) review and amend any health funding provisions  or programmes, including those of a development- assistance nature, which may promote, facilitate or  in any other way render possible such abuses;  

(f) ensure that any medical or psychological  treatment or counselling does not, explicitly or  implicitly, treat sexual orientation and gender  identity as medical conditions to be treated, cured or  suppressed.  

 

19. The right to freedom of opinion and  expression.— Everyone has the right to freedom of  opinion and expression, regardless of sexual  orientation or gender identity. This includes the  expression of identity or personhood through  speech, deportment, dress, bodily characteristics,  choice of name, or any other means, as well as the  freedom to seek, receive and impart information and  ideas of all kinds, including with regard to human  rights, sexual orientation and gender identity,  through any medium and regardless of frontiers.  

 

States shall:  

(a) take all necessary legislative, administrative and  other measures to ensure full enjoyment of freedom  of opinion and expression, while respecting the  rights and freedoms of others, without discrimination  on the basis of sexual orientation or gender identity,  including the receipt and imparting of information  and ideas concerning sexual orientation and gender  identity, as well as related advocacy for legal rights,  publication of materials, broadcasting, organisation  of or participation in conferences, and dissemination  of and access to safer-sex information;  

(b) ensure that the outputs and the organisation of  media that is State-regulated is pluralistic and non- discriminatory in respect of issues of sexual  orientation and gender identity and that the  personnel recruitment and promotion policies of

254

88  

 

such organisations are non-discriminatory on the  basis of sexual orientation or gender identity;  

(c) take all necessary legislative, administrative and  other measures to ensure the full enjoyment of the  right to express identity or personhood, including  through speech, deportment, dress, bodily  characteristics, choice of name or any other means;  

(d) ensure that notions of public order, public  morality, public health and public security are not  employed to restrict, in a discriminatory manner, any  exercise of freedom of opinion and expression that  affirms diverse sexual orientations or gender  identities;  

(e) ensure that the exercise of freedom of opinion  and expression does not violate the rights and  freedoms of persons of diverse sexual orientations  and gender identities;  

(f) ensure that all persons, regardless of sexual  orientation or gender identity, enjoy equal access to  information and ideas, as well as to participation in  public debate.”  

(Emphasis supplied)  

 88. These principles give further content to the fundamental  

rights contained in Articles 14, 15, 19 and 21, and viewed in the  

light of these principles also, Section 377 will have to be  

declared to be unconstitutional.   

89. Given the aforesaid, it has now to be decided as to  

whether the judgment in Suresh Kumar Koushal (supra) is  

correct. Suresh Kumar Koushal’s judgment (supra) first  

begins with the presumption of constitutionality attaching to pre-

255

89  

 

constitutional laws, such as the Indian Penal Code. The  

judgment goes on to state that pre-constitutional laws, which  

have been adopted by Parliament and used with or without  

amendment, being manifestations of the will of the people of  

India through Parliament, are presumed to be constitutional.   

We are afraid that we cannot agree.    

90. Article 372 of the Constitution of India continues laws in  

force in the territory of India immediately before the  

commencement of the Constitution. That the Indian Penal Code  

is a law in force in the territory of India immediately before the  

commencement of this Constitution is beyond cavil.  Under  

Article 372(2), the President may, by order, make such  

adaptations and modifications of an existing law as may be  

necessary or expedient to bring such law in accord with the  

provisions of the Constitution. The fact that the President has  

not made any adaptation or modification as mentioned in Article  

372(2) does not take the matter very much further. The  

presumption of constitutionality of a statute is premised on the  

fact that Parliament understands the needs of the people, and  

that, as per the separation of powers doctrine, Parliament is

256

90  

 

aware of its limitations in enacting laws – it can only enact laws  

which do not fall within List II of Schedule VII of the Constitution  

of India, and cannot transgress the fundamental rights of the  

citizens and other constitutional provisions in doing so.  

Parliament is therefore deemed to be aware of the aforesaid  

constitutional limitations. Where, however, a pre-constitution  

law is made by either a foreign legislature or body, none of  

these parameters obtain. It is therefore clear that no such  

presumption attaches to a pre-constitutional statute like the  

Indian Penal Code.  In fact, in the majority judgment of B.P.  

Jeevan Reddy, J. in New Delhi Municipal Council v. State of  

Punjab and Ors., (1997) 7 SCC 339, the Punjab Municipal Act  

of 1911 was deemed to be a post-constitutional law inasmuch  

as it was extended to Delhi only in 1950, as a result of which  

the presumption of constitutionality was raised. Ahmadi, C.J.’s  

dissenting opinion correctly states that if a pre-constitutional law  

is challenged, the presumption of constitutional validity would  

not obtain. The relevant paragraph is extracted below:-  

“119. Reddy, J. has taken the view that the Doctrine  of Presumption of Constitutionality of Legislations  requires the saving of the taxes which these Acts  impose upon the commercial activities of State

257

91  

 

Governments. The Act is a pre-constitutional  enactment. The basis of this doctrine is the  assumed intention of the legislators not to  transgress constitutional boundaries. It is difficult to  appreciate how that intention can be assumed  when, at the time that the law was passed, there  was no such barrier and the limitation was brought  in by a Constitution long after the enactment of the  law. (This Court has in a Constitution Bench  decision, Gulabbhai Vallabbhai Desai v. Union of  India [AIR 1967 SC 1110 : (1967) 1 SCR 602] , (AIR  at p. 1117 raised doubts along similar lines). The  Framers obviously wanted the law under Article  289(2) to be of a very high standard. Can these  laws, which are silent on the most important aspect  required by Article 289(2), i.e., the specification of  the trading activities of State Governments which  would be liable to Union taxation, be said to meet  with that standard?”  

 

91. It is a little difficult to subscribe to the view of the Division  

Bench that the presumption of constitutionality of Section 377  

would therefore attach.  

92. The fact that the legislature has chosen not to amend the  

law, despite the 172nd Law Commission Report specifically  

recommending deletion of Section 377, may indicate that  

Parliament has not thought it proper to delete the aforesaid  

provision, is one more reason for not invalidating Section 377,  

according to Suresh Kumar Koushal (supra). This is a little  

difficult to appreciate when the Union of India admittedly did not

258

92  

 

challenge the Delhi High Court judgment striking down the  

provision in part.  Secondly, the fact that Parliament may or  

may not have chosen to follow a Law Commission Report does  

not guide the Court’s understanding of its character, scope,  

ambit and import as has been stated in Suresh Kumar  

Koushal (supra).  It is a neutral fact which need not be taken  

into account at all.  All that the Court has to see is whether  

constitutional provisions have been transgressed and if so, as a  

natural corollary, the death knell of the challenged provision  

must follow.   

93. It is a little difficult to appreciate the Court stating that the  

ambit of Section 377 IPC is only determined with reference to  

the sexual act itself and the circumstances in which it is  

executed. It is also a little difficult to appreciate that Section 377  

regulates sexual conduct regardless of gender identity and  

orientation.    

94. After 2013, when Section 375 was amended so as to  

include anal and certain other kinds of sexual intercourse  

between a man and a woman, which would not be criminalized  

as rape if it was between consenting adults, it is clear that if

259

93  

 

Section 377 continues to penalize such sexual intercourse, an  

anomalous position would result. A man indulging in such  

sexual intercourse would not be liable to be prosecuted for rape  

but would be liable to be prosecuted under Section 377.  

Further, a woman who could, at no point of time, have been  

prosecuted for rape would, despite her consent, be prosecuted  

for indulging in anal or such other sexual intercourse with a  

man in private under Section 377. This would render Section  

377, as applied to such consenting adults, as manifestly  

arbitrary as it would be wholly excessive and disproportionate  

to prosecute such persons under Section 377 when the  

legislature has amended one portion of the law in 2013, making  

it clear that consensual sex, as described in the amended  

provision, between two consenting adults, one a man and one a  

woman, would not be liable for prosecution. If, by having regard  

to what has been said above, Section 377 has to be read down  

as not applying to anal and such other sex by a male-female  

couple, then the Section will continue to apply only to  

homosexual sex. If this be the case, the Section will offend  

Article 14 as it will discriminate between heterosexual and

260

94  

 

homosexual adults which is a distinction which has no rational  

relation to the object sought to be achieved by the Section -  

namely, the criminalization of all carnal sex between  

homosexual and/or heterosexual adults as being against the  

order of nature.8 Viewed either way, the Section falls foul of  

Article 14.  

95. The fact that only a minuscule fraction of the country’s  

population constitutes lesbians and gays or transgenders, and  

that in the last 150 years less than 200 persons have been  

prosecuted for committing the offence under Section 377, is  

neither here nor there. When it is found that privacy interests  

come in and the State has no compelling reason to continue an  

existing law which penalizes same-sex couples who cause no  

harm to others, on an application of the recent judgments  

delivered by this Court after Suresh Kumar Koushal (supra), it  

is clear that Articles 14, 15, 19 and 21 have all been  

transgressed without any legitimate state rationale to uphold  

such provision.    

                                                           8 An argument was made by the Petitioners that Section 377, being vague and unintelligible, should be  struck down on this ground as it is not clear as to what is meant by “against the order of nature”. Since  Section 377 applies down the line to carnal sex between human beings and animals as well, which is not  the subject matter of challenge here, it is unnecessary to go into this ground as the Petitioners have  succeeded on other grounds raised by them.  

261

95  

 

96. For all these reasons therefore, we are of the view that,  

Suresh Kumar Koushal (supra) needs to be, and is hereby,  

overruled.   

97. We may conclude by stating that persons who are  

homosexual have a fundamental right to live with dignity, which,  

in the larger framework of the Preamble of India, will assure the  

cardinal constitutional value of fraternity that has been  

discussed in some of our judgments (See (1) Nandini Sundar v.  

State of Chhattisgarh, (2011) 7 SCC 547 at paragraphs 16, 25  

and 52; and (2) Subramaniam Swamy v. Union of India (2016)  

7 SCC 221 at paragraphs 153 to 156).  We further declare that  

such groups are entitled to the protection of equal laws, and are  

entitled to be treated in society as human beings without any  

stigma being attached to any of them.  We further declare that  

Section 377 insofar as it criminalises homosexual sex and  

transgender sex between consenting adults is unconstitutional.   

98. We are also of the view that the Union of India shall take  

all measures to ensure that this judgment is given wide publicity  

through the public media, which includes television, radio, print  

and online media at regular intervals, and initiate programs to

262

96  

 

reduce and finally eliminate the stigma associated with such  

persons. Above all, all government officials, including and in  

particular police officials, and other officers of the Union of India  

and the States, be given periodic sensitization and awareness  

training of the plight of such persons in the light of the  

observations contained in this judgment.    

 

 

             ……………………………..J.         (R.F. Nariman)      

New Delhi;  September 06, 2018.

263

1    

     

IN THE SUPREME COURT OF INDIA  CRIMINAL/CIVIL ORIGINAL JURISDICTION  

 WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL) NO 76 OF 2016  

   

 

NAVTEJ SINGH JOHAR & ORS.                ...Petitioner   

 

VERSUS  

   UNION OF INDIA, THR. SECRETARY,   MINISTRY OF LAW AND JUSTICE                …Respondent     

WITH  

 

WRIT PETITION (CIVIL)  NO 572   OF 2016      

AKKAI PADMASHALI                 ...Petitioner   

 

VERSUS  

   UNION OF INDIA, THR.SECRETARY,   MINISTRY OF LAW AND JUSTICE                ...Respondent     

 

REPORTABLE

264

2    

WITH  

 

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL)  NO 88   OF 2018      

KESHAV SURI                           ...Petitioner   

 

VERSUS  

   UNION OF INDIA                            ...Respondent     

WITH  

 

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL)  NO 100   OF 2018      

ARIF JAFAR                         ...Petitioner   

 

VERSUS  

   UNION OF INDIA AND ORS.                         ...Respondents     

WITH  

 

 

265

3    

WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL)  NO 101   OF 2018    

 ASHOK ROW KAVI AND ORS.                      ...Petitioners   

 

VERSUS  

 UNION OF INDIA AND ORS.                         ...Respondents   

 

AND  

  

WITH  

 WRIT PETITION (CRIMINAL)  NO 121   OF 2018  

   

ANWESH POKKULURI AND ORS.                       ...Petitioners  

  

VERSUS  

 UNION OF INDIA                           ...Respondent     

     J U D G M E N T   

 

Index to the judgment  

 

A  From denial to freedom    B “To the wisdom of the Court”   

266

4    

C From “The Ashes of the Gay”    

C.I “Arc of the moral universe”    

D An equal love     E Beyond physicality: sex, identity and stereotypes  

E.I Facial neutrality: through the looking glass   

E.2 Deconstructing the polarities of binary genders   

  F Confronting the closet   

F.I Sexual privacy and autonomy- deconstructing the heteronormative  

framework  

F.2 A right to intimacy- celebration of sexual agency  

 

G Section 377 and the right to health  

G.I Section 377 and HIV prevention efforts  

G.2 Mental health  

 H Judicial review    I India’s commitments at International Law    J Transcending borders - comparative law    K Crime, morality and the Constitution    L Constitutional morality     M In summation : transformative constitutionalism

 

 

267

PART A   

5    

Dr Dhananjaya Y Chandrachud, J  

 A  From denial to freedom    

“What makes life meaningful is love. The right that  

makes us human is the right to love. To criminalize the  

expression of that right is profoundly cruel and  

inhumane. To acquiesce in such criminalization, or  

worse, to recriminalize it, is to display the very  

opposite of compassion. To show exaggerated  

deference to a majoritarian Parliament when the  

matter is one of fundamental rights is to display judicial  

pusillanimity, for there is no doubt, that in the  

constitutional scheme, it is the judiciary that is the  

ultimate interpreter.”1  

 

1 The lethargy of the law is manifest yet again.  

  

2 A hundred and fifty eight years ago, a colonial legislature made it  

criminal, even for consenting adults of the same gender, to find fulfillment in  

love. The law deprived them of the simple right as human beings to live, love  

and partner as nature made them. The human instinct to love was caged by  

constraining the physical manifestation of their sexuality. Gays and lesbians2  

were made subordinate to the authority of a coercive state. A charter of  

morality made their relationships hateful. The criminal law became a willing  

instrument of repression. To engage in ‘carnal intercourse’ against ‘the order  

of nature’ risked being tucked away for ten years in a jail. The offence would  

                                                           1    Justice Leila Seth, “A mother and a judge speaks out on Section 377”, The Times of India, 26 January, 2014.  2   These terms as well as terms such as “LGBT” and “LGBTIQ” used in the judgement are to be construed in an  

inclusive sense to include members of all gender and sexual minorities, whose sexual activity is criminalized by  the application of Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code, 1860.    

268

PART A   

6    

be investigated by searching the most intimate of spaces to find tell-tale signs  

of intercourse. Civilisation has been brutal.  

 

3 Eighty seven years after the law was made, India gained her liberation  

from a colonial past. But Macaulay’s legacy - the offence under Section 377 of  

the Penal Code - has continued to exist for nearly sixty eight years after we  

gave ourselves a liberal Constitution. Gays and lesbians, transgenders and  

bisexuals continue to be denied a truly equal citizenship seven decades after  

Independence. The law has imposed upon them a morality which is an  

anachronism. Their entitlement should be as equal participants in a society  

governed by the morality of the Constitution. That in essence is what Section  

377 denies to them. The shadows of a receding past confront their quest for  

fulfillment.  

 

4 Section 377 exacts conformity backed by the fear of penal reprisal.  

There is an unbridgeable divide between the moral values on which it is based  

and the values of the Constitution. What separates them is liberty and dignity.  

We must, as a society, ask searching questions to the forms and symbols of  

injustice. Unless we do that, we risk becoming the cause and not just the  

inheritors of an unjust society. Does the Constitution allow a quiver of fear to  

become the quilt around the bodies of her citizens, in the intimacies which

269

PART A   

7    

define their identities? If there is only one answer to this question, as I believe  

there is, the tragedy and anguish which Section 377 inflicts must be remedied.  

 

5 The Constitution brought about a transfer of political power. But it  

reflects above all, a vision of a society governed by justice. Individual liberty is  

its soul. The constitutional vision of justice accommodates differences of  

culture, ideology and orientation. The stability of its foundation lies in its effort  

to protect diversity in all its facets: in the beliefs, ideas and ways of living of  

her citizens. Democratic as it is, our Constitution does not demand conformity.  

Nor does it contemplate the mainstreaming of culture. It nurtures dissent as  

the safety valve for societal conflict. Our ability to recognise others who are  

different is a sign of our own evolution. We miss the symbols of a  

compassionate and humane society only at our peril.  

 

Section 377 provides for rule by the law instead of the rule of law. The rule of  

law requires a just law which facilitates equality, liberty and dignity in all its  

facets. Rule by the law provides legitimacy to arbitrary state behaviour.  

 

6 Section 377 has consigned a group of citizens to the margins. It has  

been destructive of their identities. By imposing the sanctions of the law on  

consenting adults involved in a sexual relationship, it has lent the authority of

270

PART B  

8    

the state to perpetuate social stereotypes and encourage discrimination.  

Gays, lesbians, bisexuals and transgenders have been relegated to the  

anguish of closeted identities. Sexual orientation has become a target for  

exploitation, if not blackmail, in a networked and digital age. The impact of  

Section 377 has travelled far beyond the punishment of an offence. It has  

been destructive of an identity which is crucial to a dignified existence.  

 

7 It is difficult to right the wrongs of history. But we can certainly set the  

course for the future. That we can do by saying, as I propose to say in this  

case, that lesbians, gays, bisexuals and transgenders have a constitutional  

right to equal citizenship in all its manifestations. Sexual orientation is  

recognised and protected by the Constitution. Section 377 of the Penal Code  

is unconstitutional in so far as it penalises a consensual relationship between  

adults of the same gender. The constitutional values of liberty and dignity can  

accept nothing less.   

   

B “To the wisdom of the Court”   

Union Government before the Court  

 

8 After the hearing commenced, the Additional Solicitor General tendered  

an affidavit. The Union government states that it leaves a decision on the

271

PART B  

9    

validity of Section 377 ‘to the wisdom of this Court’. Implicit in this is that the  

government has no view of its own on the subject and rests content to abide  

by the decision of this Court. During the parleys in Court, the ASG however  

submitted that the court should confine itself to the reference by ruling upon  

the correctness of Suresh Kumar Koushal v. Naz Foundation3 (“Koushal”).  

 

9 We would have appreciated a categorical statement of position by the  

government, setting out its views on the validity of Section 377 and on the  

correctness of Koushal. The ambivalence of the government does not obviate  

the necessity for a judgment on the issues raised. The challenge to the  

constitutional validity of Section 377 must squarely be addressed in this  

proceeding. That is plainly the duty of the Court. Constitutional issues are not  

decided on concession. The statement of the Union government does not  

concede to the contention of the petitioners that the statutory provision is  

invalid. Even if a concession were to be made, that would not conclude the  

matter for this Court. All that the stand of the government indicates is that it is  

to the ‘wisdom’ of this Court that the matter is left. In reflecting upon this  

appeal to our wisdom, it is just as well that we as judges remind ourselves of a  

truth which can unwittingly be forgotten: flattery is a graveyard for the gullible.   

 

                                                           3 (2014) 1 SCC 1

272

PART B  

10    

10 Bereft of a submission on behalf of the Union government on a matter of  

constitutional principle these proceedings must be dealt with in the only  

manner known to the constitutional court: through an adjudication which fulfills  

constitutional values and principles.   

 

11 The ASG made a fair submission when he urged that the court should  

deal with the matter in reference. The submission, to its credit, would have the  

court follow a path of prudence. Prudence requires, after all, that the Court  

should address itself to the controversy in the reference without pursuing an  

uncharted course beyond it. While accepting the wisdom of the approach  

suggested by the ASG, it is nonetheless necessary to make some prefatory  

observations on the scope of the reference.   

 

12 The correctness of the decision in Koushal is in question. Koushal [as  

indeed the decision of the Delhi High Court in Naz Foundation v.  

Government of NCT of Delhi4 (“Naz”)] dealt with the validity of Section 377  

which criminalizes even a consensual relationship between adults of the same  

gender who engage in sexual conduct (‘carnal intercourse against the order of  

nature’). In dealing with the validity of the provision, it is necessary to  

understand the nature of the constitutional right which LGBT individuals claim.  

                                                           4(2010) Cri LJ 94

273

PART B  

11    

According to them, the right to be in a relationship with a consenting adult of  

the same gender emanates from the right to life, as a protected value under  

the Constitution. They ground their right on the basis of an identity resting in  

their sexual orientation. According to them, their liberty and dignity require  

both an acknowledgement as well as a protection under the law, of their  

sexual orientation. Representing their identity, based on sexual orientation, to  

the world at large and asserting it in their relationship with the community and  

the state is stated to be intrinsic to the free exercise of speech and expression  

guaranteed by the Constitution. Sexual orientation is claimed to be intrinsic to  

the guarantee against discrimination on the ground of sex. The statutory  

provision, it has been asserted, also violates the fundamental guarantee  

against arbitrariness because it unequally targets gay men whose sexual  

expression falls in the area prohibited by Section 377.   

 

13 In answering the dispute in regard to the validity of Section 377, the  

court must of necessity understand and explain in a constitutional perspective,  

the nature of the right which is claimed. The challenge to Section 377 has to  

be understood from the perspective of a rights discourse. While doing so, it  

becomes necessary to understand the constitutional source from which the  

claim emerges. When a right is claimed to be constitutionally protected, it is  

but necessary for the court to analyze the basis of that assertion. Hence, in

274

PART C  

12    

answering the reference, it is crucial for the court to place the entitlement of  

the LGBT population in a constitutional framework. We have approached the  

matter thus far from the perspective of constitutional analysis. But there is a  

more simple line of reasoning as well, grounded as we believe, in common-

sense. Sexual acts between consenting adults of the same gender constitute  

one facet – albeit an important aspect – of the right asserted by gay men to  

lead fulfilling lives. Gay and lesbian relationships are sustained and nurtured  

in every aspect which makes for a meaningful life. In understanding the true  

nature of those relationships and the protection which the Constitution affords  

to them, it is necessary to adopt a perspective which leads to their acceptance  

as equal members of a humane and compassionate society. Forming a  

holistic perspective requires the court to dwell on, but not confine itself, to  

sexuality. Sexual orientation creates an identity on which there is a  

constitutional claim to the entitlement of a dignified life. It is from that broad  

perspective that the constitutional right needs to be adjudicated.  

 

C From “The Ashes of the Gay”  

“Democracy   

It's coming through a hole in the air,   

…  

It's coming from the feel   

that this ain't exactly real,   

or it's real, but it ain't exactly there.   

From the wars against disorder,   

from the sirens night and day,  

275

PART C  

13    

from the fires of the homeless,   

from the ashes of the gay:  

Democracy is coming…”5  

 

 

14 Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code, 1860 (“IPC”) has made ‘carnal  

intercourse against the order of nature’ an offence. This provision, understood  

as prohibiting non-peno vaginal intercourse, reflects the imposition of a  

particular set of morals by a colonial power at a particular point in history. A  

supposedly alien law,6 Section 377 has managed to survive for over 158  

years, impervious to both the anticolonial struggle as well as the formation of  

a democratic India, which guarantees fundamental rights to all its citizens. An  

inquiry into the colonial origins of Section 377 and its postulations about  

sexuality is useful in assessing the relevance of the provision in contemporary  

times.7  

 

15 Lord Thomas Babington Macaulay, Chairman of the First Law  

Commission of India and principal architect of the IPC, cited two main sources  

from which he drew in drafting the Code: the French (Napoleonic) Penal  

Code, 1810 and Edward Livingston’s Louisiana Code.8 Lord Macaulay also  

                                                           5    Lyrics from Leonard Cohen’s song “Democracy” (1992).  6   See Same-Sex Love in India: A Literary History (Ruth Vanita and Saleem Kidwai, eds.), Penguin India (2008) for  

writings spanning over more than 2,000 years of Indian literature which demonstrate that same-sex love has  flourished, evolved and been embraced in various forms since ancient times.   

7    Law like Love: Queer Perspectives on Law (Arvind Narrain and Alok Gupta, eds.), Yoda Press (2011).  8    K. N. Chandrasekharan Pillai and Shabistan Aquil, “Historical Introduction to the Indian Penal Code”, in Essays on  

the Indian Penal Code, New Delhi, Indian Law Institute (2005); Siyuan Chen, “Codification, Macaulay and the  Indian Penal Code [Book Review], Singapore Journal of Legal Studies, National University of Singapore, Faculty  of Law (2011), at pages 581-584.

276

PART C  

14    

drew inspiration from the English common law and the British Royal  

Commission’s 1843 Draft Code.9 Tracing that origin, English jurist Fitzjames  

Stephen observes:   

“The Indian Penal Code may be described as the criminal law  

of England freed from all technicalities and superfluities,  

systematically arranged and modified in some few particulars  

(they are surprisingly few) to suit the circumstances of British  

India.”10  

 

In order to understand the colonial origins of Section 377, it is necessary to go  

further back to modern English law’s conception of anal and oral intercourse,  

which was firmly rooted in Judeo-Christian morality and condemned non-

procreative sex.11 Though Jesus himself does not reference homosexuality or  

homosexual sex,12 the “Holiness Code”13 found in Leviticus provides thus:  

“You shall not lie with a male as with a woman. It is an  

abomination. [18:22]  

If a man also lie with mankind, as he lieth with a woman, both  

of them have committed an abomination: they shall surely be  

put to death; their blood shall be upon them. [19:13]  

If a man lies with a male as with a woman, both of them have  

committed an abomination; they shall be put to death, their  

blood is upon them. [20:13]”  

                                                           9    Douglas E. Sanders, “377 and the Unnatural Afterlife of British Colonialism in Asia”, Asian Journal of Comparative  

Law, Vol. 4 (2009), at page 11 (“Douglas”); David Skuy, “Macaulay and the Indian Penal Code of 1862: The Myth  of the Inherent Superiority and Modernity of the English Legal System Compared to India’s Legal System in the  Nineteenth Century”, Modern Asian Studies, Vol. 32 (1998), at pages 513-557.  

10  Barry Wright, “Macaulay’s Indian Penal Code: Historical Context and Originating Principles”, Carleton University  (2011).   

11 Michael Kirby, “The Sodomy Offence: England's Least Lovely Law Export?” Journal of Commonwealth Criminal  Law, Inaugural Issue (2011).  

12  Douglas, supra note 9, at page 4.  13  Ibid at page 2.

277

PART C  

15    

Another Judeo-Christian religious interpretation refers to “sodomy”, a term  

used for anal intercourse that is derived from an interpretation of Genesis  

18:20 of the Old Testament,14 known as the story of Sodom and Gomorrah.  

Briefly, when two angels took refuge in the home of Lot, the men of the town  

of Sodom surrounded the house and demanded that the angels be sent out so  

that the men may “know” them (in this interpretation, with sexual  

connotations). When Lot offered them his two virgin daughters instead, the  

men of Sodom responded by threatening Lot. The angels then blinded the  

“Sodomites.”15 The use of the term “sodomites” to describe those who  

engaged in anal intercourse emerged in the 13th Century, and the term  

“sodomy” was used as a euphemism for a number of sexual ‘sins’ two  

centuries earlier.16   

 

16 The preservation of the Judeo-Christian condemnation of homosexuality  

is also attributed to the Jewish theologian, Philo of Alexandria, who is  

regarded as the father of the Church Fathers and who reviled homosexuals  

and called for their execution.17 The condemnation of homosexuality can also  

be traced to Roman law. Emperor Justinian’s Code of 529, for instance, stated  

                                                           14  Douglas, supra note 9, at page 4.  15  Jessica Cecil, “The Destruction of Sodom and Gomorrah”, British Broadcasting Company, 11 February 2017.  16  Douglas, supra note 9, at page 4; KSN Murthy’s Criminal Law: Indian Penal Code (KVS Sarma ed), Lexis Nexis  

(2016).  17  Philo, translated by F.H. Colson and G.H. Whitaker, 10 Volumes, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1929-

1962).

278

PART C  

16    

that persons who engaged in homosexual sex were to be executed.18 From  

Rome, the condemnation of homosexuality spread across Europe, where it  

manifested itself in ecclesiastical law.19 During the Protestant Reformation,  

these laws shifted from the ecclesiastical to the criminal domain, beginning  

with Germany in 1532.20  

 

While ecclesiastical laws against homosexual intercourse were well  

established in England by the 1500s,21 England’s first criminal (non-

ecclesiastical) law was the Buggery Act of 1533, which condemned “the  

detestable and abominable vice of buggeri committed with mankind or  

beest.”22 “Buggery” is derived from the old French word for heretic, “bougre”,  

and was taken to mean anal intercourse.23  

 

17 The Buggery Act, 1533, which was enacted by Henry VIII, made the  

offence of buggery punishable by death, and continued to exist for nearly 300  

years before it was repealed and replaced by the Offences against the Person  

Act, 1828. Buggery, however, remained a capital offence in England until  

1861, one year after the enactment of the IPC. The language of Section 377  

                                                           18 David F. Greenberg and Marcia H. Bystryn, “Christian Intolerance of Homosexuality”, American Journal of  

Sociology, Vol. 88 (1982), at pages 515-548.  19   Douglas, supra note 9, at pages 5 and 8.  20   Ibid at page 5.  21   Ibid at page 2.  22   The Buggery Act, 1533.  23   Douglas, supra note 9, at page 2.

279

PART C  

17    

has antecedents in the definition of buggery found in Sir Edward Coke’s late  

17th Century compilation of English law:24  

“...Committed by carnal knowledge against the ordinance of  

the Creator, and order of nature, by mankind with mankind, or  

with brute beast, or by womankind with brute beast.”25  

 

18 The Criminal Law Amendment Act, 1885 made “gross indecency” a  

crime in the United Kingdom, and was used to prosecute homosexuals where  

sodomy could not be proven. In 1895, Oscar Wilde was arrested under the  

Act for ‘committing acts of gross indecency with male persons’.26 During  

Wilde’s trial, the Prosecutor, referring to homosexual love, asked him, “What  

is ‘the love that dare not speak its name’?” Wilde responded:   

“The love that dare not speak its name” in this century is such  

a great affection of an elder for a younger man as there was  

between David and Jonathan, such as Plato made the very  

basis of his philosophy, and such as you find in the sonnets of  

Michelangelo and Shakespeare. It is that deep spiritual  

affection that is as pure as it is perfect. It dictates and  

pervades great works of art, like those of Shakespeare and  

Michelangelo, and those two letters of mine, such as they are.  

It is in this century misunderstood, so much misunderstood  

that it may be described as “the love that dare not speak its  

name,” and on that account of it I am placed where I am now.  

It is beautiful, it is fine, it is the noblest form of affection. There  

is nothing unnatural about it. It is intellectual, and it repeatedly  

exists between an older and a younger man, when the older  

man has intellect, and the younger man has all the joy, hope  

and glamour of life before him. That it should be so, the world  

                                                           24 Ibid at 7.  25 Human Rights Watch. This Alien Legacy: The Origins of “Sodomy” Laws in British Colonialism (2008).   26 Douglas, supra note 9, at page 15.

280

PART C  

18    

does not understand. The world mocks at it, and sometimes  

puts one in the pillory for it.”27  

 

Wilde was held guilty and was sentenced to two years’ hard labour and  

subsequently incarcerated.  

 

Following World War II, arrests and prosecutions of homosexuals increased.  

Alan Turing, the renowned mathematician and cryptographer who was  

responsible for breaking the Nazi Enigma code during World War II, was  

convicted of ‘gross indecency’ in 1952. In order to avoid a prison sentence,  

Turing was forced to agree to chemical castration. He was injected with  

synthetic female hormones. Less than two years after he began the hormone  

treatment, Turing committed suicide. The Amendment Act (also known as the  

Labouchere Amendment) remained in English law until 1967. Turing was  

posthumously pardoned in 2013, and in 2017, the UK introduced the Policing  

and Crime Bill, also called the “Turing Law,” posthumously pardoning 50,000  

homosexual men and providing pardons for the living.  

 

In the wake of several court cases in which homosexuality had been featured,  

the British Parliament in 1954 set up the Wolfenden Committee, headed by  

                                                           27 H. Montgomery Hyde, John O'Connor, and Merlin Holland, The Trials of Oscar Wilde (2014), at page 201.

281

PART C  

19    

John Wolfenden, to “consider…the law and practice relating to homosexual  

offenses and the treatment of persons convicted of such offenses by the  

courts”, as well as the laws relevant to prostitution and solicitation. The  

Wolfenden Report of 1957, which was supported by the Church of England,28  

proposed that there ‘must remain a realm of private morality and immorality  

which is, in brief and crude terms, not the law’s business’ and recommended  

that homosexual acts between two consenting adults should no longer be a  

criminal offence.29  

  

19 The success of the report led England and Wales to enact The Sexual  

Offences Act, 1967, which decriminalized private homosexual sex between  

two men over the age of twenty-one. Britain continued to introduce and  

amend laws governing same-sex intercourse to make them more equal,  

including the lowering of the age of consent for gay/bisexual men to sixteen in  

2001.30 In May 2007, in a statement to the UN Human Rights Council, the UK,  

which imposed criminal prohibitions against same-sex intercourse in its former  

colonies across the world, committed itself to the cause of worldwide  

decriminalization of homosexuality.31 Today, India continues to enforce a law  

                                                           28 Ibid at 25.  29 Report of the Departmental Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution (1957) (“Wolfenden Report”).   30 Sexual Offences (Amendment) Act 2000, Parliament of the United Kingdom.  31 Douglas, supra note 9, at page 29.

282

PART C  

20    

imposed by an erstwhile colonial government, a law that has been long done  

away with by the same government in its own jurisdiction.   

 

C.I “Arc of the moral universe”  

20 Lord Macaulay was greatly influenced by English philosopher and jurist  

Jeremy Bentham, who coined the term codification and argued for replacing  

existing laws with clear, concise, and understandable provisions that could be  

universally applied across the Empire.32 Ironically, in a 1785 essay, Bentham  

himself wrote one of the earliest known defences of homosexuality in the  

English language, arguing against the criminalization of homosexuality.  

However, this essay was only discovered 200 years after his death.33  

 

21 The Law Commission’s 1837 draft of the Penal Code (prepared by Lord  

Macaulay) contained two sections (Clauses 361 and 362), which are  

considered the immediate precursors to Section 377:  

“OF UNNATURAL OFFENCES  

361. Whoever, intending to gratify unnatural lust, touches, for  

that purpose, any person, or any animal, or is by his own  

consent touched by any person, for the purpose of gratifying  

unnatural lust, shall be punished with imprisonment of either  

description for a term which may extend to fourteen years and  

                                                           32 Douglas, supra note 9, at page 9.  33 Ibid.

283

PART C  

21    

must not be less than two years, and shall also be liable to  

fine.  

 

362. Whoever, intending to gratify unnatural lust, touches for  

that purpose any person without that person's free and  

intelligent consent, shall be punished with imprisonment of  

either description for a term which may extend to life and  

must not be less than seven years, and shall also be liable to  

fine.”  

 

Both the draft clauses are vague in their description of the acts they seek to  

criminalize. Lord Macaulay also omitted an explanation to the Clauses. In a  

note presented with the 1837 draft, Lord Macaulay elaborated:  

“Clauses 361 and 362 relate to an odious class of offences  

respecting which it is desirable that as little as possible be  

said. We leave without comment to the judgment of his  

Lordship in Council the two Clauses which we have provided  

for these offences. We are unwilling to insert, either in the  

text, or in the notes, anything which could give rise to  

public discussion on this revolting subject; as we are  

decidedly of opinion that the injury which would be done  

to the morals of the community by such discussion would  

far more than compensate for any benefits which might be  

derived from legislative measures framed with the greatest  

precision.”34                                              (Emphasis supplied)  

 

So abominable did Macaulay consider these offences that he banished the  

thought of providing a rationale for their being made culpable. The prospect of  

a public discussion was revolting.      

                                                           34   Enze Han, Joseph O'Mahoney, “British Colonialism and the Criminalization of Homosexuality: Queens, Crime and  

Empire”, Routledge (2018).

284

PART C  

22    

After twenty-five years of revision, the IPC entered into force on 1 January  

1862, two years after Lord Macaulay’s death. The IPC was the first codified  

criminal code in the British Empire. Section 377 of the revised code read as  

follows:   

“Of Unnatural Offences   

377. Unnatural Offences.- Whoever voluntarily has carnal  

intercourse against the order of nature with any man, woman  

or animal, shall be punished with [imprisonment for life]35, or  

with imprisonment of either description for a term which may  

extend to ten years, and shall also be liable to fine.   

Explanation.- Penetration is sufficient to constitute the carnal  

intercourse necessary to the offence described in this  

section.”   

 

22 The Explanation is unique in that it requires proof of penetration –  

something that British Law did not. The two clauses in the Draft Code fell  

somewhere in between, requiring proof of “touch”.36   

 

By the time India gained independence in 1947, Britain had introduced Penal  

Codes similar to the IPC in other former colonies, including Zanzibar  

(Tanzania) in 1867, Singapore, Malaysia, and Brunei in 1871, Ceylon (Sri  

Lanka) in 1885, Burma (Myanmar) in 1886,37 East Africa Protectorate (Kenya)  

                                                           35   Changed from “transportation for life” by Act 26 of 1955.  36   Douglas, supra note 9, at page 16.  37  Nang Yin Kham, “An Introduction to the Law and Judicial System of Myanmar”, Centre for Asia Legal Studies  

Faculty of Law, National University of Singapore, Working Paper 14/02, (2014).

285

PART C  

23    

in 1897, Sudan in 1889, Uganda in 1902, and Tanganyika (Tanzania) in  

1920.38 Under Article 372(1) of the Indian Constitution, which provides that all  

laws in force prior to the commencement of the Constitution shall continue to  

be in force until altered or repealed, the IPC and many other pre-

Independence laws were “saved” and allowed to operate in Independent  

India.  

 

23 While Section 377 has been used to prosecute non-consensual sexual  

acts, it has also been used to prosecute consensual sexual acts. In  

(Meharban) Nowshirwan Irani v. Emperor39, for instance, a police officer  

observed Nowshirwan, a young shopkeeper, engaged in homosexual acts  

with a young man, Ratansi, through a keyhole in Nowshirwan’s house. The  

Prosecution argued that the acts were non-consensual, but could not prove  

coercion.40 The High Court of Sindh ultimately set aside the conviction based  

on insufficient evidence. Nevertheless, what should have been an intimate act  

between two consenting parties in their bedroom became a public scandal  

and the subject of judicial scrutiny.41  

 

                                                           38   Supra note 34.  39   AIR 1934 Sind. 206.  40  Arvind Narrain, “‘That Despicable Specimen of Humanity’: Policing of Homosexuality in India”, in Challenging the  

Rule(s) of Law: Colonialism, Criminology and Human Rights in India (Kalpana Kannabiran and Ranbir Singh  eds.), Sage (2008).  

41  Arvind Narrain, “A New Language of Morality: From the Trial of Nowshirwan to the Judgement in Naz Foundation”,  The Indian Journal of Constitutional Law, Vol. 4 (2010).  

286

PART C  

24    

In D P Minwalla v. Emperor42, Minawalla and Tajmahomed, were seen  

having anal intercourse in a lorry and were arrested, charged, and found guilty  

under Section 377. Tajmahomed was sentenced to four months rigorous  

imprisonment, and Minawalla, who was charged with abetment, was  

sentenced to a fine of Rs 100 and imprisonment until the rising of the Bench.  

Minawalla appealed the decision on the grounds that he was not a consenting  

partner, and submitted himself to a medical exam. The judge was  

unconvinced, however, and Minawalla’s original sentence was upheld. The  

Court, convinced that the acts were consensual, found the men guilty under  

Section 377.43  

 

In Ratan Mia v. State of Assam44, the Court convicted two men (one aged  

fifteen and a half, the other twenty) under Section 377 and treated them as  

equally culpable, as he was unable to cast one of them as the perpetrator and  

the other as the victim or abettor. Both men were originally sentenced to  

imprisonment for six months and a fine of Rs 100. After Nur had spent six  

years in prison and appealed three times,45 both men's sentences were  

                                                           42   AIR 1935 Sind. 78.  43  Supra note 40.  44  (1988) Cr.L.J. 980.  45  Suparna Bhaskaran, “The Politics of Penetration: Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code” in Queering India: Same-

Sex Love and Eroticism in Indian Culture and Society (Ruth Vanita ed.), Routledge (2002).  

287

PART C  

25    

reduced to seven days rigorous imprisonment, in view of the fact that they  

were first time offenders under the age of twenty-one.46  

 

Even though the government is not proactively enforcing a law that governs  

private activities, the psychological impact for homosexuals who are, for all  

practical purposes, felons in waiting, is damaging in its own right:  

“...The true impact of Section 377 on queer lives is felt outside  

the courtroom and must not be measured in terms of legal  

cases. Numerous studies, including both documented and  

anecdotal evidence, tell us that Section 377 is the basis for  

routine and continuous violence against sexual minorities by  

the police, the medical establishment, and the state. There  

are innumerable stories that can be cited – from the everyday  

violence faced by hijras [a distinct transgender category] and  

kothis [effeminate males] on the streets of Indian cities to the  

refusal of the National Human Rights Commission to hear the  

case of a young man who had been given electro-shock  

therapy for nearly two years. A recent report by the People’s  

Union for Civil Liberties (Karnataka), showed that Section 377  

was used by the police to justify practices such as illegal  

detention, sexual abuse and harassment, extortion and outing  

of queer people to their families.”47  

 

Before the end of the 19th century, gay rights movements were few and far  

between. Indeed, when Alfred Douglas, Oscar Wilde’s lover, wrote in his  

1890s poem entitled “Two Loves” of “the love that dare not speak its name”,  

he was alluding to society’s moral disapprobation of homosexuality.48 The 20th  

                                                           46  Ibid.     47  Douglas, supra note 9, at page 21; “Introduction” to Because I Have a Voice: Queer Politics in India, (Gautam  

Bhan and Arvind Narrain eds), Yoda Press (2005) at pages 7, 8.   48  Melba Cuddy-Keane, Adam Hammond and Alexandra Peat, “Q” in Modernism: Keywords, Wiley-Blackwell (2014).  

288

PART C  

26    

century, however, saw the LGBTIQ community emerge from the shadows  

worldwide, poised to agitate and demand equal civil rights. LGBTIQ  

movements focused on issues of intersectionality, the interplay of oppressions  

arising from being both queer and lower class, coloured, disabled, and so on.  

Despite the movement making numerous strides forward in the fight for equal  

rights, incidents of homosexual arrests were nevertheless extant at the turn of  

the 21st century.  

 

In many cases of unfulfilled civil rights, there is a tendency to operate under  

the philosophy articulated by Dr. Martin Luther King, that “the arc of the moral  

universe is long, but it bends towards justice.” It is likely that those who  

subscribe to this philosophy believe that homosexuals should practice the  

virtue of patience, and wait for society to understand and accept their way of  

life. What those who purport this philosophy fail to recognize is that Dr King  

himself argued against the doctrine of “wait”:  

“For years now I have heard the word “wait.” It rings in the ear  

of every Negro with a piercing familiarity. This “wait” has  

almost always meant “never.” It has been a tranquilizing  

thalidomide, relieving the emotional stress for a moment, only  

to give birth to an ill-formed infant of frustration. We must  

come to see with the distinguished jurist of yesterday that  

“justice too long delayed is justice denied.” We have waited  

for more than three hundred and forty years for our God-given  

and constitutional rights . . . when you are harried by day and  

haunted by night by the fact that you are a Negro, living  

constantly at tiptoe stance, never knowing what to expect  

next, and plagued with inner fears and outer resentments;

289

PART C  

27    

when you are forever fighting a degenerating sense of  

“nobodyness” -- then you will understand why we find it  

difficult to wait. There comes a time when the cup of  

endurance runs over and men are no longer willing to be  

plunged into an abyss of injustice where they experience the  

bleakness of corroding despair. I hope, sirs, you can  

understand our legitimate and unavoidable impatience.”  

(Letter from a Birmingham Jail)49  

 

24 Indian citizens belonging to sexual minorities have waited. They have  

waited and watched as their fellow citizens were freed from the British yoke  

while their fundamental freedoms remained restrained under an antiquated  

and anachronistic colonial-era law – forcing them to live in hiding, in fear, and  

as second-class citizens. In seeking an adjudication of the validity of Section  

377, these citizens urge that the acts which the provision makes culpable  

should be decriminalised. But this case involves much more than merely  

decriminalising certain conduct which has been proscribed by a colonial law.  

The case is about an aspiration to realise constitutional rights. It is about a  

right which every human being has, to live with dignity. It is about enabling  

these citizens to realise the worth of equal citizenship. Above all, our decision  

will speak to the transformative power of the Constitution. For it is in the  

transformation of society that the Constitution seeks to assure the values of a  

just, humane and compassionate existence to all her citizens.  

                                                           49 Martin Luther King Jr., “Letter from a Birmingham Jail” (1963).

290

PART D  

28    

D An equal love   

   

“Through Love's Great Power  

 

Through love's great power to be made whole  

In mind and body, heart and soul –  

Through freedom to find joy, or be  

By dint of joy itself set free  

In love and in companionhood:  

This is the true and natural good.  

To undo justice, and to seek  

To quash the rights that guard the weak -  

To sneer at love, and wrench apart  

The bonds of body, mind and heart  

With specious reason and no rhyme:  

This is the true unnatural crime.”50  

 

Article 14 is our fundamental charter of equality:  

 “The State shall not deny to any person equality before the  

law or the equal protection of the laws within the territory of  

India.”                                      (Emphasis supplied)  

   25 In Naz, the Delhi High Court held that Section 377 violates Article 14 of  

the Constitution since the classification on which it is based does not bear any  

nexus to the object which the provision seeks to achieve.51 In Koushal, this  

Court rejected the Naz formulation on the ground that “those who indulge in  

carnal intercourse in the ordinary course and those who ... [do so] against the  

order of nature constitute different classes.”52 Koushal held on that logic that  

                                                           50 Vikram Seth wrote this poem the morning after the Supreme Court refused to review its decision in Koushal.  51 Naz Foundation, at para 91.   52 Koushal, at para 65.  

291

PART D  

29    

Section 377 does not suffer from arbitrariness or from an irrational  

classification.  

 

26 A litany of our decisions – to refer to them individually would be a  

parade of the familiar – indicates that to be a reasonable classification under  

Article 14 of the Constitution, two criteria must be met: (i) the classification  

must be founded on an intelligible differentia; and (ii) the differentia must have  

a rational nexus to the objective sought to be achieved by the legislation.53  

There must, in other words, be a causal connection between the basis of  

classification and the object of the statute. If the object of the classification is  

illogical, unfair and unjust, the classification will be unreasonable.54   

 

27 Equating the content of equality with the reasonableness of a  

classification on which a law is based advances the cause of legal formalism.   

The problem with the classification test is that what constitutes a reasonable  

classification is reduced to a mere formula: the quest for an intelligible  

differentia and the rational nexus to the object sought to be achieved. In doing  

so, the test of classification risks elevating form over substance. The danger  

inherent in legal formalism lies in its inability to lay threadbare the values  

which guide the process of judging constitutional rights. Legal formalism  

                                                           53 State of West Bengal v. Anwar Ali Sarkar, AIR (1952) SC 75.  54 Deepak Sibal v. Punjab University, (1989) 2 SCC 145.

292

PART D  

30    

buries the life-giving forces of the Constitution under a mere mantra.  What it  

ignores is that Article 14 contains a powerful statement of values – of the  

substance of equality before the law and the equal protection of laws.  To  

reduce it to a formal exercise of classification may miss the true value of  

equality as a safeguard against arbitrariness in state action. As our  

constitutional jurisprudence has evolved towards recognizing the substantive  

content of liberty and equality, the core of Article 14 has emerged out of the  

shadows of classification.  Article 14 has a substantive content on which,  

together with liberty and dignity, the edifice of the Constitution is built.  Simply  

put, in that avatar, it reflects the quest for ensuring fair treatment of the  

individual in every aspect of human endeavor and in every facet of human  

existence.  

 

In E P Royappa v. State of Tamil Nadu55, the validity of state action was  

made subject to the test of arbitrariness:   

“Equality is a dynamic concept with many aspects and  

dimensions and it cannot be “cribbed cabined and confined”  

within traditional and doctrinaire limits. From a positivistic  

point of view, equality is antithetic to arbitrariness. In fact  

equality and arbitrariness are sworn enemies; one belongs to  

the rule of law in a republic while the other, to the whim and  

caprice of an absolute monarch. Where an act is arbitrary it is  

implicit in it that it is unequal both according to political logic  

and constitutional law and is therefore violative of Art.14…”  

 

                                                           55 (1974) 4 SCC 3

293

PART D  

31    

Four decades later, the test has been refined in Shayara Bano v. Union of  

India56:   

“The expression ‘arbitrarily’ means: in an unreasonable  

manner, as fixed or done capriciously or at pleasure, without  

adequate determining principle, not founded in the nature of  

things, non-rational, not done or acting according to reason or  

judgment, depending on the will alone.”  

 

28 The wording of Section 377 does not precisely map on to a distinction  

between homosexuals and heterosexuals but a precise interpretation would  

mean that it penalizes some forms of sexual expression among heterosexuals  

while necessarily criminalizing every form of sexual expression and intimacy  

between homosexuals.57 For Section 377 to withstand the scrutiny of Article  

14, it was necessary for the Court in Koushal to establish the difference  

between ‘ordinary intercourse’ and ‘intercourse against the order of nature’,  

the legitimate objective being pursued and the rational nexus between the  

goal and the classification. However, the Koushal approach has been  

criticised on the ground that while dealing with Article 14, it fell “short of the  

minimum standards of judicial reasoning that may be expected from the  

Supreme Court.”58 On a review of the prosecutions under Section 377,  

Koushal conceded that “no uniform test [could] be culled out to classify acts  

                                                           56 (2017) 9 SCC 1  57 Gautam Bhatia, “Equal moral membership: Naz Foundation and the refashioning of equality under a transformative    

constitution”, Indian Law Review, Vol. 1 (2017), at pages 115-144.  58  Shubhankar Dam, “Suresh Kumar Koushal and Another v. NAZ Foundation and Others (Civil Appeal No. 10972 of   

2013)” Public Law, International Survey Section (2014).

294

PART D  

32    

as ‘carnal intercourse against the order of nature.’”59 Yet Koushal upheld the  

classification of sexual acts in Section 377 without explaining the difference  

between the classes, or the justification for treating the classes differently.   

 This lack of reasoning and analysis by the Court has been critiqued in  

scholarly research on the subject. The following extract sums up the criticism  

with telling effect:  

“The Court says – without an iota of evidence – that there are  

two classes of persons – those who engage in sexual  

intercourse in the “ordinary course”, and those who don’t.  

What is ordinary course? Presumably, heterosexuality. Why  

is this ordinary course? Perhaps because there are more  

heterosexuals than homosexuals around, although the Court  

gives no evidence for that. Well, there are also more black-

haired people in India than brown-haired people. Is sex with a  

brown-haired person against the order of nature because it  

happens less often?... Where is the rational nexus? What is  

the legitimate governmental objective? Even if we accept that  

there is an intelligible differentia here, on what basis do  

you criminalize – and thus deny equal protection of laws – to  

one class of persons? The Court gives no answer.  

Alternatively, “ordinary sex” is penal-vaginal, and every other  

kind of sex is “against the ordinary course of nature”. Again,  

no evidence to back that claim up apart from the say-so of the  

judge.”60  

 

At the very outset, we must understand the problem with the usage of the  

term ‘order of nature’. What is ‘natural’ and what is ‘unnatural’? And who  

decides the categorization into these two ostensibly distinct and water-tight  

compartments? Do we allow the state to draw the boundaries between  

                                                           59  Koushal, at para 60.   60 Gautam Bhatia, “The Unbearable Wrongness of Koushal vs Naz Foundation”, Indian Constitutional Law and  

Philosophy (2013).

295

PART D  

33    

permissible and impermissible intimacies between consenting adults?  

Homosexuality has been documented in almost 1500 species, who  

“unfortunately are not blessed with rational capabilities (and the propensity to  

‘nurture’ same sex thoughts) as are found in mankind.”61 An interesting article  

in this regard notes that, “no species has been found in which homosexual  

behaviour has not been shown to exist, with the exception of species that  

never have sex at all, such as sea urchins and aphis.”62   

 

29 In an incisive article,63 Ambrosino discusses the shift from reproductive  

instinct to erotic desire and how crucial this shift is to understanding modern  

notions of sexuality. He analyses how the lines between homosexuality and  

heterosexuality are blurred, and perhaps even an outdated myth or invention  

when we understand the fluidity of sexual identities today:64  

““No one knows exactly why heterosexuals and homosexuals  

ought to be different,” wrote Wendell Ricketts, author of the  

1984 study Biological Research on Homosexuality. The best  

answer we’ve got is something of a tautology: “heterosexuals  

and homosexuals are considered different because they can  

be divided into two groups on the basis of the belief that they  

can be divided into two groups.”  

Though the hetero/homo divide seems like an eternal,  

indestructible fact of nature, it simply isn’t. It’s merely one  

recent grammar humans have invented to talk about what sex  

means to us.”  

                                                           61  Shamnad Basheer, Sroyon Mukherjee and Karthy Nair, “Section 377 and the ‘Order of Nature’: Nurturing  

‘Indeterminacy’ in the Law”, NUJS Law  Review, Vol, 2  (2009).  62  Bruce Bagemihl,  Biological Exuberance: Animal Homosexuality and Natural Diversity, Stonewall Inn Editions  

(2000).  63   Brandon Ambrosino, “The Invention of Heterosexuality”, British Broadcasting Company, 26 March, 2017.  64   Ibid.

296

PART D  

34    

He questions the elevated status of ‘normalcy’ in the following words:  

“Normal” is a loaded word, of course, and it has been misused  

throughout history. Hierarchical ordering leading to slavery was  

at one time accepted as normal, as was a geocentric  

cosmology. It was only by questioning the foundations of the  

consensus view that “normal” phenomena were dethroned  

from their privileged positions.”   

 

There are obvious shortcomings of the human element in the judgment of  

natural and unnatural:  

“Why judge what is natural and ethical to a human being by his  

or her animal nature? Many of the things human beings value,  

such as medicine and art, are egregiously unnatural. At the  

same time, humans detest many things that actually are  

eminently natural, like disease and death. If we consider some  

naturally occurring phenomena ethical and others unethical,  

that means our minds (the things looking) are determining what  

to make of nature (the things being looked at). Nature doesn’t  

exist somewhere “out there,” independently of us – we’re  

always already interpreting it from the inside.”  

 

It has been argued that “the ‘naturalness’ and omnipresence of  

heterosexuality is manufactured by an elimination of historical specificities  

about the organisation, regulation and deployment of sexuality across time  

and space.”65 It is thus this “closeting of history” that produces the “hegemonic  

heterosexual” - the ideological construction of a particular alignment of sex,  

gender and desire that posits itself as natural, inevitable and eternal.66  

Heterosexuality becomes the site where the male sexed masculine man’s  

desire for the female sexed feminine woman is privileged over all other forms  

                                                           65 Zaid Al Baset, “Section 377 and the Myth of Heterosexuality”, Jindal Global Law Review, Vol. 4 (2012).  66 Ibid.

297

PART D  

35    

of sexual desire and becomes a pervasive norm that structures all societal  

structures.67  

   

The expression ‘carnal’ is susceptible to a wide range of meanings.  Among  

them are:   

“sexual, sensual, erotic, lustful, lascivious, libidinous, lecherous, licentious,  

lewd, prurient, salacious, coarse, gross, lubricious, venereal.”    

 

That’s not all. The word incorporates meanings such as: “physical,  

bodily, corporeal and of the flesh.”  The late Middle English origin of ‘carnal’  

derives from Christian Latin ‘carnalis’, from caro, carn – ‘flesh’.  At one end of  

the spectrum ‘carnal’ embodies something which relates to the physical  

feelings and desires of the body.  In another sense, the word implies ‘a  

relation to the body or flesh as the state of basic physical appetites’.  In a  

pejorative sense, it conveys grossness or lewdness. The simple question  

which we need to ask ourselves is whether liberty and equality can be made  

to depend on such vagueness of expression and indeterminacy of content.   

Section 377 is based on a moral notion that intercourse which is lustful is to  

be frowned upon. It finds the sole purpose of intercourse in procreation.  In  

doing so, it imposes criminal sanctions upon basic human urges, by targeting  

                                                           67 Ibid.

298

PART D  

36    

some of them as against the order of nature.  It does so, on the basis of a  

social hypocrisy which the law embraces as its own.  It would have human  

beings lead sanitized lives, in which physical relationships are conditioned by  

a moral notion of what nature does or does not ordain. It would have human  

beings accept a way of life in which sexual contact without procreation is an  

aberration and worse still, penal. It would ask of a section of our citizens that  

while love, they may, the physical manifestation of their love is criminal. This  

is manifest arbitrariness writ large.   

 

If it is difficult to locate any intelligible differentia between indeterminate terms  

such as ‘natural’ and ‘unnatural’, then it is even more problematic to say that a  

classification between individuals who supposedly engage in ‘natural’  

intercourse and those who engage in ‘carnal intercourse against the order of  

nature’ can be legally valid.  

 In addition to the problem regarding the indeterminacy of the terms, there is a  

logical fallacy in ascribing legality or illegality to the ostensibly universal  

meanings of ‘natural’ and ‘unnatural’ as is pointed out in a scholarly article.68  

Basheer, et al make this point effectively:  

“From the fact that something occurs naturally, it does not  

necessarily follow that it is socially desirable. Similarly, acts  

that are commonly perceived to be ‘unnatural’ may not  

necessarily deserve legal sanction. Illustratively, consider a  

                                                           68 Supra note 61.

299

PART D  

37    

person who walks on his hands all the time. Although this  

may be unnatural, it is certainly not deserving of legal  

censure.  

 

…In fact, several activities that might be seen to contravene  

the order of nature (heart transplants, for example) are  

beneficial and desirable. Even if an unnatural act is harmful to  

the extent that it justifies criminal sanctions being imposed  

against it, the reason for proscribing such an act would be  

that the act is harmful, and not that it is unnatural.”  

 

 

Indeed, there is no cogent reasoning to support the idea that behaviour that  

may be uncommon on the basis of mere statistical probability is necessarily  

abnormal and must be deemed ethically or morally wrong.69 Even behaviour  

that may be considered wrong or unnatural cannot be criminalised without  

sufficient justification given the penal consequences that follow. Section 377  

becomes a blanket offence that covers supposedly all types of non-

procreative ‘natural’ sexual activity without any consideration given to the  

notions of consent and harm.  

 

30 The meaning of ‘natural’ as understood in cases such as Khanu v.  

Emperor70, which interpreted natural sex to mean only sex that would lead to  

procreation, would lead to absurd consequences. Some of the consequences  

have been pointed out thus:  

“The position of the court was thus that ‘natural’ sexual  

intercourse is restricted not only to heterosexual coitus, but  

further only to acts that might possibly result in conception.  

                                                           69 Sex, Morality and the Law, (Lori Gruen and George Panichas eds.), Routledge (1996).   70  AIR (1925) Sind. 286

300

PART D  

38    

Such a formulation of the concept of ‘natural’ sex excludes  

not only the use of contraception, which is likely to have fallen  

outside the hegemonic view of normative sexuality at the  

time, but also heterosexual coitus where one or both partners  

are infertile, or during the ‘safe’ period of a woman’s  

menstrual cycle. It is perhaps unnecessary to state that the  

formulation also excludes oral sex between heterosexual  

partners and any homosexual act whatsoever.”71  

 

The indeterminacy and vagueness of the terms ‘carnal intercourse’ and ‘order  

of nature’ renders Section 377 constitutionally infirm as violating the equality  

clause in Article 14.   

 

While it is evident that the classification is invalid, it is useful to understand its  

purported goal by looking at the legislative history of Section 377. In  

Macaulay’s first draft of the Penal Code, the predecessor to present day  

Section 377 was Clause 36172 which provided a severe punishment for  

touching another for the purpose of ‘unnatural’ lust. Macaulay abhorred the  

idea of any debate or discussion on this ‘heinous crime’. India’s anti-sodomy  

law was conceived, legislated and enforced by the British without any kind of  

public discussion.73 So abhorrent was homosexuality to the moral notions  

which he espoused, that Macaulay believed that the idea of a discussion was  

                                                           71  Andrew Davis, “The Framing of Sex: Evaluating Judicial Discourse on the 'Unnatural Offences'”, Alternative Law  

Journal, Vol. 5 (2006).  72  Clause 361 stated “Whoever, intending to gratify unnatural lust, touches, for that purpose, any person, or any  

animal, or is by his own consent touched by any person, for the purpose of gratifying unnatural lust, shall be  punished with imprisonment of either description for a term which may extend to fourteen years and must not be  less than two years, and shall also be liable to fine.”  

73  Alok Gupta, “Section 377 and the Dignity of Indian Homosexuals” The Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 41  (2006).

301

PART D  

39    

repulsive. Section 377 reveals only the hatred, revulsion and disgust of the  

draftsmen towards certain intimate choices of fellow human beings. The  

criminalization of acts in Section 377 is not based on a legally valid distinction,  

“but on broad moral proclamations that certain kinds of people, singled out by  

their private choices, are less than citizens – or less than human.”74  

 

31 The Naz judgement has been criticised on the ground that even though  

it removed private acts between consenting adults from the purview of Section  

377, it still retained the section along with its problematic terminology  

regarding the ‘order of nature’:75  

“…even though the acts would not be criminal, they would still  

be categorized as “unnatural” in the law. This is not an idle  

terminological issue. As Durkheim noted over a hundred  

years ago, the law also works as a tool that expresses social  

relations.76 Hence, this expression itself is problematic from a  

dignitarian standpoint, otherwise so eloquently referred to by  

the judgement.”   

 

At this point, we look at some of the legislative changes that have taken place  

in India’s criminal law since the enactment of the Penal Code. The Criminal  

Law (Amendment) Act 2013 imported certain understandings of the concept of  

sexual intercourse into its expansive definition of rape in Section 375 of the  

Indian Penal Code, which now goes beyond penile–vaginal penetrative  

                                                           74  Supra note 25.  75  John Sebastian, “The opposite of unnatural intercourse: understanding Section 377 through Section 375, Indian  

Law Review, Vol. 1 (2018).  76   Emile Durkheim, The Division of Labour in Society, Macmillan (1984).

302

PART D  

40    

intercourse.77 It has been argued that if ‘sexual intercourse’ now includes  

many acts which were covered under Section 377, those acts are clearly not  

‘against the order of nature’ anymore. They are, in fact, part of the changed  

meaning of sexual intercourse itself. This means that much of Section 377 has  

not only been rendered redundant but that the very word ‘unnatural’ cannot  

have the meaning that was attributed to it before the 2013 amendment.78  

Section 375 defines the expression rape in an expansive sense, to include  

any one of several acts committed by a man in relation to a woman. The  

offence of rape is established if those acts are committed against her will or  

without the free consent of the woman. Section 375 is a clear indicator that in  

a heterosexual context, certain physical acts between a man and woman are  

excluded from the operation of penal law if they are consenting adults. Many  

of these acts which would have been within the purview of Section 377, stand  

                                                           77   375. A man is said to commit “rape” if he- (a) penetrates his penis, to any extent, into the vagina, mouth, urethra  

or anus of a woman or makes her to do so with him or any other person; or (b) inserts, to any extent, any object or  a part of the body, not being the penis, into the vagina, the urethra or anus of a woman or makes her to do so with  him or any other person; or (c) manipulates any part of the body of a woman so as to cause penetration into the  vagina, urethra, anus or any part of body of such woman or makes her to do so with him or any other person; or  (d) applies his mouth to the vagina, anus, urethra of a woman or makes her to do so with him or any other person,  under the circumstances falling under any of the following seven descriptions:— First.—Against her will.  Secondly.—Without her consent. Thirdly.—With her consent, when her consent has been obtained by putting her  or any person in whom she is interested, in fear of death or of hurt. Fourthly.—With her consent, when the man  knows that he is not her husband and that her consent is given because she believes that he is another man to  whom she is or believes herself to be lawfully married. Fifthly.—With her consent when, at the time of giving such  consent, by reason of unsoundness of mind or intoxication or the administration by him personally or through  another of any stupefying or unwholesome substance, she is unable to understand the nature and consequences  of that to which she gives consent Sixthly.—With or without her consent, when she is under eighteen years of  age. Seventhly.—When she is unable to communicate consent. Explanation 1.—For the purposes of this section,  "vagina" shall also include labia majora. Explanation 2.—Consent means an unequivocal voluntary agreement  when the woman by words, gestures or any form of verbal or non-verbal communication, communicates  willingness to participate in the specific sexual act: Provided that a woman who does not physically resist to the  act of penetration shall not by the reason only of that fact, be regarded as consenting to the sexual activity.  Exception 1.—A medical procedure or intervention shall not constitute rape. Exception 2.—Sexual intercourse or  sexual acts by a man with his own wife, the wife not being under fifteen years of age, is not rape.  

78   Supra note 75, at pages 232-249.

303

PART D  

41    

excluded from criminal liability when they take place in the course of  

consensual heterosexual contact. Parliament has ruled against them being  

regarded against the ‘order of nature’, in the context of Section 375. Yet those  

acts continue to be subject to criminal liability, if two adult men or women were  

to engage in consensual sexual contact. This is a violation of Article 14.      

 

Nivedita Menon opposes the idea that ‘normal’ sexuality springs from nature  

and argues that this idea of ‘normal’ sexuality is a cultural and social  

construct:79  

“Consider the possibility that rules of sexual conduct are as  

arbitrary as traffic rules, created by human societies to  

maintain a certain sort of order, and which could differ from  

place to place -- for example, you drive on the left in India and  

on the right in the USA. Further, let us say you question the  

sort of social order that traffic rules keep in place. Say you  

believe that traffic rules in Delhi are the product of a model of  

urban planning that privileges the rich and penalizes the poor,  

that this order encourages petrol-consuming private vehicles  

and discourages forms of transport that are energy-saving --  

cycles, public transport, pedestrians. You would then question  

that model of the city that forces large numbers of inhabitants  

to travel long distances every day simply to get to school  

andwork. You could debate the merits of traffic rules and  

urban planning on the grounds of convenience, equity and  

sustainability of natural resources -- at least, nobody could  

seriously argue that any set of traffic rules is natural.”  

 

 

32 The struggle of citizens belonging to sexual minorities is located within  

the larger history of the struggles against various forms of social subordination

                                                           79  Nivedita Menon, “How Natural is Normal? Feminism and Compulsory Heterosexuality”, In Because I have a Voice,  

Queer Politics in India, (Narrain and Bhan eds.) Yoda Press (2005).

304

PART E  

42    

in India. The order of nature that Section 377 speaks of is not just about non-

procreative sex but is about forms of intimacy which the social order finds  

“disturbing”.80 This includes various forms of transgression such as inter-caste  

and inter-community relationships which are sought to be curbed by society.  

What links LGBT individuals to couples who love across caste and community  

lines is the fact that both are exercising their right to love at enormous  

personal risk and in the process disrupting existing lines of social authority.81  

Thus, a re-imagination of the order of nature as being not only about the  

prohibition of non-procreative sex but instead about the limits imposed by  

structures such as gender, caste, class, religion and community makes the  

right to love not just a separate battle for LGBT individuals, but a battle for  

all.82  

     

E Beyond physicality: sex, identity and stereotypes  

“Only in the most technical sense is this a case about who  

may penetrate whom where. At a practical and symbolical  

level it is about the status, moral citizenship and sense of self-

worth of a significant section of the community. At a more  

general and conceptual level, it concerns the nature of the  

open, democratic and pluralistic society contemplated by the  

Constitution.”83  

 

 

                                                           80  Supra note 7.  81  Ibid.  82  Supra note 7.  83 The National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v. The Minister of Justice, 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC), Sachs J.,  

concurring.  

305

PART E  

43    

33 The Petitioners contend that (i) Section 377 discriminates on the basis  

of sex and violates Articles 15 and 16; and (ii) Discrimination on the ground of  

sexual orientation is in fact, discrimination on the ground of sex. The  

intervenors argue that (i) Section 377 criminalizes acts and not people; (ii) It is  

not discriminatory because the prohibition on anal and oral sex applies equally  

to both heterosexual and homosexual couples; and (iii) Article 15 prohibits  

discrimination on the ground of ‘sex’ which cannot be interpreted so broadly  

as to include ‘sexual orientation’.  

   

34 When the constitutionality of a law is challenged on the ground that it  

violates the guarantees in Part III of the Constitution, what is determinative is  

its effect on the infringement of fundamental rights.84 This affords the  

guaranteed freedoms their true potential against a claim by the state that the  

infringement of the right was not the object of the provision. It is not the object  

of the law which impairs the rights of the citizens. Nor is the form of the action  

taken determinative of the protection that can be claimed. It is the effect of the  

law upon the fundamental right which calls the courts to step in and remedy  

the violation. The individual is aggrieved because the law hurts. The hurt to  

the individual is measured by the violation of a protected right. Hence, while  

                                                           84   Re. the Kerala Education Bill, AIR 1958 SC 956 at para 26; Sakal Papers v Union of India, AIR 1962 SC 305 at  

para  42; R.C. Cooper v Union of India, (1970) 1 SCC 248 at paras 43, 49; Bennett Coleman v. Union of India,  AIR (1972) 2 SCC 788 at para 39; Maneka Gandhi v Union of India, (1978) 1 SCC 248 at para 19.  

306

PART E  

44    

assessing whether a law infringes a fundamental right, it is not the intention of  

the lawmaker that is determinative, but whether the effect or operation of the  

law infringes fundamental rights.   

 

Article 15 of the Constitution reads thus:  

“15. (1) The State shall not discriminate against any citizen on  

grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, place of birth or any  

of them.”             (Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

 

Article 15 prohibits the State from discriminating on grounds only of sex. Early  

judicial pronouncements adjudged whether discrimination aimed only at sex is  

covered by Article 15 or whether the guarantee is attracted even to a  

discrimination on the basis of sex and some other grounds (‘Sex plus’). The  

argument was that since Article 15 prohibited discrimination on only specified  

grounds, discrimination resulting from a specified ground coupled with other  

considerations is not prohibited. The view was that if the discrimination is  

justified on the grounds of sex and another factor, it would not be covered by  

the prohibition in Article 15.   

 

35 One of the earliest cases decided in 1951 was by the Calcutta High  

Court in Sri Sri Mahadev Jiew v. Dr. B B Sen85. Under Order XXV, R. 1 of  

the Code of Civil Procedure, men could be made liable for paying a security  

                                                           85 AIR (1951) Cal. 563.

307

PART E  

45    

cost if they did not possess sufficient movable property in India only if they  

were residing outside India. However, women were responsible for paying  

such security, regardless of whether or not they were residing in India. In  

other words, the law drew a distinction between resident males who did not  

have sufficient immovable property, and resident females who did not have  

sufficient immovable property. Upholding the provision, the Calcutta High  

Court held:  

“31. Article 15(1) of the Constitution pro-vides, inter alia, --  

The State shall not discriminate against any citizen on  

grounds only of sex. The word ‘only’ in this Article is of great  

importance and significance which should not be missed. The  

impugned law must be shown to discriminate because of sex  

alone. If other factors in addition to sex come into play in  

making the discriminatory law, then such discrimination  

does not, in my judgment, come within the provision of  

Article 15(1) of the Constitution.”      (Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

This interpretation was upheld by this Court in Air India v. Nergesh Meerza  

(“Nergesh Meerza”).86 Regulations 46 and 47 of the Air India Employees’  

Service Regulations were challenged for causing a disparity between the pay  

and promotional opportunities of men and women in-flight cabin crew. Under  

Regulation 46, while the retirement age for male Flight Pursers was fifty eight,  

Air Hostesses were required to retire at thirty five, or on marriage (if they  

married within four years of joining service), or on their first  

pregnancy, whichever occurred earlier. This period could be extended in the  

                                                           86 (1981) 4 SCC 335  

308

PART E  

46    

absolute discretion of the Managing Director. Even though the two cadres  

were constituted on the grounds of sex, the Court upheld the Regulations in  

part and opined:   

“68. Even otherwise, what Articles 15(1) and 16(2) prohibit  

is that discrimination should not be made only and only  

on the ground of sex. These Articles of the Constitution  

do not prohibit the State from making discrimination on  

the ground of sex coupled with other considerations.”   

(Emphasis supplied)    

 

36 This formalistic interpretation of Article 15 would render the  

constitutional guarantee against discrimination meaningless. For it would  

allow the State to claim that the discrimination was based on sex and another  

ground (‘Sex plus’) and hence outside the ambit of Article 15. Latent in the  

argument of the discrimination, are stereotypical notions of the differences  

between men and women which are then used to justify the discrimination.  

This narrow view of Article 15 strips the prohibition on discrimination of its  

essential content. This fails to take into account the intersectional nature of  

sex discrimination, which cannot be said to operate in isolation of other  

identities, especially from the socio-political and economic context. For  

example, a rule that people over six feet would not be employed in the army  

would be able to stand an attack on its disproportionate impact on women if it  

was maintained that the discrimination is on the basis of sex and height.  Such

309

PART E  

47    

a formalistic view of the prohibition in Article 15, rejects the true operation of  

discrimination, which intersects varied identities and characteristics.   

 

37 A divergent note was struck by this Court in Anuj Garg v. Hotel  

Association of India87. Section 30 of the Punjab Excise Act, 1914 prohibited  

the employment of women (and men under 25 years) in premises where liquor  

or other intoxicating drugs were consumed by the public. Striking down the  

law as suffering from “incurable fixations of stereotype morality and  

conception of sexual role”, the Court held:  

“42… one issue of immediate relevance in such cases is  

the effect of the traditional cultural norms as also the  

state of general ambience in the society which women  

have to face while opting for an employment which is  

otherwise completely innocuous for the male  

counterpart...”   

“43…It is state’s duty to ensure circumstances of safety  

which inspire confidence in women to discharge the duty  

freely in accordance to the requirements of the profession  

they choose to follow. Any other policy inference (such as  

the one embodied under section 30) from societal  

conditions would be oppressive on the women and  

against the privacy rights.”               (Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

The Court recognized that traditional cultural norms stereotype gender roles.  

These stereotypes are premised on assumptions about socially ascribed roles  

of gender which discriminate against women. The Court held that “insofar as  

governmental policy is based on the aforesaid cultural norms, it is  

                                                           87(2008) 3 SCC 1

310

PART E  

48    

constitutionally invalid.” In the same line, the Court also cited with approval,  

the judgments of the US Supreme Court in Frontiero v. Richardson88, and  

United States v. Virginia89, and Justice Marshall’s dissent in Dothard v.  

Rawlinson90, The Court grounded the anti-stereotyping principle as firmly  

rooted in the prohibition under Article 15.   

 

In National Legal Services Authority v. Union of India (“NALSA”)91, while  

dealing with the rights of transgender persons under the Constitution, this  

Court opined:  

“66. Articles 15 and 16 sought to prohibit discrimination  

on the basis of sex, recognizing that sex discrimination  

is a historical fact and needs to be addressed.  

Constitution makers, it can be gathered, gave emphasis  

to the fundamental right against sex discrimination so as  

to prevent the direct or indirect attitude to treat people  

differently, for the reason of not being in conformity with  

stereotypical generalizations of binary genders. Both  

gender and biological attributes constitute distinct  

components of sex. Biological characteristics, of course,  

include genitals, chromosomes and secondary sexual  

features, but gender attributes include one’s self image, the  

deep psychological or emotional sense of sexual identity and  

character. The discrimination on the ground of ‘sex’ Under  

                                                           88  411 U.S. 677 (1973). The case concerned a statute that allowed service-members to claim additional benefits if  

their spouse was dependent on them. A male claimant would automatically be entitled to such benefits while a  female claimant would have to prove that her spouse was dependent on her for more than half his support. The  Court struck down this statute stating that the legislation violated the equal protection clause of the American  Constitution.  

89  518 U.S. 515 (1996). The case concerned the Virginia Military Institute (VMI), which had a stated objected of  producing “citizen-soldiers.” However, it did not admit women. The Court held that such a provision was  unconstitutional and that there were no “fixed notions concerning the roles and abilities of males and females.”  

90  433 U.S. 321 (1977).The case concerned an effective bar on females for the position of guards or correctional  counsellors in the Alabama State Penitentiary system. Justice Marshall’s dissent held that prohibition of women in  ‘contact positions’ violated the Title VII guarantee.   

91    (2014) 5 SCC 438

311

PART E  

49    

Articles 15 and 16, therefore, includes discrimination on the  

ground of gender identity.”        (Emphasis supplied)  

 

This approach, in my view, is correct.  

In Nergesh Meerza, this Court held that where persons of a particular class,  

in view of the “special attributes, qualities” are treated differently in ‘public  

interest’, such a classification would not be discriminatory. The Court opined  

that since the modes of recruitment, promotional avenues and other matters  

were different for Air Hostesses, they constituted a class separate from male  

Flight Pursers. This, despite noting that “a perusal of the job functions which  

have been detailed in the affidavit, clearly shows that the functions of the two,  

though obviously different overlap on some points but the difference, if any, is  

one of degree rather than of kind.”  

 

38 The Court did not embark on the preliminary enquiry as to whether the  

initial classification between the two cadres, being grounded in sex, was  

violative of the constitutional guarantee against discrimination. Referring  

specifically to the three significant disabilities that the Regulations imposed on  

Air Hostesses, the Court held that “there can be no doubt that these peculiar  

conditions do form part of the Regulations governing Air Hostesses but once  

we have held that Air Hostesses form a separate category with different and

312

PART E  

50    

separate incidents the circumstances pointed out by the petitioners cannot  

amount to discrimination so as to violate Article 14 of the Constitution on this  

ground.”   

 

39 The basis of the classification was that only men could become male  

Flight Pursers and only women could become Air Hostesses. The very  

constitution of the cadre was based on sex. What this meant was, that to pass  

the non-discrimination test found in Article 15, the State merely had to create  

two separate classes based on sex and constitute two separate cadres. That  

would not be discriminatory.   

The Court went a step ahead and opined:  

“80…Thus, the Regulation permits an AH to marry at the age  

of 23 if she has joined the service at the age of 19 which is by  

all standards a very sound and salutary provision. Apart from  

improving the health of the employee, it helps a good in  

the promotion and boosting up of our family planning  

programme. Secondly, if a woman marries near about the  

age of 20 to 23 years, she becomes fully mature and  

there is every chance of such a marriage proving a  

success, all things being equal. Thirdly, it has been  

rightly pointed out to us by the Corporation that if the bar  

of marriage within four years of service is removed then  

the Corporation will have to incur huge expenditure in  

recruiting additional AHs either on a temporary or on ad  

hoc basis to replace the working AHs if they conceive  

and any period short of four years would be too little a  

time for the Corporation to phase out such an ambitious  

plan.”                   (Emphasis supplied)  

313

PART E  

51    

40 A strong stereotype underlines the judgment. The Court did not  

recognize that men were not subject to the same standards with respect to  

marriage. It holds that the burdens of health and family planning rest solely on  

women. This perpetuates the notion that the obligations of raising family are  

those solely of the woman. In dealing with the provision for termination of  

service on the first pregnancy, the Court opined that a substituted provision for  

termination on the third pregnancy would be in the “larger interest of the  

health of the Air Hostesses concerned as also for the good upbringing of the  

children.” Here again, the Court’s view rested on a stereotype. The patronizing  

attitude towards the role of women compounds the difficulty in accepting the  

logic of Nergesh Meerza. This approach, in my view, is patently incorrect.   

 

41 A discriminatory act will be tested against constitutional values. A  

discrimination will not survive constitutional scrutiny when it is grounded in  

and perpetuates stereotypes about a class constituted by the grounds  

prohibited in Article 15(1). If any ground of discrimination, whether direct or  

indirect is founded on a stereotypical understanding of the role of the sex, it  

would not be distinguishable from the discrimination which is prohibited by  

Article 15 on the grounds only of sex. If certain characteristics grounded in  

stereotypes, are to be associated with entire classes of people constituted as  

groups by any of the grounds prohibited in Article 15(1), that cannot establish

314

PART E  

52    

a permissible reason to discriminate. Such a discrimination will be in violation  

of the constitutional guarantee against discrimination in Article 15(1). That  

such a discrimination is a result of grounds rooted in sex and other  

considerations, can no longer be held to be a position supported by the  

intersectional understanding of how discrimination operates. This infuses  

Article 15 with true rigour to give it a complete constitutional dimension in  

prohibiting discrimination.  

The approach adopted the Court in Nergesh Meerza, is incorrect.     

A provision challenged as being ultra vires the prohibition of discrimination on  

the grounds only of sex under Article 15(1) is to be assessed not by the  

objects of the state in enacting it, but by the effect that the provision has on  

affected individuals and on their fundamental rights. Any ground of  

discrimination, direct or indirect, which is founded on a particular  

understanding of the role of the sex, would not be distinguishable from the  

discrimination which is prohibited by Article 15 on the grounds only of sex.    

 

E.I Facial neutrality: through the looking glass   

 42 The moral belief which underlies Section 377 is that sexual activities  

which do not result in procreation are against the ‘order of nature’ and ought

315

PART E  

53    

to be criminalized under Section 377. The intervenors submit that Section  

377, criminalizes anal and oral sex by heterosexual couples as well. Hence, it  

is urged that Section 377 applies equally to all conduct against the ‘order of  

nature’, irrespective of sexual orientation. This submission is incorrect.  In  

NALSA this Court held that Section 377, though associated with specific  

sexual acts, highlights certain identities. In Naz, the Delhi High Court  

demonstrated effectively how Section 377 though facially neutral in its  

application to certain acts, targets specific communities in terms of its impact:  

“Section 377 IPC is facially neutral and it apparently  

targets not identities but acts, but in its operation it does  

end up unfairly targeting a particular community. The fact  

is that these sexual acts which are criminalised are  

associated more closely with one class of persons,  

namely, the homosexuals as a class. Section 377 IPC has  

the effect of viewing all gay men as criminals. When everything  

associated with homosexuality is treated as bent, queer,  

repugnant, the whole gay and lesbian community is marked  

with deviance and perversity. They are subject to extensive  

prejudice because what they are or what they are  

perceived to be, not because of what they do. The result is  

that a significant group of the population is, because of its  

sexual nonconformity, persecuted, marginalised and  

turned in on itself.”92 (Emphasis supplied)  

 

To this end, it chronicled the experiences of the victims of Section 377, relying  

on the extensive records and affidavits submitted by the Petitioners that  

brought to fore instances of custodial rape and torture, social boycott,  

degrading and inhuman treatment and incarceration. The court concluded that  

while Section 377 criminalized conduct, it created a systemic pattern of                                                              92 Naz, at para 94.

316

PART E  

54    

disadvantage, exclusion and indignity for the LGBT community, and for  

individuals who indulge in non-heterosexual conduct.    

 

43 Jurisprudence across national frontiers supports the principle that  

facially neutral action by the State may have a disproportionate impact upon a  

particular class. In Europe, Directive 2006/54/EC of the European  

Parliament and of the Council of 5 July 2006 defines ‘indirect  

discrimination’ as: “where an apparently neutral provision, criterion or practice  

would put persons of one sex at a particular disadvantage compared with  

persons of the other sex, unless that provision, criterion or practice is  

objectively justified by a legitimate aim, and the means of achieving that aim  

are appropriate and necessary.”   

 

In Griggs v Duke Power Co.93, the US Supreme Court, whilst recognizing  

that African-Americans received sub-standard education due to segregated  

schools, opined that the requirement of an aptitude/intelligence test  

disproportionately affected African-American candidates. The Court held that  

“The Civil Rights Act” proscribes not only overt discrimination but also  

practices that are fair in form, but discriminatory in operation.”  

                                                           93 401 U.S. 424 (1971)

317

PART E  

55    

In Bilka-Kaufhaus GmbH v. Karin Weber von Hartz94, the European Court  

of Justice held that denying pensions to part-time employees is more likely to  

affect women, as women were more likely to take up part-time jobs. The Court  

noted:  

“Article 119 of the EEC Treaty is infringed by a department  

store company which excludes part-time employees from its  

occupational pension scheme, where that exclusion affects  

a far greater number of women than men, unless the  

undertaking shows that the exclusion is based on objectively  

justified factors unrelated to any discrimination on grounds of  

sex.”     (Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

The Canadian Supreme Court endorsed the notion of a disparate impact  

where an action has a disproportionate impact on a class of persons. In  

Andrews v. Law Society of British Columbia95, the Court noted:  

“Discrimination is a distinction which, whether intentional or  

not but based on grounds relating to personal characteristics  

of the individual or group, has an effect which imposes  

disadvantages not imposed upon others or which withholds or  

limits access to advantages available to other members of  

society. Distinctions based on personal characteristics  

attributed to an individual solely on the basis of  

association with a group will rarely escape the charge of  

discrimination, while those based on an individual's merits  

and capacities will rarely be so classed.” (Emphasis supplied)  

 

Thus, when an action has “the effect of imposing burdens, obligations, or  

disadvantages on such individual or group not imposed upon others, or which  

                                                           94 (1986) ECR 1607  95  (1989) 1 SCR 143  

318

PART E  

56    

withholds or limits access to opportunities, benefits, and advantages available  

to other members of society”,96 it would be suspect.  

 

In City Council of Pretoria v. Walker97, the Constitutional Court of South  

Africa observed:   

“The concept of indirect discrimination, … was developed  

precisely to deal with situations where discrimination lay  

disguised behind apparently neutral criteria or where  

persons already adversely hit by patterns of historic  

subordination had their disadvantage entrenched or  

intensified by the impact of measures not overtly  

intended to prejudice them.   

 

In many cases, particularly those in which indirect  

discrimination is alleged, the protective purpose would  

be defeated if the persons complaining of discrimination  

had to prove not only that they were unfairly  

discriminated against but also that the unfair  

discrimination was intentional. This problem would be  

particularly acute in cases of indirect discrimination  

where there is almost always some purpose other than  

a discriminatory purpose involved in the conduct or  

action to which objection is taken.”                                

(Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

E.2 Deconstructing the polarities of binary genders    

 44 Section 377 criminalizes behaviour that does not conform to the  

heterosexual expectations of society. In doing so it perpetuates a symbiotic  

relationship between anti-homosexual legislation and traditional gender roles.  

                                                           96 Ibid.   97 (1998) 3 BCLR 257

319

PART E  

57    

The notion that the nature of relationships is fixed and within the ‘order of  

nature’ is perpetuated by gender roles, thus excluding homosexuality from the  

narrative. The effect is described as follows:  

“Cultural homophobia thus discourages social behavior that  

appears to threaten the stability of heterosexual gender roles.  

These dual normative standards of social and sexual  

behavior construct the image of a gay man as abnormal  

because he deviates from the masculine gender role by  

subjecting himself in the sexual act to another man.”98  

 

 

If individuals as well as society hold strong beliefs about gender roles – that  

men (to be characteristically reductive) are unemotional, socially dominant,  

breadwinners that are attracted to women and women are emotional, socially  

submissive, caretakers that are attracted to men – it is unlikely that such  

persons or society at large will accept that the idea that two men or two  

women could maintain a relationship. If such a denial is further grounded in a  

law, such as Article 377 the effect is to entrench the belief that homosexuality  

is an aberration that falls outside the ‘normal way of life.’   

 

45 An instructive article by Zachary A. Kramer,99 notes that a heterosexist  

society both expects and requires men and women to engage in only  

opposite-sex sexual relationships. The existence of same-sex relationships is,  

                                                           98  Elvia R. Arriola, “Gendered Inequality: Lesbians, Gays, and Feminist Legal Theory”, Berkeley Women’s Law  

Journal, Vol. 9 (1994), at pages 103-143.  99 Zachary A. Kramer, “The Ultimate Gender Stereotype: Equalizing Gender-Conforming and Gender-Nonconforming  

Homosexuals under Title VII”, University of Illinois Law Review (2004), at page 490.  

320

PART E  

58    

therefore, repugnant to heterosexist societal expectations. Kramer argues  

that:  

“Discrimination against gays and lesbians reinforces  

traditional sex roles. The primary thrust of such discrimination  

is the gender-based stigmatization of gays and lesbians,  

deriving from the idea that homosexuality departs from  

traditional gender roles and that “real” men and women  

should not be attracted to a member of the same sex. This  

portrayal relies heavily on what Bennett Capers calls the  

“binary gender system.”100  

 

 

46 Bennett Capers defines the binary gender system as based in  

“heterosexism,” which he defines as the “institutionalized valorization of  

heterosexual activity.” Capers, in fact suggests that:  

“The sanctioning of discrimination based on sexual orientation  

perpetuates the subordination not only of lesbians and gays  

but of women as well.   

 

Heterosexism, then, in its reliance on a bipolar system of sex  

and gender, reinforces sexism in two ways. First, by  

penalizing persons who do not conform to a bipolar gender  

system and rewarding men and women who do, the  

heterosexist hegemony perpetuates a schema that valorizes  

passive, dependent women, thus contributing to sexism.  

Second, heterosexism reinforces sexism because it  

subordinates the female sex through its hierarchical polarity.  

Because heterosexism perpetuates sexism, the extension of  

substantial rights to lesbians and gays, who by definition  

challenge heterosexism and the concept of a binary gender  

system, would result in a challenge to sexism and to male  

power.” 101   

 

 

                                                           100 Ibid.   101 Bennett Capers, “Note, Sexual Orientation and Title VII”, Columbia Law Review (1991), at pages 1159, 1160,  

1163.  

321

PART E  

59    

In other words, one cannot simply separate discrimination based on sexual  

orientation and discrimination based on sex because discrimination based on  

sexual orientation inherently promulgates ideas about stereotypical notions of  

sex and gender roles. Taking this further, Andrew Koppelman argues that:   

“Similarly, sodomy laws discriminate on the basis of sex-for  

example, permitting men, but not women, to have sex with  

women-in order to impose traditional sex roles. The Court has  

deemed this purpose impermissible in other contexts because  

it perpetuates the subordination of women. The same  

concern applies with special force to the sodomy laws,  

because their function is to maintain the polarities of gender  

on which the subordination of women depends.”102   

 

 

Koppelman thus suggests that the taboo against homosexuals “polices the  

boundaries that separate the dominant from the dominated in a social  

hierarchy.”103 He expands on this idea, using the analogy of miscegenation, or  

the interbreeding of races:   

“Do statutes that outlaw homosexual sex impose traditional  

sex roles? One possible answer is that of McLaughlin  

[McLaughlin v. Florida]: The crime is by definition one of  

engaging in activity inappropriate to one's sex. But these  

statutes' inconsistency with the Constitution's command of  

equality is deeper. Like the miscegenation statutes, the  

sodomy statutes reflect and reinforce the morality of a  

hierarchy based on birth. Just as the prohibition of  

miscegenation preserved the polarities of race on which white  

supremacy rested, so the prohibition of sodomy preserves the  

polarities of gender on which rests the subordination of  

women.”104  

 

                                                           102  Andrew Koppelman, “The Miscegenation Analogy: Sodomy Law as Sex Discrimination”, Yale Law Journal, Vol.  

98 (1988), at page 147.  103 Andrew Koppelman, “Why Discrimination against Lesbians and Gay Men is Sex Discrimination”, New York  

University Law Review, Vol. 69 (1994).  104  Supra note 102, at page 148.

322

PART E  

60    

Statutes like Section 377 give people ammunition to say “this is what a man  

is” by giving them a law which says “this is what a man is not.” Thus, laws that  

affect non-heterosexuals rest upon a normative stereotype: “the bald  

conviction that certain behavior-for example, sex with women-is appropriate  

for members of one sex, but not for members of the other sex.”105  

 

What this shows us is that LGBT individuals as well as those who do not  

conform to societal expectations of sexual behaviour defy gender stereotypes.   

“The construction of gender stereotypes ultimately rests on the  

assumption that there are two opposite and mutually exclusive  

biological sexes. The assumption of heterosexuality is central  

to this gender binary. In a patriarchal context, some of the  

most serious transgressors are thus: a woman who renounces  

a man sexual partner or an individual assigned female at birth  

who renounces womanhood, thereby rejecting the patriarchal  

system and all other forms of male supervision and control,  

and an individual assigned male at birth who embraces  

womanhood, thereby abandoning privilege in favor of that  

which is deemed subservient, femininity.”106   

 

 

Prohibition of sex discrimination is meant to change traditional practices which  

legally, and often socially and economically, disadvantage persons on the  

basis of gender. The case for gay rights undoubtedly seeks justice for gays.  

But it goes well beyond the concern for the gay community. The effort to end  

                                                           105  Ibid.   106 The Relationship between Homophobia, Transphobia, and Women’s Access to Justice for the Forthcoming  

CEDAW General Recommendation on Women’s Access to Justice. Submitted to the United Nations Committee  for the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (2013).

323

PART E  

61    

discrimination against gays should be understood as a necessary part of the  

larger effort to end the inequality of the sexes.  

“To be a lesbian is to be perceived (labelled) as someone  

who has stepped out of line, who has moved out of  

sexual/economic dependence on a male, who is woman-

identified. A lesbian is perceived as someone who can live  

without a man, and who is therefore (however illogically)  

against men. A lesbian is perceived as being outside the  

acceptable, routinized order of things. She is seen as  

someone who has no societal institutions to protect her and  

who is not privileged to the protection of individual males. A  

lesbian is perceived as a threat to the nuclear family, to male  

dominance and control, to the very heart of sexism.”107  

 

 

Commenting on its link with the essence of Article 15, Tarunabh Khaitan  

writes:  

“But the salience of a case on discrimination against a  

politically disempowered minority, based purely on the  

prejudices of a majority, goes beyond the issue of LGBTQ  

rights. Indian constitutional democracy is at a  

crossroads…Inclusiveness and pluralism lie at the heart of  

Article 15, which can be our surest vehicle for the Court to  

lend its institutional authority to the salience of these ideas in  

our constitutional identity.”108  

 

47 Relationships that tend to undermine the male/female divide are  

inherently required for the maintenance of a socially imposed gender  

inequality. Relationships which question the divide are picked up for target  

and abuse. Section 377 allows this. By attacking these gender roles,  

members of the affected community, in their move to build communities and  

                                                           107 Suzanne Pharr, Homophobia: A weapon of Sexism, Chardon Press (1988), at page18.  108 Tarunabh Khaitan, “Inclusive Pluralism or Majoritarian Nationalism: Article 15, Section 377 and Who We Really  

Are”, Indian Constitutional Law and Philosophy (2018).  

324

PART E  

62    

relationships premised on care and reciprocity, lay challenge to the idea that  

relationships, and by extension society, must be divided along hierarchical  

sexual roles in order to function. For members of the community, hostility and  

exclusion aimed at them, drive them into hiding, away from public expression  

and view. It is this discrimination faced by the members of the community,  

which results in silence, and consequently invisibility, creating barriers,  

systemic and deliberate, that effect their participation in the work force and  

thus undermines substantive equality. In the sense that the prohibition of  

miscegenation was aimed to preserve and perpetuate the polarities of race to  

protect white supremacy, the prohibition of homosexuality serves to ensure a  

larger system of social control based on gender and sex.  

 

48 A report prepared by the International Commission of Jurists109 has  

documented the persecution faced by the affected community due to the  

operation of Section 377. The report documents numerous violations inflicted  

on people under the authority of Section 377. According to the National Crime  

Records Bureau, 1279 persons in 2014 and 1491 in 2015 were arrested under  

Section 377.110  

 

                                                           109 International Commission of Jurists, “Unnatural Offences” Obstacles to Justice in India Based on Sexual  

Orientation and Gender Identity (2017).   110  Ibid, at page 16.  

325

PART E  

63    

The report documents instances of abuse from law enforcement agencies and  

how the possibility of persecution under Section 377 prevents redress.111  

Even though acts such as blackmail, assault, and bodily crimes are  

punishable under penal laws, such methods of seeking redressal are not  

accessed by those communities given the fear of retaliation or prosecution.   

   

49 The petitioners in the present batch of cases have real life narrations of  

suffering discrimination, prejudice and hate. In Anwesh Pokkuluri v. UOI112,  

with which this case is connected, the Petitioners are a group of persons  

belonging to the LGBTQ community, each of whom has excelled in their fields  

but suffer immensely due to the operation of Section 377. To cope with the  

growing isolation among the community, these Petitioners, all alumni of Indian  

Institutes of Technology across the country, created a closed group called  

“Pravritti”. The group consists of persons from the LGBTQ community. They  

are faculty members, students, alumni and anyone who has ever stayed on  

the campus of any IIT in the country. The group was formed in 2012 to help  

members cope with loneliness and difficulties faced while accepting their  

identity along with holding open discussions on awareness.   

   

                                                           111 Ibid, at pages 16 – 18.  112 Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 121 of 2018.

326

PART E  

64    

50 Out of twenty Petitioners, sixteen are gay, two are bisexual women and  

one is a bisexual man. One among the Petitioners is a transwoman.  Three of  

the Petitioners explain that they suffered immense mental agony due to which  

they were on the verge of committing suicide. Another two stated that  

speaking about their sexual identity has been difficult, especially since they  

did not have the support of their families, who, upon learning of their sexual  

orientation, took them for psychiatric treatment to cure the so-called “disease.”  

The families of three Petitioners ignored their sexual identity. One of them  

qualified to become an Indian Administrative Services officer in an  

examination which more than 4,00,000 people write each year. But he chose  

to forgo his dream because of the fear that he would be discriminated against  

on the ground of his sexuality. Some of them have experienced depression;  

others faced problems focusing on their studies while growing up; one among  

them was forced to drop out of high school as she was residing in a girl’s  

hostel where the authorities questioned her identity. The parents of one of  

them brushed his sexuality under the carpet and suggested that he marry a  

woman. Some doubted whether or not they should continue their relationships  

given the atmosphere created by Section 377. Several work in organisations  

that have policies protecting the LGBT community in place. Having faced so  

much pain in their personal lives, the Petitioners submit that with the  

continued operation of Section 377, such treatment will be unabated.

327

PART E  

65    

51 In Navtej Johar v. Union of India113, with which this case is concerned,  

the Petitioners have set out multiple instances of discrimination and expulsion.  

The following is a realistic account:  

“While society, friends and family are accepting of my  

sexuality, I cannot be fully open about my identity and my  

relationships because I constantly fear arrest and violence by  

the police…Without the existence of this section, the social  

prejudice and shame that I have faced would have been  

considerably lessened…the fact that gay people, like me, are  

recognized only as criminals is deeply upsetting and denies  

me the dignity and respect that I feel I deserve.114  

 

 

Apart from the visible social manifestations of Section 377, the retention of the  

provision perpetuates a certain culture. The stereotypes fostered by section  

377 have an impact on how other individuals and non-state institutions treat  

the community. While this behaviour is not sanctioned by Section 377, the  

existence of the provision nonetheless facilitates it by perpetuating  

homophobic attitudes and making it almost impossible for victims of abuse to  

access justice. Thus, the social effects of such a provision, even when it is  

enforced with zeal, is to sanction verbal harassment, familial fear, restricted  

access to public spaces and the lack of safe spaces. This results in a denial of  

the self. Identities are obliterated, denying the entitlement to equal  

participation and dignity under the Constitution. Section 377 deprives them of  

an equal citizenship. Referring to the effect of Foucault’s panopticon in  

                                                           113 Writ Petition (Criminal) No. 76 of 2016.  114 Written Submission on Behalf of the Voices Against 377, in W.P. (CRL.) No. 76/2016 at page 18.

328

PART E  

66    

inducing “a state of conscious and permanent visibility that assures the  

automatic functioning of power”,115 Ryan Goodman writes:  

“The state's relationship to lesbian and gay individuals under  

a regime of sodomy laws constructs a similar, yet dispersed,  

structure of observation and surveillance. The public is  

sensitive to the visibility of lesbians and gays as socially  

and legally constructed miscreants. Admittedly certain  

individuals, namely those who are certified with various  

levels of state authority, are more directly linked to the  

extension of law's power. Yet the social effects of  

sodomy laws are not tied to these specialized agents  

alone. On the ground level, private individuals also  

perform roles of policing and controlling lesbian and gay  

lives in a mimetic relation to the modes of justice  

itself.”116                (Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

The effect of Section 377, thus, is not merely to criminalize an act, but to  

criminalize a specific set of identities. Though facially neutral, the effect of the  

provision is to efface specific identities. These identities are the soul of the  

LGBT community.   

 

52 The Constitution envisaged a transformation in the order of relations not  

just between the state and the individual, but also between individuals: in a  

constitutional order characterized by the Rule of Law, the constitutional  

commitment to egalitarianism and an anti-discriminatory ethos permeates and  

infuses these relations. In K S Puttaswamy v. Union of India  

                                                           115 Michel Foucault, Discipline And Punish: the Birth of the Prison, Pantheon Books (1977) at page 201.  116 Ryan Goodman, “Beyond the Enforcement Principle: Sodomy Laws, Social Norms, and Social Panoptics”,  

California Law Review, Vol. 89 (2001), at page 688.

329

PART E  

67    

(“Puttaswamy”)117, this Court affirmed the individual as the bearer of the  

constitutional guarantee of rights. Such rights are devoid of their guarantee  

when despite legal recognition, the social, economic and political context  

enables an atmosphere of continued discrimination. The Constitution enjoins  

upon every individual a commitment to a constitutional democracy  

characterized by the principles of equality and inclusion. In a constitutional  

democracy committed to the protection of individual dignity and autonomy, the  

state and every individual has a duty to act in a manner that advances and  

promotes the constitutional order of values.    

 

By criminalizing consensual sexual conduct between two homosexual adults,  

Section 377 has become the basis not just of prosecutions but of the  

persecution of members of the affected community. Section 377 leads to the  

perpetuation of a culture of silence and stigmatization. Section 377  

perpetuates notions of morality which prohibit certain relationships as being  

against the ‘order of nature.’ A criminal provision has sanctioned  

discrimination grounded on stereotypes imposed on an entire class of persons  

on grounds prohibited by Article 15(1). This constitutes discrimination on the  

grounds only of sex and violates the guarantee of non-discrimination in Article  

15(1)

                                                           117(2017) 10 SCC 1

330

PART F   

68    

53 History has been witness to a systematic stigmatization and exclusion of  

those who do not conform to societal standards of what is expected of them.  

Section 377 rests on deep rooted gender stereotypes. In the quest to assert  

their liberties, people criminalized by the operation of the provision, challenge  

not only its existence, but also a gamut of beliefs that are strongly rooted in  

majoritarian standards of what is ‘normal’. In this quest, the attack on the  

validity of Section 377 is a challenge to a long history of societal discrimination  

and persecution of people based on their identities. They have been  

subjugated to a culture of silence and into leading their lives in closeted  

invisibility. There must come a time when the constitutional guarantee of  

equality and inclusion will end the decades of discrimination practiced, based  

on a majoritarian impulse of ascribed gender roles. That time is now.  

F Confronting the closet   

 

54 The right to privacy is intrinsic to liberty, central to human dignity and  

the core of autonomy. These values are integral to the right to life under  

Article 21 of the Constitution. A meaningful life is a life of freedom and self-

respect and nurtured in the ability to decide the course of living. In the nine  

judge Bench decision in Puttaswamy, this Court conceived of the right to  

privacy as natural and inalienable. The judgment delivered on behalf of four  

judges holds:    

331

PART F   

69    

“Privacy is a concomitant of the right of the individual to  

exercise control over his or her personality. It finds an origin  

in the notion that there are certain rights which are natural to  

or inherent in a human being. Natural rights are inalienable  

because they are inseparable from the human personality.  

The human element in life is impossible to conceive without  

the existence of natural rights…”118  

 

Justice Bobde, in his exposition on the form of the ‘right to privacy’ held thus:   

“Privacy, with which we are here concerned, eminently  

qualifies as an inalienable natural right, intimately connected  

to two values whose protection is a matter of universal moral  

agreement: the innate dignity and autonomy of man.”119  

 

Justice Nariman has written about the inalienable nature of the right to  

privacy:  

“…Fundamental rights, on the other hand, are contained in  

the Constitution so that there would be rights that the citizens  

of this country may enjoy despite the governments that they  

may elect. This is all the more so when a particular  

fundamental right like privacy of the individual is an  

“inalienable” right which inheres in the individual because he  

is a human being. The recognition of such right in the  

fundamental rights chapter of the Constitution is only a  

recognition that such right exists notwithstanding the shifting  

sands of majority governments…”120  

 

Justice Sapre, in his opinion, has also sanctified ‘privacy’ as a natural right:  

“In my considered opinion, “right to privacy of any individual”  

is essentially a natural right, which inheres in every human  

being by birth... It is indeed inseparable and inalienable…it is  

born with the human being…”121  

 

                                                           118 Puttaswamy, at para 42.  119 Puttaswamy, at para 392.  120 Puttaswamy, at para 490.  121 Puttaswamy  at para 557.

332

PART F   

70    

These opinions establish that the right to privacy is a natural right. The  

judgment of four judges in Puttaswamy held that the right to sexual  

orientation is an intrinsic part of the right to privacy. To define the scope of the  

right, it is useful to examine the discussion on the right to sexual orientation in  

judicial precedents of this Court.   

 

55 Speaking for a two judge Bench in NALSA, Justice K S Radhakrishnan  

elucidated upon the term ‘sexual orientation’ as differentiable from an  

individual’s ‘gender identity’, noting that:  

“Sexual orientation refers to an individual’s enduring physical,  

romantic and/or emotional attraction to another person.  

Sexual orientation includes transgender and gender-variant  

people with heavy sexual orientation and their sexual  

orientation may or may not change during or after gender  

transmission, which also includes homo-sexuals, bysexuals,  

heterosexuals, asexual etc. Gender identity and sexual  

orientation, as already indicated, are different concepts. Each  

person’s self-defined sexual orientation and gender identity is  

integral to their personality and is one of the most basic  

aspects of self-determination, dignity and freedom…”122  

 

Puttaswamy rejected the “test of popular acceptance” employed by this Court  

in Koushal and affirmed that sexual orientation is a constitutionally  

guaranteed freedom:  

“…The guarantee of constitutional rights does not depend  

upon their exercise being favourably regarded by majoritarian  

opinion. The test of popular acceptance does not furnish a  

valid basis to disregard rights which are conferred with the  

sanctity of constitutional protection. Discrete and insular  

                                                           122 NALSA, at para 22.

333

PART F   

71    

minorities face grave dangers of discrimination for the simple  

reason that their views, beliefs or way of life do not accord  

with the ‘mainstream’. Yet in a democratic Constitution  

founded on the rule of law, their rights are as sacred as those  

conferred on other citizens to protect their freedoms and  

liberties. Sexual orientation is an essential attribute of privacy.  

Discrimination against an individual on the basis of sexual  

orientation is deeply offensive to the dignity and self-worth of  

the individual. Equality demands that the sexual orientation of  

each individual in society must be protected on an even  

platform. The right to privacy and the protection of sexual  

orientation lie at the core of the fundamental rights  

guaranteed by Articles 14, 15 and 21 of the Constitution.”123  

 

Rejecting the notion that the rights of the LGBT community can be construed  

as illusory, the court held that the right to privacy claimed by sexual minorities  

is a constitutionally entrenched right:  

“…The rights of the lesbian, gay, bisexual and transgender  

population cannot be construed to be “so-called rights”. The  

expression “so-called” seems to suggest the exercise of a  

liberty in the garb of a right which is illusory. This is an  

inappropriate construction of the privacy based claims of the  

LGBT population. Their rights are not “so-called” but are real  

rights founded on sound constitutional doctrine. They inhere  

in the right to life. They dwell in privacy and dignity. They  

constitute the essence of liberty and freedom. Sexual  

orientation is an essential component of identity. Equal  

protection demands protection of the identity of every  

individual without discrimination.”124  

 

Justice Kaul, concurring with the recognition of sexual orientation as an  

aspect of privacy, noted that:  

“…The sexual orientation even within the four walls of the  

house thus became an aspect of debate. I am in agreement  

with the view of Dr. D.Y. Chandrachud, J., who in paragraphs  

144 to 146 of his judgment, states that the right of privacy  

                                                           123 Puttaswamy, at para 144.  124 Puttaswamy, at para 145.

334

PART F   

72    

cannot be denied, even if there is a miniscule fraction of the  

population which is affected. The majoritarian concept does  

not apply to Constitutional rights and the Courts are often  

called up on to take what may be categorized as a non-

majoritarian view, in the check and balance of power  

envisaged under the Constitution of India. One’s sexual  

orientation is undoubtedly an attribute of privacy…”125  

 

 

With these observations by five of the nine judges in Puttaswamy, the basis  

on which Koushal upheld the validity of Section 377 stands eroded and even  

disapproved.   

 

56 We must now consider the impact of Section 377 on the exercise of the  

right to privacy by sexual minorities. Legislation does not exist in a vacuum.  

The social ramifications of Section 377 are enormous. While facially Section  

377 only criminalizes certain “acts”, and not relationships, it alters the prism  

through which a member of the LGBTQ is viewed. Conduct and identity are  

conflated.126 The impact of criminalising non-conforming sexual relations is  

that individuals who fall outside the spectrum of heteronormative127 sexual  

identity are perceived as criminals.128   

 

57 World over, sexual minorities have struggled to find acceptance in the  

heteronormative structure that is imposed by society. In her book titled  

                                                           125 Puttaswamy, at para 647.  126 Supra note 116, at page 689.  127 The expression heteronormative is used to denote or relate to a world view that promotes heterosexuality as the  

normal or preferred sexual orientation.   128 Supra note 116, at page 689.

335

PART F   

73    

‘Epistemology of the Closet’,129 Eve Sedgwick states that “the closet is the  

defining structure for gay oppression in this century.”  The closet is symbolic  

of the exclusion faced by them:  

“Closets exist and they hide social information. They hide  

certain socially proscribed sexual desires, certain unnamable  

sexual acts deemed ‘unnatural‘ by the cultural context and  

law, certain identities which dare not speak their name and  

certain forms of behaviour which can make an individual  

susceptible to stigma and oppression. The closet does not  

simply hide this susceptibility; it hides stigma and oppression  

itself. It marks the silencing of different voices, a silence  

which is achieved by a gross violation of lives that inhabit the  

closet, through both violence and pain inflicted by significant  

others both within and without the closet and instances of  

self-inflicted pain and violence. The closet also hides  

pleasure, myriad sexual expressions and furtive encounters  

that gratify the self. The closet also conceals the possibility of  

disease and death.”130  

 

The existing heteronormative framework – which recognises only sexual  

relations that conform to social norms – is legitimized by the taint of  

‘unnaturalness’ that Section 377 lends to sexual relations outside this  

framework. The notion of ‘unnatural acts’, viewed in myopic terms of a “fixed  

procreational model of sexual functioning”, is improperly applied to sexual  

relations between consenting adults.131 Sexual activity between adults and  

based on consent must be viewed as a “natural expression” of human sexual  

competences and sensitivities.132 The refusal to accept these acts amounts to  

                                                           129 Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, Epistemology of the Closet, University of California Press (1990).  130 Supra note 65, at page 102.  131 David A. J. Richards, “Sexual Autonomy and the Constitutional Right to Privacy: A Case Study in Human Rights  

and the Unwritten Constitution”, Hastings Law Journal, Vol. 30, at page 786.   132  Ibid.

336

PART F   

74    

a denial of the distinctive human capacities for sensual experience outside of  

the realm of procreative sex.133  

 

58 To deny the members of the LGBT community the full expression of the  

right to sexual orientation is to deprive them of their entitlement to full  

citizenship under the Constitution. The denial of the right to sexual orientation  

is also a denial of the right to privacy. The application of Section 377 causes a  

deprivation of the fundamental right to privacy which inheres in every citizen.  

This Court is entrusted with the duty to act as a safeguard against such  

violations of human rights. Justice Chelameswar, in his judgement in  

Puttaswamy, held that:  

“To sanctify an argument that whatever is not found in the text  

of the Constitution cannot become a part of the Constitution  

would be too primitive an understanding of the Constitution  

and contrary to settled cannons of constitutional  

interpretation. Such an approach regarding the rights and  

liberties of citizens would be an affront to the collective  

wisdom of our people and the wisdom of the members of the  

Constituent Assembly...”134  

 

 

59 The exercise of the natural and inalienable right to privacy entails  

allowing an individual the right to a self-determined sexual orientation. Thus, it  

is imperative to widen the scope of the right to privacy to incorporate a right to  

‘sexual privacy’ to protect the rights of sexual minorities. Emanating from the  

                                                           133 Ibid.  134 Puttaswamy, at Para 350.

337

PART F   

75    

inalienable right to privacy, the right to sexual privacy must be granted the  

sanctity of a natural right, and be protected under the Constitution as  

fundamental to liberty and as a soulmate of dignity.   

 

60 Citizens of a democracy cannot be compelled to have their lives pushed  

into obscurity by an oppressive colonial legislation. In order to ensure to  

sexual and gender minorities the fulfilment of their fundamental rights, it is  

imperative to ‘confront the closet’ and, as a necessary consequence, confront  

‘compulsory heterosexuality.’135 Confronting the closet would entail  

“reclaiming markers of all desires, identities and acts which challenge it.”136 It  

would also entail ensuring that individuals belonging to sexual minorities,  

have the freedom to fully participate in public life, breaking the invisible barrier  

that heterosexuality imposes upon them. The choice of sexuality is at the core  

of privacy. But equally, our constitutional jurisprudence must recognise that  

the public assertion of identity founded in sexual orientation is crucial to the  

exercise of freedoms.   

 

61 In conceptualising a right to sexual privacy, it is important to consider  

how the delineation of ‘public’ and ‘private’ spaces affects the lives of the  

LGBTIQ community. Members of the community have argued that to base  

                                                           135 Supra note 65, at page 103.  136 Ibid.

338

PART F   

76    

their claims on a right to privacy is of no utility to individuals who do not  

possess the privilege of a private space.137 In fact, even for individuals who  

have access to private spaces the conflation of ‘private’ with home and family  

may be misplaced.138 The home is often reduced to a public space as  

heteronormativity within the family can force the individual to remain inside  

the closet.139 Thus, even the conception of a private space for certain  

individuals is utopian.140  

 

62 Privacy creates “tiers of ‘reputable’ and ‘disreputable’ sex”, only  

granting protection to acts behind closed doors.141 Thus, it is imperative that  

the protection granted for consensual acts in private must also be available in  

situations where sexual minorities are vulnerable in public spaces on account  

of their sexuality and appearance.142 If one accepts the proposition that public  

places are heteronormative, and same-sex sexual acts partially closeted,  

relegating  ‘homosexual‘ acts into the private sphere, would in effect reiterate  

the “ambient heterosexism of the public space.”143 It must be acknowledged  

that members belonging to sexual minorities are often subjected to  

                                                           137 Danish Sheikh, “Queer Rights and the Puttaswamy Judgement”, Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 52 (2017), at  

page 51.   138 Supra note 65, at page 101.  139 Ibid.  140 Ibid.  141 Supra note 137, at page 51.  142 Saptarshi Mandal, “‘Right To Privacy’ In Naz Foundation: A Counter-Heteronormative Critique”, NUJS Law  

Review, Vol. 2 (2009), at page 533.  143 Supra note 65, at page 100.

339

PART F   

77    

harassment in public spaces.144 The right to sexual privacy, founded on the  

right to autonomy of a free individual, must capture the right of persons of the  

community to navigate public places on their own terms, free from state  

interference.  

 

F.I Sexual privacy and autonomy- deconstructing the heteronormative  

framework  

 

 

63 In the absence of a protected zone of privacy, individuals are forced to  

conform to societal stereotypes. Puttaswamy has characterised the right to  

privacy as a shield against forced homogeneity and as an essential attribute  

to achieve personhood:  

“…Recognizing a zone of privacy is but an acknowledgment  

that each individual must be entitled to chart and pursue the  

course of development of personality. Hence privacy is a  

postulate of human dignity itself. Thoughts and behavioural  

patterns which are intimate to an individual are entitled to a  

zone of privacy where one is free of social expectations. In  

that zone of privacy, an individual is not judged by others.  

Privacy enables each individual to take crucial decisions  

which find expression in the human personality. It enables  

individuals to preserve their beliefs, thoughts, expressions,  

ideas, ideologies, preferences and choices against societal  

demands of homogeneity. Privacy is an intrinsic recognition of  

heterogeneity, of the right of the individual to be different and  

to stand against the tide of conformity in creating a zone of  

solitude. Privacy protects the individual from the searching  

glare of publicity in matters which are personal to his or her  

                                                           144 Supra note 137, at page 53.   

340

PART F   

78    

life. Privacy attaches to the person and not to the place where  

it is associated.”145  

 

 

This Court has recognized the right of an individual to break free from the  

demands of society and the need to foster a plural and inclusive culture. The  

judgment of four judges in Puttaswamy, for instance, held that:   

“Privacy constitutes the foundation of all liberty because it is  

in privacy that the individual can decide how liberty is best  

exercised. Individual dignity and privacy are inextricably  

linked in a pattern woven out of a thread of diversity into the  

fabric of a plural culture.”146  

 

 64 In Santosh Singh v Union of India147, a two-judge Bench of this Court  

dismissed a petition under Article 32 seeking a direction to the Central Board  

of Secondary Education to include moral science as a compulsory subject in  

the school syllabus in order to inculcate moral values. One of us  

(Chandrachud J) underscored the importance of accepting a plurality of ideas  

and tolerance of radically different views:   

“Morality is one and, however important it may sound to  

some, it still is only one element in the composition of values  

that a just society must pursue. There are other equally  

significant values which a democratic society may wish for  

education to impart to its young. Among those is the  

acceptance of a plurality and diversity of ideas, images and  

faiths which unfortunately faces global threats. Then again,  

equally important is the need to foster tolerance of those who  

hold radically differing views, empathy for those whom the  

economic and social milieu has cast away to the margins, a  

                                                           145 Puttaswamy, at para 297.  146 Puttaswamy, at para 297.  147 (2016) 8 SCC 253

341

PART F   

79    

sense of compassion and a realisation of the innate humanity  

which dwells in each human being. Value based education  

must enable our young to be aware of the horrible  

consequences of prejudice, hate and discrimination that  

continue to threaten people and societies the world over…”148  

 

 

The right to privacy enables an individual to exercise his or her autonomy,  

away from the glare of societal expectations. The realisation of the human  

personality is dependent on the autonomy of an individual. In a liberal  

democracy, recognition of the individual as an autonomous person is an  

acknowledgment of the State’s respect for the capacity of the individual to  

make independent choices. The right to privacy may be construed to signify  

that not only are certain acts no longer immoral, but that there also exists an  

affirmative moral right to do them.149  As noted by Richards, this moral right  

emerges from the autonomy to which the individual is entitled:  

“Autonomy, in the sense fundamental to the theory of human  

rights, is an empirical assumption that persons as such have  

a range of capacities that enables them to develop, and act  

upon plans of action that take as their object one's life and the  

way it is lived. The consequence of these capacities of  

autonomy is that humans can make independent decisions  

regarding what their life shall be, self-critically reflecting, as a  

separate being, which of one's first-order desires will be  

developed and which disowned, which capacities cultivated  

and which left barren, with whom one will or will not identify,  

or what one will define and pursue as needs and aspirations.  

In brief, autonomy gives to persons the capacity to call their  

life their own. The development of these capacities for  

separation and individuation is, from birth, the central  

developmental task of becoming a person.”150  

                                                           148 Ibid at para 22.  149 Supra note 131, at pages 1000-1001.  150 Supra note 131, at pages 964-965; M. Mahler, “The Psychological Birth of The Human Infant: Symbiosis And  

Individuation” (1975); L. Kaplan, Oneness And Separateness: From Infant To Individual (1978).

342

PART F   

80    

65 In Common Cause (A Registered Society) v. Union of India  

(“Common Cause”)151, a Constitution Bench of this Court held that the right  

to die with dignity is integral to the right to life recognised by the Constitution  

and an individual possessing competent mental faculties is entitled to express  

his or her autonomy by the issuance of an advance medical directive:   

“The protective mantle of privacy covers certain decisions that  

fundamentally affect the human life cycle. It protects the most  

personal and intimate decisions of individuals that affect their  

life and development. Thus, choices and decisions on matters  

such as procreation, contraception and marriage have been  

held to be protected. While death is an inevitable end in the  

trajectory of the cycle of human life individuals are often faced  

with choices and decisions relating to death. Decisions  

relating to death, like those relating to birth, sex, and  

marriage, are protected by the Constitution by virtue of the  

right of privacy…”152  

 

Autonomy and privacy are inextricably linked. Each requires the other for its  

full realization. Their interrelationship has been recognised in Puttaswamy:  

“…Privacy postulates the reservation of a private space for  

the individual, described as the right to be left alone. The  

concept is founded on the autonomy of the individual. The  

ability of an individual to make choices lies at the core of the  

human personality. The notion of privacy enables the  

individual to assert and control the human element which is  

inseparable from the personality of the individual. The  

inviolable nature of the human personality is manifested in the  

ability to make decisions on matters intimate to human life.  

The autonomy of the individual is associated over matters  

which can be kept private. These are concerns over which  

there is a legitimate expectation of privacy...”153  

 

                                                           151 (2018) 5 SCC 1  152 Ibid, at para 441.  153 Puttaswamy, at para 297.

343

PART F   

81    

In order to understand how sexual choices are an essential attribute of  

autonomy, it is useful to refer to John Rawls’ theory on social contract. Rawls’  

conception of the ‘Original Position’ serves as a constructive model to  

illustrate the notion of choice behind a “partial veil of ignorance.”154 Persons  

behind the veil are assumed to be rational and mutually disinterested  

individuals, unaware of their positions in society.155 The strategy employed by  

Rawls is to focus on a category of goods which an individual would desire  

irrespective of what individuals’ conception of ‘good’ might be.156 These  

neutrally desirable goods are described by Rawls as ‘primary social goods’  

and may be listed as rights, liberties, powers, opportunities, income, wealth,  

and the constituents of self-respect.157 Rawls's conception of self-respect, as  

a primary human good, is intimately connected to the idea of autonomy.158  

Self-respect is founded on an individual's ability to exercise her native  

capacities in a competent manner.159   

 

66 An individual’s sexuality cannot be put into boxes or  

compartmentalized; it should rather be viewed as fluid, granting the individual  

the freedom to ascertain her own desires and proclivities. The self-

                                                           154 Thomas M. Jr.  Scanlon, Rawls’ Theory of Justice, University of Pennsylvania Law Review (1973) at 1022.  155 Ibid at 1023.  156 Ibid at 1023.  157 Ibid at 1023.  158 Supra note 131, at page 971.  159 Ibid at page 972.

344

PART F   

82    

determination of sexual orientation is an exercise of autonomy. Accepting the  

role of human sexuality as an independent force in the development of  

personhood is an acknowledgement of the crucial role of sexual autonomy in  

the idea of a free individual.160 Such an interpretation of autonomy has  

implications for the widening application of human rights to sexuality.161  

Sexuality cannot be construed as something that the State has the  

prerogative to legitimize only in the form of rigid, marital procreational sex.162  

Sexuality must be construed as a fundamental experience through which  

individuals define the meaning of their lives.163 Human sexuality cannot be  

reduced to a binary formulation. Nor can it be defined narrowly in terms of its  

function as a means to procreation. To confine it to closed categories would  

result in denuding human liberty of its full content as a constitutional right. The  

Constitution protects the fluidities of sexual experience. It leaves it to  

consenting adults to find fulfilment in their relationships, in a diversity of  

cultures, among plural ways of life and in infinite shades of love and longing.     

 

F.2 A right to intimacy- celebration of sexual agency  

 67 By criminalising consensual acts between individuals who wish to  

exercise their constitutionally-protected right to sexual orientation, the State is  

                                                           160 Supra note 131, at page 1003.  161 Ibid.  162 Ibid.  163 Ibid.

345

PART F   

83    

denying its citizens the right to intimacy.  The right to intimacy emanates from  

an individual’s prerogative to engage in sexual relations on their own terms. It  

is an exercise of the individual’s sexual agency, and includes the individual’s  

right to the choice of partner as well as the freedom to decide on the nature of  

the relationship that the individual wishes to pursue.  

 

In Shakti Vahini v. Union of India164, a three judge Bench of this Court  

issued directives to prevent honour killings at the behest of Khap Panchayats  

and protect persons who enter into marriages that do not have the approval of  

the Panchayats. The Court recognised the right to choose a life partner as a  

fundamental right under Articles 19 and 21 of the Constitution. The learned  

Chief Justice held:    

“…when two adults consensually choose each other as life  

partners, it is a manifestation of their choice which is  

recognized under Articles 19 and 21 of the Constitution. Such  

a right has the sanction of the constitutional law and once that  

is recognized, the said right needs to be protected and it  

cannot succumb to the conception of class honour or group  

thinking which is conceived of on some notion that remotely  

does not have any legitimacy.”165  

 

 

In Shafin Jahan v. Asokan166, this Court set aside a Kerala High Court  

judgement which annulled the marriage of a twenty-four year old woman with  

a man of her choice in a habeas corpus petition instituted by her father. The  

                                                           164 (2018) SCC OnLine SC 275  165 Ibid, at para 44.  166 (2018) SCC OnLine SC 343

346

PART F   

84    

Court upheld her right to choose of a life partner as well as her autonomy in  

the sphere of “intimate personal decisions.” The Chief Justice held thus:  

“…expression of choice in accord with law is acceptance of  

individual identity. Curtailment of that expression and the  

ultimate action emanating therefrom on the conceptual  

structuralism of obeisance to the societal will destroy the  

individualistic entity of a person. The social values and  

morals have their space but they are not above the  

constitutionally guaranteed freedom …”167   

(Emphasis supplied)  

One of us (Chandrachud J) recognised the right to choose a partner as an  

important facet of autonomy:  

“…The choice of a partner whether within or outside  

marriage lies within the exclusive domain of each individual.  

Intimacies of marriage lie within a core zone of privacy, which  

is inviolable. The absolute right of an individual to choose a  

life partner is not in the least affected by matters of  

faith...Social approval for intimate personal decisions is not  

the basis for recognising them...”168        (Emphasis supplied)  

 

The judgement in Shafin Jahan delineates a space where an individual  

enjoys the autonomy of making intimate personal decisions:  

“The strength of the Constitution, therefore, lies in the  

guarantee which it affords that each individual will have a  

protected entitlement in determining a choice of partner to  

share intimacies within or outside marriage.”169  

 

In furtherance of the Rawlsian notion of self-respect as a primary good,  

individuals must not be denied the freedom to form relationships based on  

sexual intimacy. Consensual sexual relationships between adults, based on  

                                                           167 Ibid, at para 54.  168 Ibid, at para 88.  169 Ibid, at para 93.

347

PART F   

85    

the human propensity to experience desire must be treated with respect.  In  

addition to respect for relationships based on consent, it is important to foster  

a society where individuals find the ability for unhindered expression of the  

love that they experience towards their partner. This “institutionalized  

expression to love” must be considered an important element in the full  

actualisation of the ideal of self-respect.170 Social institutions must be  

arranged in such a manner that individuals have the freedom to enter into  

relationships untrammelled by binary of sex and gender and receive the  

requisite institutional recognition to perfect their relationships.171 The law  

provides the legitimacy for social institutions. In a democratic framework  

governed by the rule of law, the law must be consistent with the constitutional  

values of liberty, dignity and autonomy. It cannot be allowed to become a  

yoke on the full expression of the human personality. By penalising sexual  

conduct between consenting adults, Section 377 imposes moral notions  

which are anachronistic to a constitutional order. While ostensibly penalising  

‘acts’, it impacts upon the identity of the LGBT community and denies them  

the benefits of a full and equal citizenship. Section 377 is based on a  

stereotype about sex. Our Constitution which protects sexual orientation must

                                                           170 David A. J. Richards, “Unnatural Acts and the Constitutional Right to Privacy: A Moral Theory”, Fordham Law  

Review, Vol. 45 (1977), at pages 1130-1311.  171 Ibid at 1311.

348

PART G   

86    

outlaw any law which lends the authority of the state to obstructing its  

fulfilment.   

 

G Section 377 and the right to health   

“Should medicine ever fulfil its great ends, it must enter into  

the larger political and social life of our time; it must indicate  

the barriers which obstruct the normal completion of the life  

cycle and remove them.”  

- Virchow Rudolf   

 

68 In the evolution of its jurisprudence on the constitutional right to life  

under Article 21, this Court has consistently held that the right to life is  

meaningless unless accompanied by the guarantee of certain concomitant  

rights including, but not limited to, the right to health.172 The right to health is  

understood to be indispensable to a life of dignity and well-being, and  

includes, for instance, the right to emergency medical care and the right to the  

maintenance and improvement of public health.173  

 It would be useful to refer to judgments of this Court which have recognised  

the right to health.   

 

                                                           172 Dipika Jain and Kimberly Rhoten, “The Heteronormative State and the Right to Health in India”, NUJS Law  

Review, Vol. 6 (2013).  173 C.E.S.C. Limited v. Subhash Chandra Bose, (1992) 1 SCC 441; Consumer Education and Research Centre v.  

UOI, (1995) 3 SCC 42; Paschim Banga Khet Mazdoor Samity v. State of West Bengal, (1996) 4 SCC 37; Society  for Unaided Private Schools of Rajasthan v. Union of India, (2012) 6 SCC 1; Devika Biswas v. Union of India &  Ors., (2016) 10 SCC 726; Common Cause v. Union of India & Ors., (2018) 5 SCC 1.  

349

PART G   

87    

In Bandhua Mukti Morcha v. Union of India174, a three-judge Bench  

identified the right to health within the right to life and dignity. In doing so, this  

Court drew on the Directive Principles of State Policy:  

“It is the fundamental right of every one in this country … to  

live with human dignity, free from exploitation. This right to  

live with human dignity enshrined in Article 21 derives  

its life breath from the Directive Principles of State  

Policy and particularly Clauses (e) and (f) of Article 39  

and Articles 41 and 42 and at the least, therefore, it  

must include protection of the health and strength of  

workers men and women, and of the tender age of  

children against abuse, opportunities and facilities for  

children to develop in a healthy manner and in  

conditions of freedom and dignity, educational  

facilities, just and humane conditions of work and  

maternity relief. These are the minimum requirements  

which must exist in order to enable a person to live with  

human dignity and no State neither the Central Government  

nor any State Government-has the right to take any action  

which will deprive a person of the enjoyment of these basic  

essentials.”                (Emphasis supplied)  

 

In Consumer Education & Research Centre v. Union of India (“CERC”)175,  

a Bench of three judges dealt with the right to health of workers in asbestos  

industries. While laying down mandatory guidelines to be followed for the well-

being of workers, the Court held that:  

“The right to health to a worker is an integral facet of  

meaningful right to life to have not only a meaningful  

existence but also robust health and vigour without which  

worker would lead life of misery. Lack of health denudes his  

livelihood...Therefore, it must be held that the right to  

health and medical care is a fundamental right under  

                                                           174 (1984) 3 SCC 161  175 (1995) 3 SCC 42

350

PART G   

88    

Article 21 read with Articles 39(c), 41 and 43 of the  

Constitution and makes the life of the workman  

meaningful and purposeful with dignity of person. Right  

to life includes protection of the health and strength of the  

worker and is a minimum requirement to enable a person to  

live with human dignity.”          (Emphasis supplied)  

 

In a dissenting judgment in C.E.S.C. Limited v. Subhash Chandra Bose176,  

K Ramaswamy J observed that:  

“Health is thus a state of complete physical, mental and  

social well-being and not merely the absence of disease  

or infirmity. In the light of Articles. 22 to 25 of the  

Universal Declaration of Human Rights, International  

Convention on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, and  

in the light of socio-economic justice assured in our  

constitution, right to health is a fundamental human right  

to workmen. The maintenance of health is a most imperative  

constitutional goal whose realisation requires interaction by  

many social and economic factors”      (Emphasis supplied)  

 

In Kirloskar Brothers Ltd. V. Employees' State Insurance Corporation177,  

a three-judge Bench of this Court considered the applicability of the  

Employees' State Insurance Act, 1948 to the regional offices of the Appellant,  

observing that:  

“Health is thus a state of complete physical, mental and social  

well-being. Right to health, therefore, is a fundamental and  

human right to the workmen. The maintenance of health is  

the most imperative constitutional goal whose realisation  

requires interaction of many social and economic factors.”  

                                                           176 (1992) 1 SCC 441  177 (1996) 2 SCC 682

351

PART G   

89    

In State of Punjab v. Ram Lubhaya Bagga178, a three-judge Bench of this  

Court considered a challenge to the State of Punjab’s medical reimbursement  

policy. A.P. Mishra J, speaking for the Bench, observed that:   

“Pith and substance of life is the health, which is the nucleus  

of all activities of life including that of an employee or other  

viz. the physical, social, spiritual or any conceivable human  

activities. If this is denied, it is said everything crumbles.  

This Court has time and again emphasised to the  

Government and other authorities for focussing and giving  

priority and other authorities for focussing and giving priority  

to the health of its, citizen, which not only makes one's life  

meaningful, improves one's efficiency, but in turn gives  

optimum out put.”  

 

In Smt M Vijaya v. The Chairman and Managing Director Singareni  

Collieries Co. Ltd.179, a five judge Bench of the Andhra Pradesh High Court  

considered a case where a girl was infected with HIV due to the negligence of  

hospital authorities. The Court observed that:   

“Article 21 of the Constitution of India provides that no person  

shall be deprived of his life or personal liberty except  

according to procedure established by law. By reason of  

numerous judgments of the Apex Court the horizons of Article  

21 of the Constitution have been expanded recognising  

various rights of the citizens i.e...right to health...  

It is well settled that right to life guaranteed under Article 21 is  

not mere animal existence. It is a right to enjoy all faculties of  

life. As a necessary corollary, right to life includes right to  

healthy life.”  

 

                                                           178 (1998) 4 SCC 117  179 (2001) 5 ALD 522

352

PART G   

90    

In Devika Biswas v. Union of India180, while hearing a public interest petition  

concerning several deaths that had taken place due to unsanitary conditions  

in sterilization camps across the country, a two judge Bench of this Court held  

that:   

“It is well established that the right to life under Article 21 of  

the Constitution includes the right to lead a dignified and  

meaningful life and the right to health is an integral facet of  

this right...That the right to health is an integral part of the  

right to life does not need any repetition.”  

 

In his concurring judgment in Common Cause v. Union of India, Sikri J,  

noted the inextricable link between the right to health and dignity:   

“There is a related, but interesting, aspect of this dignity which  

needs to be emphasised. Right to health is a part of Article  

21 of the Constitution. At the same time, it is also a harsh  

reality that everybody is not able to enjoy that right because  

of poverty etc. The State is not in a position to translate into  

reality this right to health for all citizens. Thus, when citizens  

are not guaranteed the right to health, can they be denied  

right to die in dignity?”     (Emphasis supplied)  

 

In addition to the constitutional recognition granted to the right to health, the  

right to health is also recognised in international treaties, covenants, and  

agreements which India has ratified, including the International Covenant on  

Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, 1966 (“ICESCR”) and the Universal  

                                                           180 (2016) 10 SCC 726

353

PART G   

91    

Declaration of Human Rights, 1948 (“UDHR”). Article 25 of the UDHR  

recognizes the right to health:  

"Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for  

the health and well-being of himself and of his family,  

including food, clothing, housing and medical care and  

necessary social services."  

 

69 Article 12 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and  

Cultural Rights (“ICESCR”) recognizes the right of all persons to the  

enjoyment of the highest attainable standard of physical and mental health:  

“The States Parties to the present Covenant recognize the  

right of everyone to the enjoyment of the highest attainable  

standard of physical and mental health.”  

 

Article 12.2 requires States Parties to take specific steps to improve the health  

of their citizens, including creating conditions to ensure equal and timely  

access to medical services. In its General Comment No. 14,181 the UN  

Economic and Social Council stated that States must take measures to  

respect, protect and fulfil the health of all persons. States are obliged to  

ensure the availability and accessibility of health-related information,  

education, facilities, goods and services, without discrimination, especially for  

vulnerable and marginalized populations.  

 

                                                           181 UN Economic and Social Council (ECOSOC), Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, General  

Comment No. 14: The Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of Health, UN Doc. E/C.12/2004 (2000).

354

PART G   

92    

Pursuant to General Comment No. 14, India is required to provide  

marginalized populations, including members of the LGBTIQ community,  

goods and services that are available (in sufficient quantity), accessible  

(physically, geographically, economically and in a non-discriminatory manner),  

acceptable (respectful of culture and medical ethics) and of quality  

(scientifically and medically appropriate and of good quality).  

 

70 As early as 1948, the World Health Organization (“WHO”) defined the  

term ‘health’ broadly to mean “a state of complete physical, mental and social  

well-being and not merely the absence of disease or infirmity.”182 Even today,  

for a significant number of Indian citizens this standard of health remains an  

elusive aspiration. Of relevance to the present case, a particular class of  

citizens is denied the benefits of this constitutional enunciation of the right to  

health because of their most intimate sexual choices.  

   71 Sexuality is a natural and precious aspect of life, an essential and  

fundamental part of our humanity.183 Sexual rights are entitlements related to  

sexuality and emanate from the rights to freedom, equality, privacy,  

autonomy, and dignity of all people.184 For people to attain the highest  

                                                           182Definition contained in the Preamble to the WHO Constitution (1948).  183 Sexual Rights, International Planned Parenthood Federation (2008).   184 Ibid.

355

PART G   

93    

standard of health, they must also have the right to exercise choice in their  

sexual lives and feel safe in expressing their sexual identity. However, for  

some citizens, discrimination, stigma, fear and violence prevent them from  

attaining basic sexual rights and health.  

 

72 Individuals belonging to sexual and gender minorities experience  

discrimination, stigmatization, and, in some cases, denial of care on account  

of their sexual orientation and gender identity.185 However, it is important to  

note that ‘sexual and gender minorities’ do not constitute a homogenous  

group, and experiences of social exclusion, marginalization, and  

discrimination, as well as specific health needs, vary considerably.186  

Nevertheless, these individuals are united by one factor - that their exclusion,  

discrimination and marginalization is rooted in societal heteronormativity and  

society’s pervasive bias towards gender binary and opposite-gender  

relationships, which marginalizes and excludes all non-heteronormative  

sexual and gender identities.187 This, in turn, has important implications for  

individuals’ health-seeking behaviour, how health services are provided, and  

the extent to which sexual health can be achieved.188  

                                                           185 Alexandra Muller, “Health for All? Sexual Orientation, Gender Identity, and the Implementation of the Right to  

Access to Health Care in South Africa”, Health and Human Rights (2016) at pages 195–208.   186 Institute of Medicine, “The Health of Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, and Transgender People: Building a Foundation for  

Better Understanding”, National Academies Press (2011).  187 Supra note 185, at pages 195–208.  188 Ibid.

356

PART G   

94    

73 The term ‘sexual health’ was first defined in a 1975 WHO Technical  

Report series as “the integration of the somatic, emotional, intellectual and  

social aspects of sexual being, in ways that are positively enriching and that  

enhance personality, communication and love.”189 The WHO’s current working  

definition of sexual health is as follows:  

“…a state of physical, emotional, mental and social well-being  

in relation to sexuality; it is not merely the absence of  

disease, dysfunction or infirmity. Sexual health requires a  

positive and respectful approach to sexuality and sexual  

relationships, as well as the possibility of having pleasurable  

and safe sexual experiences, free of coercion, discrimination  

and violence. For sexual health to be attained and  

maintained, the sexual rights of all persons must be  

respected, protected and fulfilled.”  

 

 

The WHO further states that “sexual health cannot be defined, understood or  

made operational without a broad consideration of sexuality, which underlies  

important behaviours and outcomes related to sexual health.” It defines  

sexuality thus:  

 

“…a central aspect of being human throughout life  

encompasses sex, gender identities and roles, sexual  

orientation, eroticism, pleasure, intimacy and reproduction.  

Sexuality is experienced and expressed in thoughts,  

fantasies, desires, beliefs, attitudes, values, behaviours,  

practices, roles and relationships. While sexuality can include  

all of these dimensions, not all of them are always  

experienced or expressed. Sexuality is influenced by the  

interaction of biological, psychological, social, economic,  

political, cultural, legal, historical, religious and spiritual  

factors.”  

 

                                                           189 World Health Organization, “Gender and human rights: Defining sexual health”, (2002).

357

PART G   

95    

74 A report entitled “Sexual Health, Human Rights and the Law”,190  

published by the WHO in 2015 explores the relationship between these  

concepts. The report notes that “human sexuality includes many different  

forms of behaviour and expression, and that the recognition of the diversity of  

sexual behaviour and expression contributes to people’s overall sense of  

health and well-being.”191 It emphasizes the importance of sexual health by  

stating that not only is it essential to the physical and emotional well-being of  

individuals, couples and families, but it is also fundamental to the social and  

economic development of communities and countries.192 The ability of  

individuals to progress towards sexual health and well-being depends on  

various factors, including “access to comprehensive information about  

sexuality, knowledge about the risks they face and their vulnerability to the  

adverse consequences of sexual activity; access to good quality sexual health  

care, and an environment that affirms and promotes sexual health.”  

  

75 The International Women’s Health Coalition has located the right to  

sexual health within ‘sexual rights’, defined as follows:193   

“Sexual rights embrace certain human rights that are already  

recognized in national laws, international human rights  

documents, and other consensus documents. They rest on  

the recognition that all individuals have the right—free of  

                                                           190 World Health Organisation, “Sexual Health, Human Rights and the Law” (2015).   191 Ibid.  192 Ibid.  193 International Women’s Health Coalition, “Sexual Rights are Human Rights” (2014).

358

PART G   

96    

coercion, violence, and discrimination of any kind—to the  

highest attainable standard of sexual health; to pursue a  

satisfying, safe, and pleasurable sexual life; to have control  

over and decide freely, and with due regard for the rights of  

others, on matters related to their sexuality, reproduction,  

sexual orientation, bodily integrity, choice of partner, and  

gender identity; and to the services, education, and  

information, including comprehensive sexuality education,  

necessary to do so.”  

 

The discussion of ‘sexual rights’ (as they pertain to sexuality and sexual  

orientation) within the framework of the right to health is a relatively new  

phenomenon:194  

“..Before the 1993 World Conference on Human Rights in  

Vienna, and the subsequent 1994 International Conference  

on Population and Development in Cairo, sexuality, sexual  

rights, and sexual diversity had not formed part of the  

international health and human rights discourse. These  

newly emerged “sexual rights” were founded on the  

principles of bodily integrity, personhood, equality, and  

diversity.”195          (Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

76 The operation of Section 377 denies consenting adults the full  

realization of their right to health, as well as their sexual rights. It forces  

consensual sex between adults into a realm of fear and shame, as persons  

who engage in anal and oral intercourse risk criminal sanctions if they seek  

health advice. This lowers the standard of health enjoyed by them and  

particularly by members of sexual and gender minorities, in relation to the rest  

of society.   

                                                           194 Supra note 185, at pages 195–208.  195 Supra note 185, at pages 195–208.

359

PART G   

97    

77 The right to health is not simply the right not to be unwell, but rather the  

right to be well. It encompasses not just the absence of disease or infirmity,  

but “complete physical, mental and social well being”,196 and includes both  

freedoms such as the right to control one’s health and body and to be free  

from interference (for instance, from non-consensual medical treatment and  

experimentation), and entitlements such as the right to a system of healthcare  

that gives everyone an equal opportunity to enjoy the highest attainable level  

of health.   

 

78 The jurisprudence of this Court, in recognizing the right to health and  

access to medical care, demonstrates the crucial distinction between negative  

and positive obligations. Article 21 does not impose upon the State only  

negative obligations not to act in such a way as to interfere with the right to  

health. This Court also has the power to impose positive obligations upon the  

State to take measures to provide adequate resources or access to treatment  

facilities to secure effective enjoyment of the right to health.197  

 

79 A study of sexuality and its relationship to the right to health in South  

Africa points to several other studies that suggest a negative correlation  

between sexual orientation-based discrimination and the right to health:                                                              196 Preamble to the Constitution of the World Health Organisation.  197 Jayna Kothari, “Social Rights and the Indian Constitution”, Law, Social Justice and Global Development Journal  

(2004).

360

PART G   

98    

“For example, in a Canadian study, Brotman and colleagues  

found that being open about their sexual orientation in health  

care settings contributed to experiences of discrimination for  

lesbian, gay, and bisexual people.”198   

  

“Lane and colleagues interviewed men who have sex with  

men in Soweto, and revealed that all men who disclosed their  

sexual orientation at public health facilities had experienced  

some form of discrimination. Such discrimination [‘ranging  

from verbal abuse to denial of care’199], and also the  

anticipation thereof, leads to delays when seeking sexual  

health services such as HIV counseling and testing.”200   

 

80 Alexandra Muller describes the story of two individuals who experienced  

such discrimination. T, a gay man, broke both his arms while fleeing from a  

group of people that attacked him because of his sexuality. At the hospital, the  

staff learned about T’s sexual orientation, and pejoratively discussed it in his  

presence. He also had to endure “a local prayer group that visited the ward  

daily to provide spiritual support to patients” which “prayed at his bedside to  

rectify his “devious” sexuality. When he requested that they leave, or that he  

be transferred to another ward, the nurses did not intervene, and the prayer  

group visited regularly to continue to recite their homophobic prayers. T did  

not file an official complaint, fearing future ramifications in accessing care.  

Following his discharge, he decided not to return for follow up appointments  

and had his casts removed at another facility.201   

 

                                                           198 Supra note 185, at pages 195–208.  199 Ibid.  200 Ibid.  201 Ibid.  

361

PART G   

99    

Another woman, P, who had been with her female partner for three years,  

wanted to get tested for HIV. The nurse at the hospital asked certain  

questions to discern potential risk behaviours. When asked why she did not  

use condoms or contraception, P revealed that she did not need to on account  

of her sexuality. The nurse immediately exclaimed that P was not at risk for  

HIV, and that she should “go home and not waste her time any longer.” P has  

not attempted to have another HIV test since.202  

 

These examples are illustrative of a wider issue: individuals across the world  

are denied access to equal healthcare on the basis of their sexual orientation.  

That people are intimidated or blatantly denied healthcare access on a  

discriminatory basis around the world proves that this issue is not simply an  

ideological tussle playing out in classrooms and courtrooms, but an issue  

detrimentally affecting individuals on the ground level and violating their rights  

including the right to health.  

 

81 The right to health is one of the major rights at stake in the struggle for  

equality amongst gender and sexual minorities:203   

“The right to physical and mental health is at conflict with  

discriminatory policies and practices, some physicians'  

homophobia, the lack of adequate training for health care  

                                                           202 Ibid.  203 Study Guide: Sexual Orientation and Human Rights, University of Minnesota Human RIghts Library (2003).

362

PART G   

100    

personnel regarding sexual orientation issues or the general  

assumption that patients are heterosexuals.”204  

 

While the enumeration of the right to equal healthcare is crucial, an  

individual’s sexual health is also equally significant to holistic well-being. A  

healthy sex life is integral to an individual’s physical and mental health,  

regardless of whom an individual is attracted to. Criminalising certain sexual  

acts, thereby shunning them from the mainstream discourse, would invariably  

lead to situations of unsafe sex, coercion, and a lack of sound medical advice  

and sexual education, if any at all.   

 

82 A report by the Francois-Xavier Bagnoud Center for Health and Human  

Rights at Harvard School of Public Health defines the term ‘sexual health’ as  

follows:   

“A state of physical, emotional, mental, and social well-being  

in relation to sexuality. Like health generally, it is not merely  

the absence of disease, but encompasses positive and  

complex experiences of sexuality as well as freedom to  

determine sexual relationships, as well as the possibility of  

having pleasurable sexual experiences, free of coercion,  

discrimination and violence.”205  

 

83 Laws that criminalize same-sex intercourse create social barriers to  

accessing healthcare, and curb the effective prevention and treatment of  

                                                           204 Ibid.  205 Center for Health and Human Rights and Open Society Foundations. “Health and Human Rights Resource Guide   

(2013).  

363

PART G   

101    

HIV/AIDS.206 Criminal laws are the strongest expression of the State’s power  

to punish certain acts and behaviour, and it is therefore incumbent upon the  

State to ensure full protection for all persons, including the specific needs of  

sexual minorities. The equal protection of law mandates the state to fulfill this  

constitutional obligation. Indeed, the state is duty bound to revisit its laws and  

executive decisions to ensure that they do not deny equality before the law  

and the equal protection of laws. That the law must not discriminate is one  

aspect of equality. But there is more. The law must take affirmative steps to  

achieve equal protection of law to all its citizens, irrespective of sexual  

orientation.       

 

In regard to sexuality and health, it is important to distinguish between  

behaviour that is harmful to others, such as rape and coerced sex, and that  

which is not, such as consensual same-sex conduct between adults, conduct  

related to gender-expression such as cross-dressing, as well as seeking or  

providing sexual and reproductive health information and services. The use of  

criminal laws in relation to an expanding range of otherwise consensual  

sexual conduct has been found to be discriminatory by international and  

                                                           206 Supra note 172.  

364

PART G   

102    

domestic courts, often together with violations of other human rights, such as  

the rights to privacy, self-determination, human dignity and health.207  

   

G.I Section 377 and HIV prevention efforts  

 

84 Section 377 has a significant detrimental impact on the right to health of  

those persons who are susceptible to contracting HIV – men who have sex  

with men (“MSM”)208 and transgender persons.209 The Global Commission on  

HIV and the Law has noted the impact of Section 377 on the right of health of  

persons afflicted with or vulnerable to contracting HIV:   

“The law and its institutions can protect the dignity of all  

people living with HIV, and in so doing fortify those most  

vulnerable to HIV, so-called “key populations”, such  as  sex  

workers, MSM, transgender people, prisoners and migrants.  

The law can open the doors to justice when these people’s  

rights are trampled…. But the law can also do grave harm to  

the bodies and spirits of people living with HIV. It can  

perpetuate discrimination and isolate the people most  

vulnerable to HIV from the programmes that would help them  

to avoid or cope with the virus. By dividing people into  

criminals and victims or sinful and innocent, the legal  

environment can destroy the social, political, and economic  

                                                           207 Eszter Kismodi, Jane Cottingham, Sofia Gruskin & Alice M. Miller, “Advancing sexual health through human  

rights: The role of the law”, Taylor and Francis, (2015), at pages 252-267.  208 The term “men who have sex with men” (MSM) denotes all men who have sex with men, regardless of their  

sexual identity, sexual orientation and whether or not they also have sex with females. MSM is an epidemiological  term which focuses on sexual behaviours for the purpose of HIV and STI surveillance. The assumption is that  behaviour, not sexual identity, places people at risk for HIV. See Regional Office for South-East Asia, World  Health Organization, “HIV/AIDS among men who have sex with men and transgender populations in South-East  Asia: the current situation and national responses” (2010).  

209 Transgender people continue to be included under the umbrella term “MSM”. However, it has increasingly been  recognized that Transgender people have unique needs and concerns, and it would be more useful to view them  as a separate group. See Regional Office for South-East Asia, World Health Organization, “HIV/AIDS among men  who have sex with men and transgender populations in South-East Asia: the current situation and national  responses” (2010).

365

PART G   

103    

solidarity that is necessary to overcome this global  

epidemic.”210   

 

 

85 Mr Anand Grover, learned Senior Counsel in his submissions,  

highlighted the vulnerability of MSM and transgender persons. According to a  

study published by the Global Commission on HIV and the Law, MSM were  

found to be 19 times more susceptible to be infected with HIV than other adult  

men.211  

 

86 The UN Human Rights Committee has recognized the impact of the  

criminalization of homosexuality on the spread of HIV/AIDS. In Toonen v  

Australia212, a homosexual man from Tasmania, where homosexual sex was  

criminalized, argued that criminalization of same-sex activities between  

consenting adults was an infringement of his right to privacy under Article 17  

of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (“ICCPR”). The  

Committee rejected the argument of the Tasmanian authorities that the law  

was justified on grounds of public health and morality as it was enacted to  

prevent the spread of HIV/AIDS in Tasmania. The Committee observed that:   

“... the criminalization of homosexual practices cannot be  

considered a reasonable means or proportionate measure to  

achieve the aim of preventing the spread of AIDS/HIV …  

                                                           210 United Nations Development Programme, “Global Commission on HIV and the Law: Risks, Rights and Health”  

(2012), at pages 11-12.  211 Ibid at page 45; HIV prevalence amongst MSM is 4.3% and amongst transgender persons it is 7.5% as opposed  

to the overall adult HIV prevalence of 0.26%.  212 Communication No. 488/1992, U.N. Doc CCPR/C/50/D/488/1992 (1994), decision dated 31/03/1994.

366

PART G   

104    

Criminalization of homosexual activity thus would appear to  

run counter to the implementation of effective education  

programmes in respect of the HIV/AIDS prevention.  

Secondly, the Committee notes that no link has been shown  

between the continued criminalization of homosexual activity  

and the effective control of the spread of the HIV/AIDS virus.”  

 

 

In response to the Committee’s decision, a law was enacted to overcome the  

Tasmanian law criminalizing homosexual sex.  

 

87 Section 377 has had far-reaching consequences for this “key  

population”, pushing them out of the public health system. MSM and  

transgender persons may not approach State health care providers for fear of  

being prosecuted for engaging in criminalized intercourse. Studies show that  

it is the stigma attached to these individuals that contributes to increased  

sexual risk behaviour and/or decreased use of HIV prevention services.213   

 

88 The silence and secrecy that accompanies institutional discrimination  

may foster conditions which encourage escalation of the incidence of  

HIV/AIDS.214 The key population is stigmatized by health providers,  

employers and other service providers.215 As a result, there exist serious  

obstacles to effective HIV prevention and treatment as discrimination and  

                                                           213 Beena Thomas, Matthew J. Mimiaga, Senthil Kumar, Soumya Swaminathan, Steven A. Safren, and Kenneth H.  

Mayer, “HIV in Indian MSM: Reasons for a concentrated epidemic & strategies for prevention”, Indian Journal  Medical Research (2011), at pages 920–929.  

214 Ibid.  215 Ibid.

367

PART G   

105    

harassment can hinder access to HIV and sexual health services and  

prevention programmes.216  

    

89 An incisive article, based on extensive empirical research carried out in  

various countries, has concluded that there is a demonstrable relationship  

between “laws which criminalize same-sex conduct and adverse health  

effects on HIV-AIDs rates as well as other health indicators for the MSM  

community” due to poor access to key HIV prevention tools and outreach  

programmes.217  According to a report published by the Joint United Nations  

Programme on HIV/AIDS (“UNAIDS”), in Caribbean countries where same-

sex relations are criminalised, almost one in four MSMs is infected with  

HIV.218 In the absence of such criminal provisions, the prevalence of HIV is  

one in fifteen among MSMs.219   

 

90 Closer to home, the UNAIDS project found that in the four years  

following the judgement in Naz, there had been an increase of more than 50%  

in the number of healthcare centers providing HIV services to MSM and  

transgender persons in India.220 If same-sex relations remain criminalised, it is  

                                                           216 Ibid.  217 Supra note 172, at page 636.  218 Supra note 210, at page 45.  219 Ibid.  220 UNAIDS, “UNAIDS Calls on India and All Countries to Repeal Laws That Criminalize Adult Consensual Same Sex  

Sexual Conduct” (2013).  

368

PART G   

106    

likely that HIV interventions for MSMs will continue to be inadequate, MSMs  

will continue to be marginalised from health services, and the prevalence of  

HIV will exacerbate.221   

   

91 To safeguard the health of persons who are at the greatest risk of HIV  

infection, it is imperative that access is granted to effective HIV prevention  

and treatment services and commodities such as clean needles, syringes,  

condoms and lubricants.222 A needle or a condom can only be considered a  

concrete representation of the entitlements of vulnerable groups: the  

fundamental human rights of dignity, autonomy and freedom from ill-  

treatment, along with the right to the highest attainable standard of physical  

and mental health, without regard to sexuality or legal status.223 This is the  

mandate of the Directive Principles contained in Part IV of the Constitution.   

 

92 In 2017, Parliament enacted the HIV (Prevention and Control) Act, to  

provide for the prevention and control of the spread of HIV/AIDS and for the  

protection of the human rights of persons affected. Parliament recognized the  

importance of prevention interventions for vulnerable groups including MSMs.  

Section 22 of this Act provides for protection against criminal sanctions as  

well as any civil liability arising out of promoting actions or practices or “any                                                              221 UNAIDS, “Judging the Epidemic: A Judicial Handbook on HIV, Human Rights and the Law” (2013) at page 165.  222 Supra note 210, at page 26.  223 Ibid, at page 26.

369

PART G   

107    

strategy or mechanism or technique” undertaken for reducing the risk of HIV  

transmission. Illustrations (a) and (b) to Section 22 read as follows:  

“(a) A supplies condoms to B who is a sex worker or to C,  

who is a client of B. Neither A nor B nor C can be held  

criminally or civilly liable for such actions or be prohibited,  

impeded, restricted or prevented from implementing or using  

the strategy.   

(b) M carries on an intervention project on HIV or AIDS and  

sexual health information, education and counselling for men,  

who have sex with men, provides safer sex information,  

material and condoms to N, who has sex with other men.  

Neither M nor N can be held criminally or civilly liable for such  

actions or be prohibited, impeded, restricted or prevented  

from implementing or using the intervention.”  

     

Persons who engage in anal or oral intercourse face significant sexual health  

risks due to the operation of Section 377. Prevalence rates of HIV are high,  

particularly among men who have sex with men. Discrimination, stigma and a  

lack of knowledge on the part of many healthcare providers means that these  

individuals often cannot and do not access the health care they need. In order  

to promote sexual health and reduce HIV transmission among LGBT  

individuals, it is imperative that the availability, effectiveness, and quality of  

health services to the LGBT community be significantly improved.  

 

Under our constitutional scheme, no minority group must suffer deprivation of  

a constitutional right because they do not adhere to the majoritarian way of  

life. By the application of Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code, MSM and  

transgender persons are excluded from access to healthcare due to the

370

PART G   

108    

societal stigma attached to their sexual identity. Being particularly vulnerable  

to contraction of HIV, this deprivation can only be described as cruel and  

debilitating. The indignity suffered by the sexual minority cannot, by any  

means, stand the test of constitutional validity.  

 

G.2 Mental health  

 93 The treatment of homosexuality as a disorder has serious  

consequences on the mental health and well-being of LGBT persons. The  

mental health of citizens “growing up in a culture that devalues and silences  

same-sex desire” is severely impacted.224 Global psychiatric expert Dinesh  

Bhugra has emphasised that radical solutions are needed to combat the high  

levels of mental illness among the LGBT population stating there is a “clear  

correlation between political and social environments” and how persecutory  

laws against LGBT individuals are leading to greater levels of depression,  

anxiety, self-harm, and suicide. Even in Britain, gay people are at greater risk  

of a range of mental health problems, and, it is believed, are more likely to  

take their own lives.  

“A number of studies this year have highlighted the  

disproportionate levels of mental illness among LGBT people.  

In Britain, one of the world's most legally equal countries for  

this community, research in the last few months has revealed  

that LGBT people are nearly twice as likely to have  

                                                           224 Ketki Ranade, “Process of Sexual Identity Development for Young People with Same Sex Desires: Experiences  

of Exclusion”, Psychological Foundations - The Journal (2008).

371

PART G   

109    

attempted suicide or harmed themselves, gay men are more  

than twice as likely to have a mental illness than  

heterosexual men, and 4 in 5 transgender people have  

suffered depression in the last five years.”225      

(Emphasis supplied)  

 

 

He discusses studies from various countries which indicate that in countries  

where laws continue to discriminate against LGBT individuals, there are high  

rates of mental illness. Similarly he states that there have been a series of  

studies showing that in America, rates of psychiatric disorders have dropped  

when state policies have recognised the equal rights of LGBT individuals.  

  

94 Mr Chander Uday Singh, learned Senior Counsel appearing on behalf of  

an intervenor, a psychiatrist, has brought to our notice how even the mental  

health sector has often reflected the societal prejudice regarding  

homosexuality as a pathological condition.   

 

95 Medical and scientific authority has now established that consensual  

same sex conduct is not against the order of nature and that homosexuality is  

natural and a normal variant of sexuality. Parliament has provided legislative  

acknowledgment of this global consensus through the enactment of the  

Mental Healthcare Act, 2017. Section 3 of the Act mandates that mental  

illness is to be determined in accordance with ‘nationally’ or ‘internationally’  

                                                           225 Dinesh Bhugra, globally renowned psychiatrist (article annexed in compilation provided by Mr. Chander Uday  

Singh, learned Senior Counsel).

372

PART G   

110    

accepted medical standards. The International Classification of Diseases  

(ICD-10) by the World Health Organisation is listed as an internationally  

accepted medical standard and does not consider non-peno-vaginal sex  

between consenting adults either a mental disorder or an illness. The Act  

through Section 18(2)226 and Section 21227 provides for protection against  

discrimination on the grounds of sexual orientation.  

 

The repercussions of prejudice, stigma and discrimination continue to impact  

the psychological well-being of individuals impacted by Section 377. Mental  

health professionals can take this change in the law as an opportunity to re-

examine their own views of homosexuality.  

 

96 Counselling practices will have to focus on providing support to  

homosexual clients to become comfortable with who they are and get on with  

their lives, rather than motivating them for change. Instead of trying to cure  

something that isn’t even a disease or illness, the counsellors have to adopt a  

more progressive view that reflects the changed medical position and

                                                           226 Section 18. Right to access mental healthcare.—(1) Every person shall have a right to access mental  

healthcare and treatment from mental health services run or funded by the appropriate Government. (2) The right  to access mental healthcare and treatment shall mean mental health services of affordable cost, of good quality,  available in sufficient quantity, accessible geographically, without discrimination on the basis of gender, sex,  sexual orientation, religion, culture, caste, social or political beliefs, class, disability or any other basis and  provided in a manner that is acceptable to persons with mental illness and their families and care-givers.  

227 Section 21. Right to equality and non-discrimination.—(1) Every person with mental illness shall be treated as  equal to persons with physical illness in the provision of all healthcare which shall include the following, namely:—  (a) there shall be no discrimination on any basis including gender, sex, sexual orientation, religion, culture, caste,  social or political beliefs, class or disability.

373

PART H   

111    

changing societal values. There is not only a need for special skills of  

counsellors but also heightened sensitivity and understanding of LGBT lives.  

The medical practice must share the responsibility to help individuals, families,  

workplaces and educational and other institutions to understand sexuality  

completely in order to facilitate the creation of a society free from  

discrimination228 where LGBT individuals like all other citizens are treated with  

equal standards of respect and value for human rights.  

 

H Judicial review  

 

97 The Constitution entrusts the function of making laws to Parliament and  

the State Legislatures under Articles 245 and 246 of the Constitution.   

Parliament and the State Legislatures are empowered to create offences  

against laws with respect to the heads of legislation, falling within the purview  

of their legislative authority. (See Entry 93 of List I and Entry 64 of List II of the  

Seventh Schedule).  Criminal law is a subject which falls within the Concurrent  

List.  Entry I of List III provides thus:  

“1. Criminal law, including all matters included in the Indian  

Penal Code at the commencement of this Constitution but  

excluding offences against laws with respect to any of the  

matters specified in List I or List II and excluding the use of  

naval, military or air forces or any other armed forces of the  

Union in aid of the civil power.”  

 

                                                           228 Vinay Chandran, “From judgement to practice: Section 377 and the medical sector”, Indian Journal of Medical  

Ethics, Vol. 4 (2009).

374

PART H   

112    

The power to enact legislation in the field of criminal law has been entrusted  

to Parliament and, subject to its authority, to the State Legislatures.  Both  

Parliament and the State Legislatures can enact laws providing for offences  

arising out of legislation falling within their legislative domains.  The authority  

to enact law, however, is subject to the validity of the law being scrutinised on  

the touchstone of constitutional safeguards.  A citizen, or, as in the present  

case, a community of citizens, having addressed a challenge to the validity of  

a law which creates an offence, the authority to determine that question is  

entrusted to the judicial branch in the exercise of the power of judicial review.   

The Court will not, as it does not, in the exercise of judicial review, second  

guess a value judgment made by the legislature on the need for or the  

efficacy of legislation. But where a law creating an offence is found to be  

offensive to fundamental rights, such a law is not immune to challenge.  The  

constitutional authority which is entrusted to the legislatures to create offences  

is subject to the mandate of a written Constitution. Where the validity of the  

law is called into question, judicial review will extend to scrutinising whether  

the law is manifestly arbitrary in its encroachment on fundamental liberties.  If  

a law discriminates against a group or a community of citizens by denying  

them full and equal participation as citizens, in the rights and liberties granted  

by the Constitution, it would be for the Court to adjudicate upon validity of  

such a law.

375

PART I   

113    

I India’s commitments at International Law  

 

98 International human rights treaties and jurisprudence impose obligations  

upon States to protect all individuals from violations of their human rights,  

including on the basis of their sexual orientation.229 Nevertheless, laws  

criminalizing same-sex relations between consenting adults remain on the  

statute books in more than seventy countries. Many of them, including so-

called “sodomy laws”, are vestiges of colonial-era legislation that prohibits  

either certain types of sexual activity or any intimacy or sexual activity  

between persons of the same sex.230 In some cases, the language used  

refers to vague and indeterminate concepts, such as ‘crimes against the order  

of nature’,  ‘morality’, or ‘debauchery’.231 There is a familiar ring to it in India,  

both in terms of history and text.  

 

99 International law today has evolved towards establishing that the  

criminalization of consensual sexual acts between same-sex adults in private  

contravenes the rights to equality, privacy, and freedom from discrimination.  

These rights are recognised in international treaties, covenants, and  

                                                           229 Dominic McGoldrick, “The Development and Status of Sexual Orientation Discrimination under International  

Human Rights Law”, Human Rights Law Review, Vol. 16 (2016).  230 UN Human Rights Council, “Discriminatory laws and practices and acts of violence against individuals based on  

their sexual orientation and gender identity” (2011).  231 UN Human Rights Council, “Promotion and Protection of all Human Rights, Civil, Political, Economic, Social and  

Cultural Rights, including the Right to Development” (2008).

376

PART I   

114    

agreements which India has ratified, including the UDHR, ICCPR, and the  

ICESCR. India has a constitutional duty to honour these internationally  

recognized rules and principles.232 Article 51 of the Constitution, which forms  

part of the Directive Principles of State Policy, requires the State to endeavour  

to “foster respect for international law and treaty obligations in the dealings of  

organised peoples with one another.”  

 

100 The human rights treaties that India has ratified require States Parties to  

guarantee the rights to equality before the law, equal protection of the law and  

freedom from discrimination. For example, Article 2 of the ICESCR requires  

states to ensure that:  

“The rights enunciated in the present Covenant will be  

exercised without discrimination of any kind as to race,  

colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion,  

national or social origin, property, birth or other status.”  

 

101 The Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights - the body  

mandated by the ICESCR to monitor States Parties’ implementation of the  

treaty – has stated that “other status” in article 2 (2) includes sexual  

orientation, and reaffirmed that “gender identity is recognized as among the  

                                                           232 Vishaka v State of Rajasthan, (1997) 6 SCC 241.

377

PART I   

115    

prohibited grounds of discrimination”, as “persons who are transgender,  

transsexual or intersex often face serious human rights violations.”233  

 

102 The prohibition against discrimination in the ICCPR is contained in  

Article 26, which guarantees equality before the law:  

“All persons are equal before the law and are entitled without  

any discrimination to the equal protection of the law. In this  

respect, the law shall prohibit any discrimination and  

guarantee to all persons equal and effective protection  

against discrimination on any ground such as race, colour,  

sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or  

social origin, property, birth or other status.”  

 

India is also required to protect the right to privacy, which includes within its  

ambit the right to engage in consensual same-sex sexual relations.234 Article  

12 of the UDHR recognises the right to privacy:   

“Article 12: No one shall be subjected to arbitrary interference  

with his privacy, family, home or correspondence, nor to  

attacks upon his honour and reputation. Everyone has the  

right to the protection of the law against such interference or  

attacks.”   

 

 

                                                           233 Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, “General Comment 20: Non-discrimination in economic,  

social and cultural rights” (2009), at para 32.  234 Toonen.  

378

PART I   

116    

Similarly, Article 17 of the ICCPR, which India ratified on 11 December 1977,  

provides that:   

“The obligations imposed by this article require the State to  

adopt legislative and other measures to give effect to the  

prohibition against such interferences and attacks as well as  

to the protection of the right.”  

 

In its General Comment No. 16, the Human Rights Committee confirmed that  

any interference with privacy, even if provided for by law, “should be in  

accordance with the provisions, aims and objectives of the Covenant and  

should be, in any event, reasonable in the particular circumstances.”235  

 

In their general comments, concluding observations and views on  

communications, human rights treaty bodies have affirmed that States are  

obliged to protect individuals from discrimination on grounds of sexual  

orientation and/or gender identity, as these factors do not limit an individual’s  

entitlement to enjoy the full range of human rights to which they are entitled.236  

 

103 In NALSA, while dealing with the rights of transgender persons, this  

Court recognized the ‘Yogyakarta Principles on the Application of International  

Law in Relation to Issues of Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity’ – which  

                                                           235 Supra note 230, at page 6.   236 Ibid.

379

PART I   

117    

outline the rights that sexual minorities enjoy as human persons under the  

protection of international law – and held that they should be applied as a part  

of Indian law. Principle 33 provides thus:  

“Everyone has the right to be free from criminalisation and  

any form of sanction arising directly or indirectly from that  

person’s actual or perceived sexual orientation, gender  

identity, gender expression or sex characteristics.”  

 

While the Yogyakarta Principles are not legally binding, NALSA nevertheless  

signifies an affirmation of the right to non-discrimination on the grounds of  

gender identity, as well as the relevance of international human rights norms  

in addressing violations of these rights.  

 

104 There is a contradiction between India’s international obligations and  

Section 377 of the Indian Penal Code, insofar as it criminalizes consensual  

sexual acts between same-sex adults in private. In adjudicating the validity of  

this provision, the Indian Penal Code must be brought into conformity with  

both the Indian Constitution and the rules and principles of international law  

that India has recognized. Both make a crucial contribution towards  

recognizing the human rights of sexual and gender minorities.  

 

380

PART J   

118    

J Transcending borders - comparative law  

 105 Over the past several decades, international and domestic courts have  

developed a strong body of jurisprudence against discrimination based on  

sexual orientation. This section analyses the evolution of the perspective of  

the law towards sexual orientation from a comparative law perspective, and  

looks at how sodomy laws have been construed in various jurisdictions based  

on their histories.   

 

106 In 1967, England and Wales decriminalized same-sex intercourse  

between consenting adult males in private, and in 1980, Scotland followed  

suit. The law in Northern Ireland only changed in 1982 with the decision of the  

ECtHR in Dudgeon v The United Kingdom (“Dudgeon”).237 The Petitioners  

challenged the Offences against the Person Act, 1861, the Criminal Law  

Amendment Act, 1885 and a sodomy law that made buggery and “gross  

indecency” a criminal offense, irrespective of consent. Although the law did  

not specifically define these terms, the Court interpreted ‘buggery’ to mean  

anal intercourse by a man with a man or woman and gross indecency to mean  

any act “involving sexual indecency between male persons.” Regarding acts  

prohibited by these provisions, the ECtHR observed that:  

                                                           237 App No 7525/76, (1981) ECHR 5.

381

PART J   

119    

“Although it is not homosexuality itself which is prohibited but  

the particular acts of gross indecency between males and  

buggery, there can be no doubt but that male homosexual  

practices whose prohibition is the subject of the applicant’s  

complaints come within the scope of the offences punishable  

under the impugned legislation.”  

 

The ECtHR concluded that Dudgeon had suffered and continued to suffer an  

unjustified interference with his right to respect for his private life. Hence, the  

Court struck down the laws under challenge as violative of Article 8 of the  

European Convention on Human Rights, in so far as they criminalised “private  

homosexual relations between adult males capable of valid consent.” In  

observing that these laws were not proportionate to their purported need, the  

Court observed:  

“On the issue of proportionality, the Court considers that such  

justifications as there are for retaining the law in force  

unamended are outweighed by the detrimental effects which  

the very existence of the legislative provisions in question can  

have on the life of a person of homosexual orientation like the  

applicant. Although members of the public who regard  

homosexuality as immoral may be shocked, offended or  

disturbed by the commission by others of private homosexual  

acts, this cannot on its own warrant the application of penal  

sanctions when it is consenting adults alone who are  

involved.”238  

 

The ECtHR thus concluded:  

“To sum up, the restriction imposed on Mr. Dudgeon under  

Northern Ireland law, by reason of its breadth and absolute  

character, is, quite apart from the severity of the possible  

                                                           238 Ibid, at para 60.

382

PART J   

120    

penalties provided for, disproportionate to the aims sought to  

be achieved.”239  

 

Later, in Norris v Ireland240, the Applicant challenged Ireland's criminalization  

of certain homosexual acts between consenting adult men as being violative  

of Article 8 of the European Convention on Human Rights, which protected  

the right to respect for private and family life. The ECtHR held that the law  

violated Article 8, regardless of whether it was actively enforced:  

“A law which remains on the statute books even though it is  

not enforced in a particular class of cases for a considerable  

time, may be applied again in such cases at any time, if for  

example, there is a change of policy. The applicant can  

therefore be said to ‘run the risk of being directly affected’ by  

the legislation in question.”  

 

This decision was affirmed in Modinos v Cyprus241, where the Criminal Code  

of Cyprus, which penalized homosexual conduct, was alleged to constitute an  

unjustified interference with the Applicant’s private life.  

 

107 Five years after Dudgeon, the United States Supreme Court, in  

Bowers v. Hardwick (“Bowers”)242, held that “sodomy” laws had been a  

significant part of American history and did not violate the Constitution. The  

Supreme Court’s reasoning in Bowers is a clear departure from that of the  

                                                           239 Ibid, at para 61.  240 Application No. 10581/83, (1988) ECHR 22.  241 Application No. 15070/89,16 EHRR 485.  242 478 U.S. 186 (1986).

383

PART J   

121    

ECtHR in Dudgeon. In Bowers, the Supreme Court declined to accept that  

the question concerned the right to privacy. Instead, it stated that the issue  

was about "a fundamental right upon homosexuals to engage in sodomy”,243  

which was held not to be protected by the US Constitution.  

 

Seventeen years later, the United States Supreme Court laid the constitutional  

foundation for LGBT rights in the country with its judgment in Lawrence v  

Texas (“Lawrence”).244 In Lawrence, the Petitioner had been arrested under  

a Texas statute, which prohibited same-sex persons from engaging in sexual  

conduct, regardless of consent. The validity of the statute was considered.  

 

Relying on Dudgeon, the U S Supreme Court struck down the statute as  

violative of the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the U.S.  

Constitution. Overruling the judgment in Bowers, Justice Kennedy, writing for  

the majority, upheld Justice Stevens’ dissent in Bowers – who was also part  

of the majority in Lawrence – to note that:  

“Our prior cases make two propositions abundantly clear.  

First, the fact that the governing majority in a State has  

traditionally viewed a particular practice as immoral is not a  

sufficient reason for upholding a law prohibiting the practice;  

neither history nor tradition could save a law prohibiting  

miscegenation from constitutional attack. Second, individual  

                                                           243 Bowers, at para 190.  244 539 U.S. 558 (2003).

384

PART J   

122    

decisions by married persons, concerning the intimacies of  

their physical relationship, even when not intended to produce  

offspring, are a form of “liberty” protected by the Due Process  

Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Moreover, this  

protection extends to intimate choices by unmarried as well  

as married persons.”245   

 

He also noted that the case concerned the private, personal relationships of  

consenting adults, and that the laws challenged did not further any legitimate  

state interest:   

“The present case does not involve minors. It does not  

involve persons who might be injured or coerced or who are  

situated in relationships where consent might not easily be  

refused. It does not involve public conduct or prostitution. It  

does not involve whether the government must give formal  

recognition to any relationship that homosexual persons seek  

to enter [eg, a right to marry or to register a ‘civil union’]. The  

case does involve two adults who, with full and mutual  

consent from each other, engaged in sexual practices  

common to a homosexual lifestyle. The petitioners are  

entitled to respect for their private lives. The State cannot  

demean their existence or control their destiny by making  

their private sexual conduct a crime. Their right to liberty  

under the Due Process Clause gives them the full right to  

engage in their conduct without intervention of the  

government. ... The Texas statute furthers no legitimate state  

interest which can justify its intrusion into the personal and  

private life of the individual....”  

 

108 Justice Kennedy also identified the harm caused by the operation of the  

criminal law:   

“When homosexual conduct is made criminal by the law of  

the State, that declaration in and of itself is an invitation to  

                                                           245 Bowers, at para 216.

385

PART J   

123    

subject homosexual persons to discrimination both in the  

public and in the private spheres.”  

 

The Court thus struck down the Texas law banning “deviate sexual  

intercourse” between persons of the same sex (and similar laws in 13 other  

US states and Puerto Rico), holding that:  

“The laws involved in Bowers and here are, to be sure,  

statutes that purport to do no more than prohibit a particular  

sexual act. Their penalties and purposes, though, have  

more far-reaching consequences, touching upon the  

most private human conduct, sexual behavior, and in the  

most private of places, the home. The statutes do seek to  

control a personal relationship that, whether or not entitled to  

formal recognition in the law, is within the liberty of persons to  

choose without being punished as criminals.”                                    

(Emphasis supplied)   

 

109 In Toonen, the UN Human Rights Committee held that laws used to  

criminalize private, adult, consensual same-sex sexual relations violate the  

right to privacy and the right to non-discrimination. Mr Toonen – a member of  

the Tasmanian Gay Law Reform Group – had complained to the Committee  

about a Tasmanian law that criminalized ‘unnatural sexual intercourse’,  

‘intercourse against nature’ and ‘indecent practice between male persons’.  

The law allowed police officers to investigate intimate aspects of his private  

life and to detain him if they had reason to believe that he was involved in  

sexual activities with his long-term partner in the privacy of their home. Mr

386

PART J   

124    

Toonen challenged these laws as violative of Article 2(1)246, Article 17247 and  

Article 26248 of the ICCPR, on the ground that:  

“[The provisions] have created the conditions for  

discrimination in employment, constant stigmatization,  

vilification, threats of physical violence and the violation of  

basic democratic rights.”249   

 

The Committee rejected the argument that criminalization may be justified as  

“reasonable” on grounds of protection of public health or morals, noting that  

the use of criminal law in such circumstances is neither necessary nor  

proportionate:250  

“As far as the public health argument of the Tasmanian  

authorities is concerned, the Committee notes that the  

criminalization of homosexual practices cannot be considered  

a reasonable means or proportionate measure to achieve the  

aim of preventing the spread of AIDS/HIV.”   

 

 

                                                           246 Article 2(1): Each State Party to the present Covenant undertakes to respect and to ensure to all individuals within  

its territory and subject to its jurisdiction the rights recognized in the present Covenant, without distinction of any  kind, such as race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property,  birth or other status.  

247 Article 17: No one shall be subjected to arbitrary or unlawful interference with his privacy, family, home or  correspondence, nor to unlawful attacks on his honour and reputation.  

248 Article 26: All persons are equal before the law and are entitled without any discrimination to the equal protection  of the law. In this respect, the law shall prohibit any discrimination and guarantee to all persons equal and  effective protection against discrimination on any ground such as race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or  other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status.  

249 Toonen, at para 2.4.  250 Toonen, at para. 8.5.

387

PART J   

125    

The Court concluded that the legislation was violative of Article 7 of the  

ICCPR, holding that:  

“… It is undisputed that adult consensual sexual activity in  

private is covered by the concept of “privacy”, and that Mr.  

Toonen is actually and currently affected by the continued  

existence of the Tasmanian laws.”251  

 

110 In X v. Colombia252, the Committee clarified that there is no “Global  

South exception” to Toonen.253 The Egyptian and Tunisian members of the  

Committee, who dissented from the majority’s decision requiring equal  

treatment of unmarried same-sex and different-sex couples, concurred with  

the principle laid down in Toonen:   

“[T]here is no doubt that [A]rticle 17…is violated by  

discrimination on grounds of sexual orientation. The  

Committee…has rightly and repeatedly found that protection  

against arbitrary or unlawful interference with privacy  

precludes prosecution and punishment for homosexual  

relations between consenting adults.”  

 

111 The Constitutional Tribunal of Ecuador was the first Constitutional Court  

in the Global South to decriminalise sodomy laws.254 The constitutionality of  

Article 516 of the Penal Code, which penalised “cases of homosexualism, that  

do not constitute rape”, was challenged before the Tribunal. The Tribunal’s  

                                                           251 Toonen, at para 8.2.  252 Communication No. 1361/2005.  253 Robert Wintemute, “Same-Sex Love and Indian Penal Code §377: An Important Human Rights Issue for India”  

National University of Juridical Sciences Law Review, (2011).  254 Case No. 111-97-TC (27 November 1997).

388

PART J   

126    

reasoning was that “this abnormal behaviour should be the object of medical  

treatment ... imprisonment in jails, creates a suitable environment for the  

development of this dysfunction.” The Tribunal’s line of reasoning – referring  

to homosexual activity as ‘abnormal behaviour’, requiring medical treatment –  

is seriously problematic.255 That assumption is unfounded in fact and is an  

incorrect doctrine for a constitutional court which protects liberty and dignity.  

However ultimately, the Tribunal struck down the first paragraph of Article 516  

of the Penal Code, holding that:  

“Homosexuals are above all holders of all the rights of the  

human person and therefore, have the right to exercise them  

in conditions of full equality ... that is to say that their rights  

enjoy legal protection, as long as in the exteriorisation of their  

behaviour they do not harm the rights of others, as is the case  

with all other persons.”  

 

112 The adverse impact of sodomy laws on the lives of homosexual adults  

was also considered by the Constitutional Court of South Africa in National  

Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v. Minister of Justice (“National  

Coalition”)256, in which the constitutionality of the common law offence of  

sodomy and other legislations which penalised unnatural sexual acts between  

men was at issue. The Constitutional Court unanimously found that the  

sodomy laws, all of which purported to proscribe sexual intimacy between  

                                                           255 The Tribunal’s decision was criticized by LGBT rights activists for its description of homosexuality as “abnormal  

conduct.” However, a year after this decision, Ecuador became the third country in the world to include sexual  orientation as a constitutionally protected category against discrimination.  

256 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC).

389

PART J   

127    

homosexual adult men, violated their right to equality and discriminated  

against them on the basis of their sexual orientation.  

Justice Ackerman, concurring with the ECtHR’s observation in Norris, noted  

that:  

“The discriminatory prohibitions on sex between men  

reinforces already existing societal prejudices and severely  

increases the negative effects of such prejudices on their  

lives.”257  

 

Justice Ackerman quoted from Edwin Cameron’s “Sexual Orientation and the  

Constitution: A Test Case for Human Rights”258:  

“Even when these provisions are not enforced, they reduce  

gay men… to what one author has referred to as  

‘unapprehended felons’, thus entrenching stigma and  

encouraging discrimination in employment and  

insurance and in judicial decisions about custody and  

other matters bearing on orientation.”259                          

(Emphasis supplied)  

 

Commenting on the violation of individuals’ rights to privacy and dignity, the  

Court held that:   

“Gay people are a vulnerable minority group in our society.  

Sodomy laws criminalise their most intimate relationships.  

This devalues and degrades gay men and therefore  

constitutes a violation of their fundamental right to dignity.  

Furthermore, the offences criminalise private conduct  

                                                           257 National Coalition, at para 23.  258 (1993) 110 SALJ 450.  259 National Coalition, at para 23.

390

PART J   

128    

between consenting adults which causes no harm to anyone  

else. This intrusion on the innermost sphere of human life  

violates the constitutional right to privacy. The fact that the  

offences, which lie at the heart of the discrimination, also  

violate the rights to privacy and dignity strengthens the  

conclusion that the discrimination against gay men is unfair.”  

 

In its conclusion, the Court held that all persons have a right to a “sphere of  

private intimacy and autonomy that allows [them] to establish and nurture  

human relationships without interference from the outside community.”260  

 

113 In 2005, the High Court of Fiji, in Dhirendra Nadan Thomas McCoskar  

v. State261, struck down provisions of the Fijian Penal Code, which punished  

any person who permits a male person to have “carnal knowledge” of him, as  

well as acts of “gross indecency” between male persons. The High Court read  

down the provisions to the extent that they were inconsistent with the  

Constitution of Fiji, drawing a clear distinction between consensual and non-

consensual sexual behavior:   

“What the constitution requires is that the Law acknowledges  

difference, affirms dignity and allows equal respect to every  

citizen as they are. The acceptance of difference celebrates  

diversity. The affirmation of individual dignity offers respect to  

the whole of society. The promotion of equality can be a  

source of interactive vitality…A country so founded will put  

sexual expression in private relationships into its proper  

perspective and allow citizens to define their own good  

moral sensibilities leaving the law to its necessary duties  

                                                           260 National Coalition, at para 32.  261 [2005] FJHC 500.

391

PART J   

129    

of keeping sexual expression in check by protecting the  

vulnerable and penalizing the predator.”                

(Emphasis supplied)  

 

In recent years, the Caribbean States of Belize and Trinidad and Tobago have  

also decriminalized consensual sexual acts between adults in private. In  

Caleb Orozco v. The Attorney General of Belize (“Caleb Orozco”)262,  

provisions of the Belize Criminal Code which penalized “every person who  

has intercourse against the order of nature with any person…” were  

challenged before the Supreme Court. Commenting on the concept of dignity,  

Justice Benjamin borrowed from the Canadian Supreme Court’s observations  

and noted that:263  

“Human dignity means that an individual or group feels self-

respect and self-worth. It is concerned with physical and  

psychological integrity and empowerment. Human dignity is  

harmed by unfair treatment premised upon personal  

traits or circumstances which do not relate to the  

individual needs, capacities or merits. It is enhanced by  

laws which are sensitive to the needs, capacities and merits  

of different individuals, taking into account the context  

underlying the differences.”          (Emphasis supplied)  

 

Relying on the judgments in Dudgeons, National Coalition, McCoskar,  

Toonen, and Lawrence, the Supreme Court struck down the provision as  

violative of the claimant’s constitutional rights to privacy, dignity, and equality.  

Justice Benjamin held thus:  

                                                           262 Claim No. 668 of 2010.  263 Law v Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497.

392

PART J   

130    

“However, from the perspective of legal principle, the Court  

cannot act upon prevailing majority views or what is popularly  

accepted as moral…There must be demonstrated that some  

harm will be caused should the proscribed conduct be  

rendered unregulated. No evidence has been presented as to  

the real likelihood of such harm. The duty of the Court is to  

apply the provisions of the Constitution.”264  

 

114 In Jason Jones v. The Attorney General of Trinidad and Tobago  

(“Jones”)265, an expatriate gay rights activist living in the United Kingdom  

challenged the provisions of Trinidad and Tobago’s Sexual Offences Act,  

which criminalized ‘buggery’ and ‘serious indecency’ before the High Court of  

Justice at Trinidad and Tobago. The central issue before the Court was  

whether the provisions were ‘saved’ under Section 6 of the Constitution, which  

protects laws that were in existence before the Constitution came into force  

and were only marginally changed since, from being struck down for breach of  

fundamental rights.  

 

The High Court struck down the provisions as unconstitutional, observing that  

the right to choose a partner and to have a family is intrinsic to an individual’s  

personal autonomy and dignity:  

“To this court, human dignity is a basic and inalienable right  

recognized worldwide in all democratic societies. Attached to  

that right is the concept of autonomy and the right of an  

individual to make decisions for herself/himself without any  

                                                           264 Caleb Orozco, at para 81.  265 Claim no. CV2017-00720.

393

PART J   

131    

unreasonable intervention by the State. In a case such as  

this, she/he must be able to make decisions as to who she/he  

loves, incorporates in his/her life, who she/he wishes to live  

with and with who to make a family.”266   

 

The High Court also held that the existence of such laws deliberately  

undermined the lives of homosexuals:  

“A citizen should not have to live under the constant threat,  

the proverbial “Sword of Damocles,” that at any moment  

she/he may be persecuted or prosecuted. That is the threat  

that exists at present. It is a threat that is sanctioned by the  

State and that sanction is an important sanction because it  

justifies in the mind of others in society who are differently  

minded, that the very lifestyle, life and existence of a person  

who chooses to live in the way that the claimant does is  

criminal and is deemed to be of a lesser value than anyone  

else…The Parliament has taken the deliberate decision to  

criminalise the lifestyle of persons like the claimant whose  

ultimate expression of love and affection is crystallised in an  

act which is statutorily unlawful, whether or not enforced.”267  

(Emphasis supplied)  

 

The High Court compared the impugned provisions to racial segregation, the  

Holocaust, and apartheid, observing that:  

“To now deny a perceived minority their right to humanity and  

human dignity would be to continue this type of thinking, this  

type of perceived superiority, based on the genuinely held  

beliefs of some.”268  

 

                                                           266 Jones, at para 91.  267 Ibid.  268 Jones, at para 171.

394

PART J   

132    

115 In Leung TC William Roy v. Secretary for Justice269, the High Court  

of Hong Kong considered the constitutional validity of provisions that  

prescribed different ages of consent for buggery and regular sexual  

intercourse. The court held that these provisions violated the petitioner’s rights  

to privacy and equality:  

“Denying persons of a minority class the right to sexual  

expression in the only way available to them, even if that way  

is denied to all, remains discriminatory when persons of a  

majority class are permitted the right to sexual expression in a  

way natural to them.  During the course of submissions, it  

was described as ‘disguised discrimination’.  It is, I think, an  

apt description.  It is disguised discrimination founded on a  

single base: sexual orientation.”270  

 

The Court concluded that the difference in the ages of consent was  

unjustifiable, noting that:  

“No evidence has been placed before us to explain why the  

minimum age requirement for buggery is 21 whereas as far  

as sexual intercourse between a man and a woman is  

concerned, the age of consent is only 16.  There is, for  

example, no medical reason for this and none was suggested  

in the course of argument.”271  

 

Courts around the world have not stopped at decriminalizing sodomy laws;  

they have gone a step further and developed a catena of broader rights and  

protections for homosexuals. These rights go beyond the mere freedom to  

                                                           269 Civil Appeal No. 317 of 2005.  270 Ibid, at para 48.  271 Ibid, at para 51.

395

PART J   

133    

engage in consensual sexual activity in private, and include the right to full  

citizenship, the right to form unions and the right to family life.  

 

116 Israel was one of the first countries to recognize the rights of  

homosexuals against discrimination in matters of employment. In El-Al Israel  

Airlines Ltd v. Jonathan Danielwitz (“El-Al Israel Airlines”)272, the Supreme  

Court of Israel considered an airline company’s policy of giving discounted  

tickets to their employees and a ‘companion recognized as the husband/wife  

of the employee’. This benefit was also given to a partner with whom the  

employee was living together like husband and wife, but not married.  

However, the airline refused to give the discounted tickets to the Respondent  

and his male partner.   

 

The Supreme Court of Israel observed thus:  

“The principle of equality demands that the existence of a rule  

that treats people differently is justified by the nature and  

substance of the issue…therefore, a particular law will create  

discrimination when two individuals who are different from  

one another (factual inequality), are treated differently by the  

law, even though the factual difference between them  

does not justify different treatment in the  

circumstances.”273                 (Emphasis supplied)  

 

                                                           272 HCJ 721/94.  273 El-A Israel Airlines, at para 14.

396

PART J   

134    

The Supreme Court held that giving a benefit to an employee who has a  

spouse of the opposite sex and denying the same benefit to an employee  

whose spouse is of the same sex amounts to discrimination based on sexual  

orientation. This violated the Petitioner’s right to equality and created an  

unjustifiable distinction in the context of employee benefits.  

 

117 In Vriend v Alberta274, the appellant, a homosexual college employee,  

was terminated from his job. He alleged that his employer had discriminated  

against him because of his sexual orientation, but that he could not make a  

complaint under Canada’s anti-discrimination statute – the Individual’s Rights  

Protection Act (“IRPA”) – because it did not include sexual orientation as a  

protected ground. The Supreme Court of Canada held that the omission of  

protection against discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation was an  

unjustified violation of the right to equality under the Canadian Charter of  

Rights and Freedoms.  

 

118 The Supreme Court held that the State had failed to provide a rational  

justification for the omission of sexual orientation as a protected ground under  

the IRPA. Commenting on the domino effect that such discriminatory  

measures have on the lives of homosexuals, the Supreme Court noted thus:                                                              274 (1998) 1 S.C.R. 493.   

397

PART J   

135    

“Perhaps most important is the psychological harm which  

may ensue from this state of affairs. Fear of discrimination will  

logically lead to concealment of true identity and this must be  

harmful to personal confidence and self-esteem.  

Compounding that effect is the implicit message conveyed by  

the exclusion, that gays and lesbians, unlike other individuals,  

are not worthy of protection. This is clearly an example of a  

distinction which demeans the individual and strengthens and  

perpetrates [sic] the view that gays and lesbians are less  

worthy of protection as individuals in Canada’s society. The  

potential harm to the dignity and perceived worth of gay and  

lesbian individuals constitutes a particularly cruel form of  

discrimination.”  

 

The next breakthrough for LGBTQ rights came from the Supreme Court of  

Nepal, in Sunil Babu Pant v. Nepal Government275. Sunil Pant – the first  

openly gay Asian national leader – filed a PIL before the Supreme Court of  

Nepal praying for the recognition of the rights of lesbians, gays, and third  

gender persons. The Supreme Court located the rights of LGBTQ persons to  

their sexuality within the right to privacy, holding that:  

“The right to privacy is a fundamental right of any individual.  

The issue of sexual activity falls under the definition of  

privacy. No one has the right to question how do two adults  

perform the sexual intercourse and whether this intercourse is  

natural or unnatural.”  

 

The Court held that all individuals have an inherent right to marriage,  

regardless of their sexual orientation:  

                                                           275 Writ Petition No. 917 of 2007.

398

PART J   

136    

“Looking at the issue of same sex marriage, we hold that it is  

an inherent right of an adult to have marital relation with  

another adult with his/her free consent and according to  

her/his will.”  

 

In concluding, the Court directed the Nepalese government to enact new  

legislation or amend existing legislation to ensure that persons of all sexual  

orientations and gender identities could enjoy equal rights.    

 

119 In 2015, in Oliari v Italy (“Oliari”)276, the Applicants before the ECtHR  

argued that the absence of legislation in Italy permitting same-sex marriage or  

any other type of civil union constituted discrimination on the basis of sexual  

orientation, in violation of Articles 8, 12, and 14 of the European Convention  

on Human Rights. In line with its previous case law, the Court affirmed that  

same-sex couples “are in need of legal recognition and protection of their  

relationship.”277 The ECtHR concluded that gay couples are equally capable  

of entering into stable and committed relationships in the same way as  

heterosexual couples.278  

 

120 The ECtHR examined the domestic context in Italy, and noted a clear  

gap between the “social reality of the applicants”,279 who openly live their  

                                                           276 [2015] ECHR 716  277 Oliari, at para 165.  278 Ibid.  279 Oliari, at para. 173.

399

PART J   

137    

relationship, and the law, which fails to formally recognize same-sex  

partnerships. The Court held that in the absence of any evidence of a  

prevailing community interest in preventing legal recognition of same-sex  

partnerships, Italian authorities “have overstepped their margin of appreciation  

and failed to fulfil their positive obligation to ensure that the applicants have  

available a specific legal framework providing for the recognition and  

protection of their same-sex unions.”280  

 

121 In 2013, in United States v. Windsor281, US Supreme Court considered  

the constitutionality of the Defense of Marriage Act (“DOMA”) which states  

that, for the purposes of federal law, the words ‘marriage’ and ‘spouse’ refer to  

legal unions between one man and one woman. Windsor, who had inherited  

the estate of her same-sex partner, was barred from claiming the federal  

estate tax exemption for surviving spouses since her marriage was not  

recognized by federal law.282 Justice Kennedy writing for the majority, held  

that restricting the federal interpretation of ‘marriage’ and ‘spouse’ to apply  

only to opposite-sex unions was unconstitutional under the Due Process  

Clause of the Fifth Amendment:  

“Its [the DOMA’s] unusual deviation from the tradition of  

recognizing and accepting state definitions of marriage  

                                                           280 Oliari, at para 185.  281 570 U.S. 744 (2013).  282 Section 3, Defense of Marriage Act.

400

PART J   

138    

operates to deprive same-sex couples of the benefits and  

responsibilities that come with federal recognition of their  

marriages. This is strong evidence of a law having the  

purpose and effect of disapproval of a class recognized and  

protected by state law. DOMA’s avowed purpose and  

practical effect are to impose a disadvantage, a separate  

status, and so a stigma upon all who enter into same-sex  

marriages made lawful by the unquestioned authority of the  

States.”  

 

Two years later, in Obergefell v. Hodges (“Obergefell”),283 while analysing  

precedent and decisions of other US courts recognizing same-sex marriage,  

Justice Kennedy observed that:  

“A first premise of the Court’s relevant precedents is that the  

right to personal choice regarding marriage is inherent in the  

concept of individual autonomy… Like choices concerning  

contraception, family relationships, procreation, and  

childrearing, all of which are protected by the Constitution,  

decisions concerning marriage are among the most intimate  

that an individual can make.”284  

 

122 Justice Kennedy expressed the need to go beyond the narrow holding  

in Lawrence, towards a more expansive view of the rights of homosexuals:  

“Lawrence invalidated laws that made same- sex intimacy a  

criminal act... But while Lawrence confirmed a dimension  

of freedom that allows individuals to engage in intimate  

association without criminal liability, it does not follow  

that freedom stops there. Outlaw to outcast may be a  

step forward, but it does not achieve the full promise of  

liberty.”                                 (Emphasis supplied)  

                                                           283 576 U.S. ___ (2015).  284 Obergefell, at page 12.

401

PART J   

139    

By a 5-4 majority, the US Supreme Court ruled that the fundamental right to  

marry is guaranteed to same-sex couples by the Due Process Clause and the  

Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the US Constitution.   

Commenting on the right to marriage, Justice Kennedy noted:  

“No union is more profound than marriage, for it embodies the  

highest ideals of love, fidelity, devotion, sacrifice, and family.  

… It would misunderstand these men and women to say they  

disrespect the idea of marriage. Their plea is that they do  

respect it, respect it so deeply that they seek to find its  

fulfilment for themselves. Their hope is not to be condemned  

to live in loneliness, excluded from one of civilization’s oldest  

institutions. They ask for equal dignity in the eyes of the law.  

The Constitution grants them that right.”  

 

123 The recent case of Masterpiece Cakeshop v. Colorado Civil Rights  

Commission (“Masterpiece Cakeshop”)285 concerned a Christian baker who  

was accused of violating an anti-discrimination ordinance for refusing to make  

a wedding cake for a same-sex couple based on his religious beliefs. The  

Colorado Civil Rights Commission (“CCRC”) decided against the baker, and,  

on appeal, the Supreme Court ruled 7-2 that the CCRC violated the baker’s  

rights under the First Amendment, which guarantees freedom of expression.   

 

Writing for the majority, Justice Kennedy said the CCRC showed “hostility” to  

the baker’s religious beliefs:  

                                                           285 584 U.S. ____ (2018).

402

PART J   

140    

“It must be concluded that the State’s interest could have  

been weighed against Phillips’ sincere religious objections in  

a way consistent with the requisite religious neutrality that  

must be strictly observed. The official expressions of hostility  

to religion in some of the commissioners’ comments—

comments that were not disavowed at the Commission or by  

the State at any point in the proceedings that led to  

affirmance of the order—were inconsistent with what the Free  

Exercise Clause requires. The Commission’s disparate  

consideration of Phillips’ case compared to the cases of the  

other bakers suggests the same. For these reasons, the order  

must be set aside.”  

 

The majority held that while the Constitution allows gay persons to exercise  

their civil rights, “religious and philosophical objections to gay marriage are  

protected views and in some instances protected forms of expression.” The  

Supreme Court found merit in the baker’s First Amendment claim, noting that  

his dilemma was understandable, especially given that the cause of action  

arose in 2012, before the enactment of Colorado’s anti-discrimination law and  

the Obergefell judgment that legalised same-sex marriage.   

 

The court buttressed its position by noting that in several other cases, bakers  

had declined to decorate cakes with messages that were derogatory towards  

gay persons and the State Civil Rights Division had held that the bakers were  

within their rights to have done so. According to the majority in Masterpiece  

Cakeshop, the owner was similarly entitled to decline the order, and his case  

should have been treated no differently.

403

PART J   

141    

124 Justice Ginsburg’s dissenting opinion, which was supported by Justice  

Sotomayor, distinguished the baker in Masterpiece Cakeshop from the other  

three bakers. Justice Ginsburg noted that while the other bakers would have  

refused the said cake decorations to all customers, Phillips refused to bake a  

wedding cake (which he baked for other customers), specifically for the  

couple. She observed that:   

“Phillips declined to make a cake he found offensive where  

the offensiveness of the product was determined solely  

by the identity of the customer requesting it. The three  

other bakeries declined to make cakes where their objection  

to the product was due to the demeaning message the  

requested product would literally display.”              (Emphasis  

supplied)  

“When a couple contacts a bakery for a wedding cake, the  

product they are seeking is a cake celebrating their  

wedding—not a cake celebrating heterosexual weddings or  

same-sex weddings—and that is the service Craig and  

Mullins were denied.”  

 

Justice Ginsburg concluded that a proper application of the Colorado Anti-

Discrimination Act would require upholding the lower courts’ rulings.  

 

125 Masterpiece Cakeshop is also distinguishable from a similar case, Lee  

v. Ashers Bakery Co. Ltd.286, which is currently on appeal to the United  

Kingdom Supreme Court. In that case, a bakery in Northern Ireland offered a  

                                                           286 [2015] NICty 2.

404

PART J   

142    

service whereby customers could provide messages, pictures or graphics that  

would be iced on a cake. Lee – a member of an LGBT organisation – ordered  

a cake with the words “support gay marriage” on it. The Christian owners  

refused, stating that preparing such an order would conflict with their religious  

beliefs. Lee claimed that in refusing his order, the bakery discriminated  

against him on grounds of sexual orientation. Both the County Court and the  

Court of Appeal ruled in favour of Lee, on the ground that the respondent’s  

refusal on the ground of his religious beliefs was contrary to the provisions of  

the Equality Act (Sexual Orientation) Regulations (Northern Ireland) 2006 and  

the Fair Employment and Treatment Order 1998.  

 

From an analysis of comparative jurisprudence from across the world, the  

following principles emerge:  

1. Sexual orientation is an intrinsic element of liberty, dignity, privacy,  

individual autonomy and equality;  

2. Intimacy between consenting adults of the same-sex is beyond the  

legitimate interests of the state;  

3. Sodomy laws violate equality by targeting a segment of the population for  

their sexual orientation;

405

PART J   

143    

4. Such a law perpetrates stereotypes, lends authority of the state to societal  

stereotypes and has a chilling effect on the exercise of freedom;  

5. The right to love and to a partner, to find fulfillment in a same-sex  

relationship is essential to a society which believes in freedom under a  

constitutional order based on rights;  

6. Sexual orientation implicates negative and positive obligations on the state.  

It not only requires the state not to discriminate, but also calls for the state  

to recognise rights which bring true fulfillment to same-sex relationships;  

and  

7. The constitutional principles which have led to decriminalization must  

continuously engage in a rights discourse to ensure that same-sex  

relationships find true fulfillment in every facet of life. The law cannot  

discriminate against same-sex relationships. It must also take positive  

steps to achieve equal protection.  

 

The past two decades have witnessed several decisions by constitutional and  

international courts, recognizing both the decriminalization of same-sex  

intercourse in private, as well as broader rights recognizing sexual orientation  

equality. In 1996, South Africa became the first country in the world to

406

PART J   

144    

constitutionally prohibit discrimination based on sexual orientation.287 As on  

the date of this judgment, ten countries constitutionally prohibit discrimination  

on grounds of sexual orientation.288 The United Kingdom, Bolivia, Ecuador,  

Fiji, and Malta specifically prohibit discrimination on the basis of gender  

identity, either constitutionally or through enacted laws.289 According the  

International Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, Trans and Intersex Association, 74  

countries (including India) criminalize same-sex sexual conduct, as of 2017.290  

Most of these countries lie in the Sub-Saharan and Middle East region. Some  

of them prescribe death penalty for homosexuality.291  

 

126 We are aware that socio-historical contexts differ from one jurisdiction to  

another and that we must therefore look at comparative law-making  

allowances for them. However, the overwhelming weight of international  

opinion and the dramatic increase in the pace of recognition of fundamental  

rights for same-sex couples reflects a growing consensus towards sexual  

orientation equality. We feel inclined to concur with the accumulated wisdom  

reflected in these judgments, not to determine the meaning of the guarantees

                                                           287 Amy Raub, “Protections Of Equal Rights Across Sexual Orientation And Gender Identity: An Analysis Of 193  

National Constitutions”, Yale Journal of Law and Feminism, Vol. 28 (2017).   288 Ibid. Of these, three are in the Americas (Bolivia, Ecuador, and Mexico), four are in Europe and Central Asia  

(Malta, Portugal, Sweden, and the United Kingdom), two are in East Asia and the Pacific (Fiji and New Zealand),  and one is in Sub-Saharan Africa (South Africa).  

289 Ibid.  290 The International Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, Trans And Intersex Association, “Sexual Orientation Laws of the World”,  

(2017).   291 Ibid.

407

PART K   

145    

contained within the Indian Constitution, but to provide a sound and  

appreciable confirmation of our conclusions about those guarantees.  

 

This evolution has enabled societies governed by liberal constitutional values  

– such as liberty, dignity, privacy, equality and individual autonomy – to move  

beyond decriminalisation of offences involving consensual same-sex  

relationships. Decriminalisation is of course necessary to bury the ghosts of  

morality which flourished in a radically different age and time. But  

decriminalisation is a first step. The constitutional principles on which it is  

based have application to a broader range of entitlements. The Indian  

Constitution is based on an abiding faith in those constitutional values. In the  

march of civilizations across the spectrum of a compassionate global order,  

India cannot be left behind.   

 

K Crime, morality and the Constitution  

 

127 The question of what qualifies as a punishable offence under the law  

has played a central role in legal theory. Attempts have been made by legal  

scholars and jurists alike, to define a crime. Halsbury’s Laws of England  

defines a crime as “an unlawful act or default which is an offence against the

408

PART K   

146    

public and renders the person guilty of the act or default liable to legal  

punishment.”292 As Glanville Williams observes:  

“A crime is an act capable of being followed by criminal  

proceedings, having a criminal outcome…criminal law is that  

branch of law which deals with conduct…by prosecution in  

the criminal courts.”293  

 

Henry Hart, in his essay titled “The Aims of Criminal Law”, 294 comments on  

the difficulty of a definition in this branch of law. A crime is a crime because it  

is called a crime:  

“If one were to judge from the notions apparently underlying  

many judicial opinions, and the overt language even of some  

of them, the solution of the puzzle is simply that a crime is  

anything which is called a crime, and a criminal penalty is  

simply the penalty provided for doing anything which has  

been given that name.”295  

 

However, Hart confesses that such a simplistic definition would be “a betrayal  

of intellectual bankruptcy.”296 Roscoe Pound articulates the dilemma in  

defining what constitutes an offence:   

“A final answer to the question ‘what is a crime?’, is  

impossible, because law is a living, changing thing, which  

may at one time be uniform, and at another time give much  

room for judicial discretion, which may at one time be more  

                                                           292 Halsbury’s Laws of England. 3rd edition, Vol. 3, Butterworths (1953) at page. 271.  293 Glanville Williams, ‘The Definition of Crime’, Current Legal Problems, Vol. 8 (1955).  294 Henry M. Hart, “The Aims of the Criminal Law”, Law and Contemporary Problems, Vol. 23 (1958), at pages 401–

441.   295 Ibid.   296 Ibid.  

409

PART K   

147    

specific in its prescription and at another time much more  

general.”297  

 

 

Early philosophers sought to define crime by distinguishing it from a civil  

wrong. In his study of rhetoric, Aristotle observed that:   

“Justice in relation to the person is defined in two ways. For it  

is defined either in relation to the community or to one of its  

members what one should or should not do. Accordingly, it is  

possible to perform just and unjust acts in two ways, either  

towards a defined individual or towards the community.”298  

 

Kant, in the Metaphysics of Morals,299 observed that:   

“A transgression of public law that makes someone who  

commits it unfit to be a citizen is called a crime simply  

(crimen) but is also called a public crime (crimen publicum);  

so the first (private crime) is brought before a civil court, the  

latter before a criminal court.”300  

 

Another method of defining crime is from the nature of injury caused, “of being  

public, as opposed to private, wrongs.”301 This distinction was brought out by  

Blackstone and later by Duff, in their theories on criminal law. Blackstone, in  

his “Commentaries on the Laws of England” put forth the idea that only  

                                                           297   Roscoe Pound, Interpretation of Legal History, Harvard University Press (1946).  298   H.C. Lawson-Tancred, The Art of Rhetoric/ Aristotle, Penguin (2004).  299   Immanuel Kant: The Metaphysics of Morals (Mary Gregor ed.), Cambridge University Press (1996).  300   Ibid, at pages 353, 331.  301   Grant Lamond, “What is a Crime?”, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol.27 (2007).  

410

PART K   

148    

actions which constitute a ‘public wrong’ will be classified as a crime.302 He  

characterised public wrongs as “a breach and violation of the public rights and  

duties, due to the whole community, considered as a community, in its social  

aggregate capacity.”303 Duff adds to the idea of public wrong by arguing that   

“[w]e should interpret a ‘public’ wrong, not as a wrong that injures the public,  

but as one that properly concerns the public, i.e. the polity as a whole.”304   

 

Nozick and Becker also support the theory that crime is conduct that harms  

the public. Nozick argues that the harm caused by a crime, unlike other  

private law wrongs, extends beyond the immediate victim to all those who  

view themselves as potential victims of the crime.305 When such an act is  

done on purpose, it spreads fear in the general community, and it is due to  

this additional harm to the community [of causing fear and insecurity], that  

such actions are classified as crimes and pursued by the state.306 Becker  

preferred to describe crime as something which disrupts social stability and  

has “the potential for destructive disturbance of fundamental social  

structures.”307  

                                                           302   Sir William Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, Book IV, Ch. 1 & 2.   303   Ibid.    304 Antony Duff and Sandra Marshall, “Criminalization and Sharing Wrongs”, Canadian Journal of Law and  

Jurisprudence, Vol. 11, (1998) at pages 7-22.  305 Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia, Basic Books (1974) ,at page 65.   306 Supra note 301.    307 Lawrence C. Becker, “Criminal Attempts and the Theory of the Law of Crimes”, Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol 3  

(1974), at page 273.  

411

PART K   

149    

However, Hart questioned the theory of simply defining crime as a public  

wrong, for all wrongs affect society in some way or the other:   

“Can crimes be distinguished from civil wrongs on the ground  

that they constitute  injuries to society generally which society  

is interested in preventing? The difficulty is that society is  

interested also in the due fulfilment of contracts and the  

avoidance of traffic accidents and most of the other stuff of  

civil litigation.” 308   

 

128 Hart preferred to define crime in terms of the methodology of criminal  

law and the characteristics of this method. He described criminal law as  

possessing the following features:  

“1. The method operates by means of a series of directions,  

or commands, formulated in general terms, telling people  

what they must or must not do…   

2. The commands are taken as valid and binding upon all  

those who fall within their terms when the time comes for  

complying with them, whether or not they have been  

formulated in advance in a single authoritative set of words…  

3. The commands are subject to one or more sanctions for  

disobedience which the community is prepared to enforce…   

4. What distinguishes a criminal from a civil sanction and  

all that distinguishes it, it is ventured, is the judgment of  

community condemnation which accompanies and justifies  

its imposition.”309        (Numbering and emphasis supplied)  

 

                                                           308 Supra note 294.  309 Ibid.

412

PART K   

150    

According to Hart, the first three characteristics above are common to both  

civil and criminal law.310 However, the key differentiating factor between  

criminal and civil law, he observed, is the “community condemnation.” 311 Thus,  

he attempted to define crime as:  

“Conduct which, if duly shown to have taken place, will incur a  

formal and solemn pronouncement of the moral  

condemnation of the community.” 312   

 

Perhaps it is difficult to carve out a single definition of crime due to the multi-

dimensional nature of criminal law. The process of deconstructing the  

criminalisation of consensual sexual acts by adults will be facilitated by  

examining some criminal theories and their interplay with Section 377.  

 

Criminal Law Theories  

 Bentham’s Utilitarian Theory  

129 Utilitarianism has provided some of the most powerful critiques of  

existing laws. Bentham was one of the earliest supporters for reform in  

sodomy laws. In his essay, “Offences Against One’s Self”,313 Bentham  

rebutted all the justifications given by the state for enacting laws on  

                                                           310 Ibid.   311 Ibid.   312 Ibid.   313 Jeremy Bentham, “Offences Against One's Self” (Louis Crompton Ed.), Columbia University.  

413

PART K   

151    

sodomy.314 According to Bentham, homosexuality, if viewed outside the  

realms of morality and religion, is neutral behaviour which gives the  

participants pleasure and does not cause pain to anyone else.315 Therefore,  

he concluded that such an act cannot constitute an offence, and there is “no  

reason for punishing it at all.”316   

 

130 Bentham tested sodomy laws on three main principles: (i) whether they  

produce any primary mischief, i.e., direct harm to another person; (ii) whether  

they produce any secondary mischief, i.e., harm to the stability and security of  

society; and (iii) whether they cause any danger to society.317  He argued that  

sodomy laws do not satisfy any of the above tests, and hence, should be  

repealed. On the first principle of primary mischief, Bentham said:  

“As to any primary mischief, it is evident that it produces no  

pain in anyone. On the contrary it produces pleasure, and that  

a pleasure which, by their perverted taste, is by this  

supposition preferred to that pleasure which is in general  

reputed the greatest. The partners are both willing. If either of  

them be unwilling, the act is not that which we have here in  

view: it is an offence totally different in its nature of effects: it  

is a personal injury; it is a kind of rape.” 318   

 

                                                           314 Ibid.   315 Ibid.  316 Ibid.  317 Ibid.  318 Ibid.

414

PART K   

152    

Thus, Bentham argued that consensual homosexual acts do not harm anyone  

else. Instead, they are a source of pleasure to adults who choose to engage in  

them. Bentham was clear about the distinction between ‘willing’ partners and  

‘unwilling’ partners, and the latter according to him, would not fall under his  

defence.   

 

Bentham’s second argument was that there was no secondary mischief,  

which he described as something which may “produce any alarm in the  

community.” On this, Bentham argued:   

“As to any secondary mischief, it produces not any pain of  

apprehension. For what is there in it for any body to be afraid  

of? By the supposition, those only are the objects of it who  

choose to be so, who find a pleasure, for so it seems they do,  

in being so.”319  

 

Bentham’s explanation was that only those adults who choose will be the  

objects of homosexual sexual acts. It does not involve any activity which will  

create anxiety among the rest of the society. Therefore, homosexuality does  

not cause secondary harm either.   

 

Lastly, Bentham tested sodomy laws on whether they cause danger to  

society. The only danger that Bentham could apprehend was the supposed  

                                                           319 Ibid.  

415

PART K   

153    

danger of encouraging others to engage in homosexual practices. However,  

Bentham argues that since homosexual activities in themselves do not cause  

any harm, there is no danger even if they have a domino effect on other  

individuals:  

“As to any danger exclusive of pain, the danger, if any, must  

consist in the tendency of the example. But what is the  

tendency of this example? To dispose others to engage in the  

same practises: but this practise for anything that has yet  

appeared produces not pain of any kind to anyone.” 320  

 

Thus, according to Bentham, sodomy laws fail on all three grounds- they  

neither cause primary mischief, nor secondary mischief, nor any danger to  

society.   

Bentham also critiqued criminal laws by analysing the utility of the punishment  

prescribed by them. He succinctly described the objective of law through the  

principles of utility- “The general object which all laws have, or ought to  

have…is to augment the total happiness of the community; [and] to  

exclude…everything that tends to subtract from that happiness.”321 According  

to Bentham, “all punishment in itself is evil”322 because it reduces the level of  

happiness in society, and should be prescribed only if it “excludes some  

                                                           320 Ibid.   321 Ibid.  322 Ibid.

416

PART K   

154    

greater evil.”323 Bentham stipulated four kinds of situations where it is not  

utilitarian to inflict punishment:    

“1. Where it is groundless: where there is no mischief for it to  

prevent; the act not being mischievous upon the whole.  

2. Where it must be inefficacious: where it cannot act so as to  

prevent the mischief.   

3. Where it is unprofitable, or too expensive: where the  

mischief it would produce would be greater than what it  

prevented.  

4. Where it is needless: where the mischief may be  

prevented, or cease of itself, without it: that is, at a cheaper  

rate.”324  

 

The Harm Principle  

131 John Stuart Mill, in his treatise “On Liberty,” makes a powerful case to  

preclude governments from interfering in those areas of an individual’s life  

which are private. Mill’s theory, which came to be called the “harm principle”,  

suggests that the state can intrude into private life by way of sanction only if  

harm is caused to others or if the conduct is “other-affecting.”325 In Mill’s  

words:  

“The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised  

over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is  

to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or  

moral, is not a sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be  

compelled to do or forbear because it will be better for him to  

do so, because it will make him happier, because, in the  

                                                           323 Ibid.  324 Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, The Library of Economics and  

Liberty (1823).  325 John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, (Elizabeth Rapaport ed), Hackett Publishing Co, Inc (1978).  

417

PART K   

155    

opinions of others, to do so would be wise, or even right…  

The only part of the conduct of any one, for which he is  

amenable to society, is that which concerns others. In the part  

which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right,  

absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the  

individual is sovereign.” 326  (Emphasis supplied)  

 

Mill created a dichotomy between “self-regarding” actions (those which affect  

the individual himself and have no significant effect on society at large) and  

“other-regarding” actions (those which affect the society).327  He was aware  

that in a way, all actions of an individual are likely to affect “those nearly  

connected with him and, in a minor degree, society at large.”328  However, he  

argued that as long as an action does not “violate a distinct and assignable  

obligation to any other person or persons”, it may not be taken out of the self-

regarding class of actions.329 Thus, Mill proposed that “all that portion of a  

person’s life and conduct which affects only himself, or, if it also affects others,  

only with their free, voluntary, and undeceived consent and participation”  

should be free from state interference.330 He further added that the state and  

society are not justified in interfering in the self-regarding sphere, merely  

because they believe certain conduct to be “foolish, perverse, or wrong.”331  

 

                                                           326 Ibid.   327 Ibid.  328 Ibid.  329 Ibid.  330 Ibid.  331 Ibid.

418

PART K   

156    

Essentially, Mill created a taxonomy on types of conduct – (a) self-regarding  

actions should not be the subject of sanctions either from the state or society;  

(b) actions which may hurt others but do not violate any legal rights may only  

be the subject of public condemnation but not state sanction; (c) only action  

which violate the legal rights of others should be the subject of legal sanction  

(and public condemnation).332 The harm principle thus, operated as a negative  

or limiting principle, with the main objective of restricting criminal law from  

penalising conduct merely on the basis of its perceived immorality or  

unacceptability when the same is not harmful.333   

 

While Mill’s theory was not propounded in relation to LGBTQ rights, his  

understanding of criminal law is well-suited to argue that sodomy laws  

criminalise ‘self-regarding’ actions which fall under the first category of  

conduct, and should not be subjected to sanctions either by the state or the  

society.   

 

132 A jurisprudential debate on the interplay between criminal law and  

morality was set off when Lord Devlin delivered the 1959 Maccabean Lecture,  

                                                           332 Mark Strasser, “Lawrence, Mill, and Same Sex Relationships: On Values, Valuing and the Constitution”, Southern  

California Interdisciplinary Law Journal, Vol. 15 (2006).  333 Joseph Raz, ‘Autonomy, Toleration and the Harm Principle’, in Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy: The  

Influence of HLA Hart (R. Gavison ed.), Oxford University Press (1987).

419

PART K   

157    

titled “The Enforcement of Morals.”334 Lord Devlin’s lecture was an attack  

against the Report of the Wolfenden Committee on Homosexual Offences and  

Prostitution (“Wolfenden Report”), which had recommended the  

decriminalisation of sodomy laws in England.335 The Wolfenden Committee,  

headed by Sir John Wolfenden, Vice-Chancellor of Reading University, was  

set up in 1954 to consider the criminalisation of homosexuality and  

prostitution, in the wake of increased arrests and convictions in the UK for  

homosexuality between men.336 Among those prosecuted for ‘gross  

indecency’ under the Buggery Act of 1553 and Sexual Offences Act of 1967  

were eminent persons like Oscar Wilde, Alan Turing and Lord Montagu of  

Beaulieu.337 After conducting a three-year long inquiry, carrying out empirical  

research, and interviewing three gay men, the Wolfenden Committee   

released its Report in 1957.338 The Wolfenden Report recommended that:  

“Homosexual behaviour between consenting adults should no  

longer be a criminal offence... Unless a deliberate attempt is  

to be made by society, acting through the agency of the law,  

to equate the sphere of crime with that of sin, there must  

remain a realm of private morality and immorality which is, in  

brief and crude terms, not the law’s business.”339   

 

                                                           334 Graham Hughes, “Morals and the Criminal Law”, The Yale Law Journal, Vol.71 (1962).   335 Supra note 29.  336 Ibid.   337 Ibid.  338 Ibid.    339 Supra note 29, at paras 61 and 62.

420

PART K   

158    

The Wolfenden Report stated that “it is not the purpose of law to intervene in  

the private lives of citizens, or to seek to enforce any particular pattern of  

behaviour…”340 The Wolfenden Report acknowledged that the law and public  

opinion have a close relationship with each other – the law ought to “follow  

behind public opinion” so that it garners the community support, while at the  

same time, the law must also fortify and lead public opinion.341 However, it   

made out a strong case for divorcing morality from criminal law and stated that  

- “moral conviction or instinctive feeling, however strong, is not a valid basis  

for overriding the individual’s privacy and for bringing within the ambit of the  

criminal law private sexual behaviour of this kind.”342 Stating that  

homosexuality is not a mental illness, the Wolfenden Report clarified that  

homosexuality is “a sexual propensity for persons of one’s own sex…[it] is a  

state or condition, and as such does not, and cannot, come within the purview  

of criminal law.”343    

 

133 Lord Devlin, perturbed by the Wolfenden Report’s line of reasoning,  

framed questions on the issue of criminal law and morality:  

“1. Has society the right to pass judgments on all matters of  

morals?   

                                                           340 Ibid, at para 14.   341 Ibid, at para 16.  342 Ibid, at para 54.  343 Ibid, at para 18.

421

PART K   

159    

2. If society has the right to pass judgment, has it also the  

right to use the weapon of the law to enforce it?”344  

 

Devlin believed that society depends upon a common morality for its stability  

and existence.345 On the basis of this belief, Devlin answered the above  

questions in the affirmative, stating that – society has the right to pass  

judgments on all matters of morality and also the right to use law to enforce  

such morality.346  Devlin reasoned that society would disintegrate if a common  

morality was not observed. Therefore, society is justified in taking steps to  

preserve its morality as much as it preserves the government.347 Devlin  

proposed that the common morality or “collective judgment of the society”  

should be ascertained taking into consideration the “reasonable man.”348  

According to him, a reasonable man is an ordinary man whose judgment “may  

largely be a matter of feeling.”349  He added that if the reasonable man  

believed a practice to be immoral, and held this belief honestly and  

dispassionately, then for the purpose of law such practice should be  

considered immoral.350   

 

                                                           344 Sir Patrick Arthur Devlin, “The Enforcement Of Morals” Oxford University Press (1959) at page 9.  345 Supra note 334, at page 662.   346 Animesh Sharma, “Section 377: No Jurisprudential Basis.” Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 43 (2008) at  

pages 12-14.  347 Supra note 344.  348 Ibid.   349 Ibid.  350 Ibid.

422

PART K   

160    

134 Countering Devlin’s theory, Hart argued that society is not held together  

by a common morality, for, after all, it is not a hive mind or a monolith,  

governed by a singular set of morals and principles.351 Hart rebutted Devlin’s  

argument in the following way:   

“…apart from one vague reference to ‘history’ showing the  

‘the loosening of moral bonds is often the first stage of  

disintegration,’ no evidence is produced to show that  

deviation from accepted sexual morality, even by adults in  

private is something which, like treason, threatens the  

existence of society. No reputable historian has maintained  

this thesis, and there is indeed much evidence against  

it…Lord Devlin’s belief in it [that homosexuality is a cause of  

societal disintegration], and his apparent indifference to the  

question of evidence, are at points traceable to an  

undiscussed assumption. This is that all morality – sexual  

morality together with the morality that forbids acts injurious to  

others such as killing, stealing, and dishonesty -- forms a  

single seamless web, so that those who deviate from any part  

are likely to perhaps bound to deviate from the whole. It is of  

course clear (and one of the oldest insights of political theory)  

that society could not exist without a morality which mirrored  

and supplemented the law’s proscription of conduct injurious  

to others. But there is again no evidence to support, and  

much to refute, the theory that those who deviate from  

conventional sexual morality are in other ways hostile to  

society.”352   

 

Despite countering Devlin, Hart was not completely opposed to a relationship  

between law and morality, and in fact, he emphasised that the two are closely  

related:  

                                                           351 Supra note 346, at pages 12-14.  352 Hart, H. L. A, “The Changing Sense of Morality” In Political Thought (Michael Rosen and Jonathan Wolff eds.),  

Oxford University Press (1999) at pages 140-141.  

423

PART K   

161    

“The law of every modem state shows at a thousand points  

the influence of both the accepted social morality and wider  

moral ideals. These influences enter into law either abruptly  

and avowedly through legislation, or silently and piecemeal  

through the judicial process…The further ways in which law  

mirrors morality are myriad, and still insufficiently studied:  

statutes may be a mere legal shell and demand by their  

express terms to be filled out with the aid of moral principles;  

the range of enforceable contracts may be limited by  

reference to conceptions of morality and fair- ness; liability for  

both civil and criminal wrongs may be adjusted to prevailing  

views of moral responsibility.” 353    

 

  

However, unlike Devlin, Hart did not propose that morality is a necessary  

condition for the validity of law.354 Hart argued, in summary, that “law is  

morally relevant,” but “not morally conclusive.”355 Hart vehemently disagreed  

with Devlin's view that if laws are not based on some collective morality and  

enacted to buttress that morality, society will disintegrate.356 Hart draws this  

distinction by conceding that certain sexual acts (including homosexual acts)  

were considered ‘immoral’ by mainstream Western society but adding that  

private sexual acts are an issue of “private morality” over which society has no  

interest and the law, no control.357  

 

Hart further expounded his warning about the imposition of majoritarian  

morals, propounding that “[l]t is fatally easy to confuse the democratic                                                              353 H.L.A. Hart, Law, Liberty And Morality (1979).  354 William Starr, “Law and Morality in H.L.A. Hart’s Legal Philosophy”, Marquette Law Review, Vol. 67 (1984).  355 Ibid.   356 Supra note 352.  357 Peter August Bittlinger, “Government enforcement of morality: a critical analysis of the Devlin-Hart controversy”,  

Doctoral Dissertations 1896-February 2014 (1975) at pages 69-70.  

424

PART K   

162    

principle that power should be in the hands of the majority with the utterly  

different claim that the majority, with power in their hands, need respect no  

limits”358:  

“Whatever other arguments there may be for the enforcement  

of morality, no one should think even when popular morality is  

supported by an “overwhelming majority” or marked by  

widespread "intolerance, indignation, and disgust" that loyalty  

to democratic principles requires him to admit that its  

imposition on a minority is justified.”359   

 

In this way, Hart avoided the specious generalization that the law must be  

severely quarantined from morality but still made it clear that laws like Section  

377, which impose a majoritarian view of right and wrong upon a minority in  

order to protect societal cohesion, are jurisprudentially and democratically  

impermissible.   

 

Bentham had a different view on morality and weighed morality against  

utilitarian principles. Bentham argued that if the punishment is not utilitarian  

(i.e. does not serve as a deterrent, is unprofitable, or unnecessary), the  

‘immoral’ action would have to go unpunished.360  He opined that legislators  

should not be overly swayed by the society’s morality:   

                                                           358 Ibid at page 91.  359 Ibid at page 93.  360 Supra note 334.  

425

PART K   

163    

“The strength of their prejudice is the measure of the  

indulgence which should be granted to it…The legislator  

ought to yield to the violence of a current which carries away  

everything that obstructs it.   

But ought the legislator to be a slave to the fancies of those  

whom he governs? No. Between an imprudent opposition and  

a servile compliance, there is a middle path, honourable and  

safe.”361     

 

In other words, it appears that Bentham argued that the morality of the people  

ought not be ignored in creating laws but also must not become their  

unchecked fount. And if prejudicial moralities arise from the people, they  

should not be unthinkingly and permanently cemented into the law, but rather  

addressed and conquered.  

 

John Stuart Mill also made a strong argument against popular morality being  

codified into laws. He argued that ‘disgust’ cannot be classified as harm, and  

those “who consider as an injury to themselves any conduct which they have  

a distaste for”, cannot dictate the actions of others merely because such  

actions contradict their own beliefs or views.362 Mill believed that society is not  

the right judge when dealing with the question of when to interfere in conduct  

                                                           361 Ibid.  362 Supra note 325.

426

PART K   

164    

that is purely personal, and that when society does interfere, “the odds are  

that it interferes wrongly and in the wrong place.”363  

 

135 Christopher R Leslie points out the dangers of letting morality creep into  

law:  

“Current generations enshrine their morality by passing laws  

and perpetuate their prejudices by handing these laws down  

to their children. Soon, statutes take on lives of their own, and  

their very existence justifies their premises and consequent  

implications. The underlying premises of ancient laws are  

rarely discussed, let alone scrutinized.”364  

 

Leslie further adds that “sodomy laws do not merely express societal  

disapproval; they go much further by creating a criminal class”365:   

“Sodomy laws are kept on the books, even though state  

governments do not intend to actively enforce them, because  

the laws  send a message to society that homosexuality is  

unacceptable. Even without actual criminal prosecution, the  

laws carry meaning… In short, the primary importance of  

sodomy laws today is the government’s message to diminish  

the societal status of gay men and lesbians.”366   

  

136 A broad analysis of criminal theory points to the general conclusion that  

criminologists and legal philosophers have long been in agreement about one  

basic characteristic of crime: that it should injure a third person or the society.  

                                                           363 Ibid.    364 Christopher. R. Leslie, “Creating criminals: The Injuries Inflicted by “Unenforced” Sodomy Laws”, Harvard Civil  

Rights and Civil Liberties Law Review, Vol. 35 (2000).  365 Ibid, at pages 103-181.   366 Ibid.  

427

PART K   

165    

An element of larger public interest emerges as the crux of crime. The  

conduct which Section 377 criminalises voluntary ‘carnal intercourse against  

the order of nature’ with a man or woman, inter alia – pertains solely to acts  

between consenting adults. Such conduct is purely private, or as Mill would  

call it, “self-regarding,” and is neither capable of causing injury to someone  

else nor does it pose a threat to the stability and security of society. Once the  

factor of consent is established, the question of such conduct causing any  

injury, does not arise.  

  

Although Section 377 prima facie appears to criminalise certain acts or  

conduct, it creates a class of criminals, consisting of individuals who engage  

in consensual sexual activity. It typecasts LGBTQ individuals as sex-

offenders, categorising their consensual conduct on par with sexual offences  

like rape and child molestation. Section 377 not only criminalises acts  

(consensual sexual conduct between adults) which should not constitute  

crime, but also stigmatises and condemns LGBTQ individuals in society.   

 

137 We are aware of the perils of allowing morality to dictate the terms of  

criminal law. If a single, homogenous morality is carved out for a society, it will  

undoubtedly have the effect of hegemonizing or ‘othering’ the morality of  

minorities. The LGBTQ community has been a victim of the pre-dominant

428

PART L   

166    

 

(Victorian) morality which prevailed at the time when the Indian Penal Code  

was drafted and enacted. Therefore, we are inclined to observe that it is  

constitutional morality, and not mainstream views about sexual morality, which  

should be the driving factor in determining the validity of Section 377.   

 

L Constitutional morality   

138 With the attainment of independence on 15 August 1947, Indians were  

finally free to shape their own destiny.367 The destiny was to be shaped  

through a written Constitution. Constitutions are scripts in which people  

inscribe the text of their professed collective destiny. They write down who  

they think they are, what they want to be, and the principles that will guide  

their interacting along that path in the future.368 The Constitution of India was  

burdened with the challenge of “drawing a curtain on the past”369 of social  

inequality and prejudices. Those who led India to freedom established into the  

Constitution the ideals and vision of a vibrant equitable society. The framing of  

India’s Constitution was a medium of liberating the society by initiating the  

process of establishing and promoting the shared values of liberty, equality

                                                           367 Jawaharlal Nehru, “Tryst with Destiny”, address to the Constituent Assembly of India, delivered on 14-15 August  

1947.  368 Uday S. Mehta, “Constitutionalism”, In The Oxford Companion to Politics in India (Niraja Gopal Jayal and Pratap  

Bhanu Mehta eds.), Oxford University Press (2010), at  page 15.  369 Ibid, at page 16.

429

PART L   

167    

and fraternity. Throughout history, socio-cultural revolts, anti-discrimination  

assertions, movements, literature and leaders have worked at socializing  

people away from supremacist thought and towards an egalitarian existence.  

The Indian Constitution is an expression of these assertions. It was an attempt  

to reverse the socializing of prejudice, discrimination, and power hegemony in  

a disjointed society. All citizens were to be free from coercion or restriction by  

the state, or by society privately.370 Liberty was no longer to remain the  

privilege of the few. The judgment in Puttaswamy highlights the commitment  

of the constitution makers, thus:   

“The vision of the founding fathers was enriched by the  

histories of suffering of those who suffered oppression and a  

violation of dignity both here and elsewhere.”  

 

139 Understanding the vision of India at a time when there was little else  

older than that vision, is of paramount importance for the reason that though  

the people may not have played any role in the actual framing of the  

Constitution, the Preamble professes that the Constitution has been adopted  

by the people themselves. Constitutional historian Granville Austin has said  

that the Indian Constitution is essentially a social document.371 The Indian  

Constitution does not provide merely a framework of governance. It embodies  

a vision. It is goal-oriented and its purpose is to bring about a social  

                                                           370 Granville Austin, The Indian Constitution: Cornerstone of a Nation, Oxford University Press (1966), at page 65.  371 Ibid, at page 63.

430

PART L   

168    

transformation in the country. It represents the aspirations of its framers. The  

democratic Constitution of India embodies provisions which are value-based.  

 

140 During the framing of the Constitution, it was realized by the members  

of the Constituent Assembly that there was a wide gap between constitutional  

precept and reality. The draftspersons were clear that the imbibing of new  

constitutional values by the population at large would take some time. Society  

was not going to change overnight. Dr Ambedkar remarked in the Constituent  

Assembly:  

“Democracy in India is only a top-dressing on an Indian soil,  

which is essentially undemocratic.”  

 

141 The values of a democracy require years of practice, effort, and  

experience to make the society work with those values. Similar is the position  

of non-discrimination, equality, fraternity and secularism. While the  

Constitution guarantees equality before the law and equal protection of the  

law, it was felt that the realization of the constitutional vision requires the  

existence of a commitment to that vision. Dr Ambedkar described this  

commitment to be the presence of constitutional morality among the members  

of the society. The conception of constitutional morality is different from that of  

public or societal morality. Under a regime of public morality, the conduct of

431

PART L   

169    

society is determined by popular perceptions existent in society. The  

continuance of certain symbols, labels, names or body shapes determine the  

notions, sentiments and mental attitudes of the people towards individuals and  

things.372 Constitutional morality determines the mental attitude towards  

individuals and issues by the text and spirit of the Constitution. It requires that  

the rights of an individual ought not to be prejudiced by popular notions of  

society. It assumes that citizens would respect the vision of the framers of the  

Constitution and would conduct themselves in a way which furthers that  

vision. Constitutional morality reflects that the ideal of justice is an overriding  

factor in the struggle for existence over any other notion of social acceptance.  

It builds and protects the foundations of a democracy, without which any  

nation will crack under its fissures. For this reason, constitutional morality has  

to be imbibed by the citizens consistently and continuously. Society must  

always bear in mind what Dr Ambedkar observed before the Constituent  

Assembly:  

“Constitutional morality is not a natural sentiment. It has to be  

cultivated. We must realize that our people have yet to learn  

it.”   

 

                                                           372 Babasaheb.R. Ambedkar, Annihilation of Caste, Navayana Publishing (2014); See also Martha C. Nussbaum,  

“Disgust or Equality? Sexual Orientation and Indian Law”, Journal of Indian Law and Society, Vol. 6 (2010).

432

PART L   

170    

142 In the decision in Government of NCT of Delhi v. Union of India373,  

the Constitution Bench of this Court dealt with the constitutive elements of  

constitutional morality which govern the working of a democratic system and  

representative form of government. Constitutional morality was described as  

founded on a “constitutional culture”, which requires the “existence of  

sentiments and dedication for realizing a social transformation which the  

Indian Constitution seeks to attain.” This Court held thus:  

“If the moral values of our .Constitution were not upheld at  

every stage, the text of the Constitution may not be enough to  

protect its democratic values.”  

 

This Court held that constitutional morality acts a check against the “tyranny of  

the majority” and as a “threshold against an upsurge in mob rule.” It was held  

to be a balance against popular public morality.  

 

143 Constitutional morality requires in a democracy the assurance of certain  

minimum rights, which are essential for free existence to every member of  

society. The Preamble to the Constitution recognises these rights as “Liberty  

of thought, expression, belief, faith and worship” and “Equality of status and of  

opportunity.” Constitutional morality is the guarantee which seeks that all  

inequality is eliminated from the social structure and each individual is  

                                                           373 2018 (8) SCALE 72

433

PART L   

171    

assured of the means for the enforcement of the rights guaranteed.  

Constitutional morality leans towards making Indian democracy vibrant by  

infusing a spirit of brotherhood amongst a heterogeneous population,  

belonging to different classes, races, religions, cultures, castes and sections.  

Constitutional morality cannot, however, be nurtured unless, as recognised by  

the Preamble, there exists fraternity, which assures and maintains the dignity  

of each individual. In his famous, yet undelivered speech titled “Annihilation of  

Caste” (which has been later published as a book), Dr Ambedkar described  

‘fraternity’ as “primarily a mode of associated living, of conjoint communicated  

experience” and “essentially an attitude of respect and reverence towards  

fellow men.”374 He remarked:   

“An ideal society should be mobile, should be full of channels  for conveying a change taking place in one part to other parts.  In an ideal society there should be many interests consciously  communicated and shared. There should be varied and free  points of contact with other modes of association. In other  words there must be social endosmosis. This is fraternity,  which is only another name for democracy.”  

   

In his last address to the Constituent Assembly, he defined fraternity as “a  

sense of common brotherhood of all Indians.” As on the social and economic  

plane, Indian society was based on graded inequality, Dr Ambedkar had  

warned in clear terms:  

“Without fraternity, liberty [and] equality could not become a  

natural course of things. It would require a constable to  

                                                           374 Supra note 372, at para 14.2.

434

PART L   

172    

enforce them… Without fraternity equality and liberty will be  

no deeper than coats of paint.”375  

 

144 Constitutional morality requires that all the citizens need to have a  

closer look at, understand and imbibe the broad values of the Constitution,  

which are based on liberty, equality and fraternity. Constitutional morality is  

thus the guiding spirit to achieve the transformation which, above all, the  

Constitution seeks to achieve.  This acknowledgement carries a necessary  

implication: the process through which a society matures and imbibes  

constitutional morality is gradual, perhaps interminably so. Hence,  

constitutional courts are entrusted with the duty to act as external facilitators  

and to be a vigilant safeguard against excesses of state power and  

democratic concentration of power. This Court, being the highest  

constitutional court, has the responsibility to monitor the preservation of  

constitutional morality as an incident of fostering conditions for human dignity  

and liberty to flourish. Popular public morality cannot affect the decisions of  

this Court. Lord Neuberger (of the UK Supreme Court) has aptly observed:  

“[W]e must always remember that Parliament has democratic  

legitimacy – but that has disadvantages as well as  

advantages. The need to offer oneself for re-election  

sometimes makes it hard to make unpopular, but correct,  

decisions. At times it can be an advantage to have an  

                                                           375 Constituent Assembly Debates (25 November 1949).

435

PART L   

173    

independent body of people who do not have to worry about  

short term popularity.”376  

 

The flourishing of a constitutional order requires not only the institutional  

leadership of constitutional courts, but also the responsive participation of the  

citizenry.377 Constitutional morality is a pursuit of this responsive participation.  

The Supreme Court cannot afford to denude itself of its leadership as an  

institution in expounding constitutional values. Any loss of its authority will  

imperil democracy itself.  

 

145 The question of morality has been central to the concerns around  

homosexuality and the rights of LGBT individuals. Opponents – including  

those of the intervenors who launched a diatribe in the course of hearing –  

claim that homosexuality is against popular culture and is thus unacceptable in  

Indian society. While dealing with the constitutionality of Section 377 of the  

Indian Penal Code, the Delhi High Court in Naz Foundation had held:  

“Thus popular morality or public disapproval of certain acts is  

not a valid justification for restriction of the fundamental rights  

under Article 21. Popular morality, as distinct from a  

constitutional morality derived from constitutional values, is  

based on shifting and subjecting notions of right and wrong. If  

there is any type of “morality” that can pass the test of  

compelling state interest, it must be “constitutional” morality  

                                                           376  Lord Neuberger, “UK Supreme Court decisions on private and commercial law: The role of public policy and  

public interest”, Centre for Commercial Law Studies Conference (2015).  377  Marc Galanter, “Fifty Years on”, in BN Kirpal et al, Supreme but Not Infallible: Essays in Honour of the Supreme  

Court of India, Oxford University Press (2000), at page 57.

436

PART L   

174    

and not public morality… In our scheme of things,  

constitutional morality must outweigh the argument of public  

morality, even if it be the majoritarian view.”  

 

The invocation of constitutional morality must be seen as an extension of Dr  

Ambedkar’s formulation of social reform and constitutional transformation.  

Highlighting the significance of individual rights in social transformation, he  

had observed:  

“The assertion by the individual of his own opinions and  

beliefs, his own independence and interest—over and against  

group standards, group authority, and group interests—is the  

beginning of all reform. But whether the reform will continue  

depends upon what scope the group affords for such  

individual assertion.”378  

  

After the enactment of the Constitution, every individual assertion of rights is  

to be governed by the principles of the Constitution, by its text and spirit. The  

Constitution assures to every individual the right to lead a dignified life. It  

prohibits discrimination within society. It is for this reason that constitutional  

morality requires this court to issue a declaration - which we now do - that  

LGBT individuals are equal citizens of India, that they cannot be discriminated  

against and that they have a right to express themselves through their  

intimate choices. In upholding constitutional morality, we affirm that  the  

protection of the rights of LGBT individuals are not only about guaranteeing a  

                                                           378 Supra note 373, at para 12.1.

437

PART L   

175    

minority their rightful place in the constitutional scheme, but that we equally  

speak of the vision of the kind of country we want to live in and of what it  

means for the majority.379 The nine-judge Bench of this Court in Puttaswamy  

had held in clear terms that discrimination against an individual on the basis of  

sexual orientation is deeply offensive to the dignity and self-worth of the  

individual. The Bench held:  

“The purpose of elevating certain rights to the stature of  

guaranteed fundamental rights is to insulate their exercise  

from the disdain of majorities, whether legislative or popular.  

The guarantee of constitutional rights does not depend upon  

their exercise being favourably regarded by majoritarian  

opinion. The test of popular acceptance does not furnish a  

valid basis to disregard rights which are conferred with the  

sanctity of constitutional protection. Discrete and insular  

minorities face grave dangers of discrimination for the simple  

reason that their views, beliefs or way of life does not accord  

with the ‘mainstream’. Yet in a democratic Constitution  

founded on the rule of law, their rights are as sacred as those  

conferred on other citizens to protect their freedoms and  

liberties.”  

 

Constitutional morality will impact upon any law which deprives the LGBT  

individuals of their entitlement to a full and equal citizenship. After the  

Constitution came into force, no law can be divorced from constitutional  

morality. Society cannot dictate the expression of sexuality between  

consenting adults. That is a private affair. Constitutional morality will

                                                           379 Supra note 41.  

438

PART M  

176    

supersede any culture or tradition.   

The interpretation of a right in a matter of decriminalisation and beyond must  

be determined by the norms of the Constitution.   

 

146 LGBT individuals living under the threats of conformity grounded in  

cultural morality have been denied a basic human existence. They have been  

stereotyped and prejudiced. Constitutional morality requires this Court not to  

turn a blind eye to their right to an equal participation of citizenship and an  

equal enjoyment of living.  Constitutional morality requires that this Court must  

act as a counter majoritarian institution which discharges the responsibility of  

protecting constitutionally entrenched rights, regardless of what the majority  

may believe.380 Constitutional morality must turn into a habit of citizens. By  

respecting the dignity of LGBT individuals, this Court is only fulfilling the  

foundational promises of our Constitution.  

 

M In summation : transformative constitutionalism   

 

147 This case has required a decision on whether Section 377 of the Penal  

Code fulfills constitutional standards in penalising consensual sexual conduct  

between adults of the same sex.  We hold and declare that in penalising such  

                                                           380 Ibid.  

439

PART M  

177    

sexual conduct, the statutory provision violates the constitutional guarantees  

of liberty and equality.  It denudes members of the LGBT communities of their  

constitutional right to lead fulfilling lives.  In its application to adults of the  

same sex engaged in consensual sexual behaviour, it violates the  

constitutional guarantee of the right to life and to the equal protection of law.    

 

148 Sexual orientation is integral to the identity of the members of the LGBT  

communities. It is intrinsic to their dignity, inseparable from their autonomy  

and at the heart of their privacy.  Section 377 is founded on moral notions  

which are an anathema to a constitutional order in which liberty must trump  

over stereotypes and prevail over the mainstreaming of culture.  Our  

Constitution, above all, is an essay in the acceptance of diversity. It is founded  

on a vision of an inclusive society which accommodates plural ways of life.  

 

149 The impact of Section 377 has travelled far beyond criminalising certain  

acts. The presence of the provision on the statute book has reinforced  

stereotypes about sexual orientation. It has lent the authority of the state to  

the suppression of identities. The fear of persecution has led to the closeting  

of same sex relationships. A penal provision has reinforced societal disdain.   

440

PART M  

178    

150 Sexual and gender based minorities cannot live in fear, if the  

Constitution has to have meaning for them on even terms.  In its quest for  

equality and the equal protection of the law, the Constitution guarantees to  

them an equal citizenship.  In de-criminalising such conduct, the values of the  

Constitution assure to the LGBT community the ability to lead a life of freedom  

from fear and to find fulfilment in intimate choices.  

 

151 The choice of a partner, the desire for personal intimacy and the  

yearning to find love and fulfilment in human relationships have a universal  

appeal, straddling age and time.  In protecting consensual intimacies, the  

Constitution adopts a simple principle: the state has no business to intrude  

into these personal matters.  Nor can societal notions of heteronormativity  

regulate constitutional liberties based on sexual orientation.    

 

152 This reference to the Constitution Bench is about the validity of Section  

377 in its application to consensual sexual conduct between adults of the  

same sex. The constitutional principles which we have invoked to determine  

the outcome address the origins of the rights claimed and the source of their  

protection. In their range and content, those principles address issues broader  

than the acts which the statute penalises. Resilient and universal as they are,  

these constitutional values must enure with a mark of permanence.  

441

PART M  

179    

153 Above all, this case has had great deal to say on the dialogue about the  

transformative power of the Constitution. In addressing LGBT rights, the  

Constitution speaks – as well – to the rest of society. In recognising the rights  

of the LGBT community, the Constitution asserts itself as a text for  

governance which promotes true equality. It does so by questioning prevailing  

notions about the dominance of sexes and genders.  In its transformational  

role, the Constitution directs our attention to resolving the polarities of sex and  

binarities of gender. In dealing with these issues we confront much that  

polarises our society. Our ability to survive as a free society will depend upon  

whether constitutional values can prevail over the impulses of the time.    

  

154 A hundred and fifty eight years is too long a period for the LGBT  

community to suffer the indignities of denial. That it has taken sixty eight years  

even after the advent of the Constitution is a sobering reminder of the  

unfinished task which lies ahead. It is also a time to invoke the transformative  

power of the Constitution.  

 

155 The ability of a society to acknowledge the injustices which it has  

perpetuated is a mark of its evolution. In the process of remedying wrongs  

under a regime of constitutional remedies, recrimination gives way to  

restitution, diatribes pave the way for dialogue and healing replaces the hate

442

PART M  

180    

of a community. For those who have been oppressed, justice under a regime  

committed to human freedom, has the power to transform lives. In addressing  

the causes of oppression and injustice, society transforms itself. The  

Constitution has within it the ability to produce a social catharsis. The  

importance of this case lies in telling us that reverberations of how we address  

social conflict in our times will travel far beyond the narrow alleys in which  

they are explored.      

  

156 We hold and declare that:  

(i) Section 377 of the Penal Code, in so far as it criminalises consensual  

sexual conduct between adults of the same sex, is unconstitutional;  

(ii) Members of the LGBT community are entitled, as all other citizens, to  

the full range of constitutional rights including the liberties protected by  

the Constitution;  

(iii) The choice of whom to partner, the ability to find fulfilment in sexual  

intimacies and the right not to be subjected to discriminatory behaviour  

are intrinsic to the constitutional protection of sexual orientation;  

(iv) Members of the LGBT community are entitled to the benefit of an equal  

citizenship, without discrimination, and to the equal protection of law;  

and

443

PART M  

181    

(v) The decision in Koushal stands overruled.       

 

Acknowledgment   

Before concluding, I acknowledge the efforts of counsel for the petitioners and  

intervenors who appeared in this case – Mr Mukul Rohatgi, Mr Arvind Datar,  

Mr Ashok Desai, Mr Anand Grover, Mr Shyam Divan, Mr CU Singh and Mr  

Krishnan Venugopal, Senior Counsel; and Mr Saurabh Kirpal, Dr Menaka  

Guruswamy and Ms Arundhati Katju, and Ms Jayna Kothari, learned Counsel.  

Their erudition has enabled us to absorb, as we reflected and wrote. Mr  

Tushar Mehta, learned Additional Solicitor General appeared for the Union of  

India. We acknowledge the assistance rendered by the counsel for the  

intervenors who opposed the petitioners.    

         

…….....….............................................J                [Dr Dhananjaya Y Chandrachud]  

        New Delhi;  September 06, 2018.  

444

1    

REPORTABLE    

IN THE SUPREME COURT OF INDIA  

CRIMINAL ORIGINAL JURISDICTION  

WRIT PETITION (CRL.) NO. 76 OF 2016  

Navtej Singh Johar and Others                                 …Petitioners  

VERSUS    

Union of India Ministry of Law   

and Justice Secretary                          …Respondent  

WITH  

W.P. (C) NO. 572/2016  

W.P. (CRL.) NO. 88/2018  

W.P. (CRL.) NO. 100/2018  

W.P. (CRL.) NO. 101/2018  

W.P. (CRL.) NO. 121/2018  

 

J U D G E M E N T  

INDU MALHOTRA, J.    

1. I have had the advantage of reading the opinions prepared by  

the Hon’ble Chief Justice, and my brother Judges Justice

445

2    

Nariman and Justice Chandrachud. The Judgments have dealt  

in-depth with the various issues that are required to be  

examined by this Bench, to answer the reference.  

2. The present batch of Writ Petitions have been filed to challenge  

the constitutional validity of Section 377 of the Indian Penal  

Code, 1860 (“IPC”) on the specific ground that it criminalises  

consensual sexual intercourse between adult persons  

belonging to the same sex in private.   

3. The issue as to whether the decision in Suresh Kumar Koushal  

& Anr. v. Naz Foundation & Ors.1 requires re-consideration was  

referred to the Constitution Bench vide Order dated 8th  

January, 2018.  

4. The Petitioners have inter alia submitted that sexual  

expression and intimacy between consenting adults of the  

same sex in private ought to receive protection under Part III of  

the Constitution, as sexuality lies at the core of a human  

being’s innate identity. Section 377 inasmuch as it  

criminalises consensual relationships between same sex  

couples is violative of the fundamental rights guaranteed by  

Articles 21, 19 and 14, in Part III of the Constitution.  

                                                           1 (2014) 1 SCC 1

446

3    

The principal contentions raised by the Petitioners during  

the course of hearing are:  

i. Fundamental rights are available to LGBT persons  

regardless of the fact that they constitute a minority.  

ii. Section 377 is violative of Article 14 being wholly  

arbitrary, vague, and has an unlawful objective.  

iii. Section 377 penalises a person on the basis of their  

sexual orientation, and is hence discriminatory under  

Article 15.  

iv. Section 377 violates the right to life and liberty  

guaranteed by Article 21 which encompasses all aspects  

of the right to live with dignity, the right to privacy, and  

the right to autonomy and self-determination with respect  

to the most intimate decisions of a human being.  

5. During the course of hearing, the Union of India tendered an  

Affidavit dated 11th July, 2018 wherein it was submitted that  

with respect to the Constitutional validity of Section 377  

insofar as it applies to consensual acts of adults in private, the  

Union of India would leave the said question to the wisdom of  

this Hon’ble Court.

447

4    

However, if the Court is to decide and examine any issue  

other than the Constitutional validity of Section 377, or  

construe any other right in favour of the LGBT community, the  

Union of India would like to file a detailed Affidavit as that  

would have far-reaching and wide ramifications, not  

contemplated by the reference.  

6. LEGISLATIVE BACKGROUND  

6.1. The legal treatises Fleta and Britton, which date back to  

1290 and 1300 respectively, documented prevailing laws  

in England at the time. These treatises made references  

to sodomy as a crime.2  

6.2. The Buggery Act, 1533 was re-enacted in 1563 during  

the regime of Queen Elizabeth I, which penalized acts of  

sodomy by hanging.   

In 1861, death penalty for buggery was abolished in  

England and Wales. However, it remained a crime “not to  

be mentioned by Christians”.  

6.3. The 1861 Act became the charter for enactments framed  

in the colonies of Great Britain.  

                                                           2 John Boswell, Christianity, Social Tolerance, and Homosexuality: Gay People in Western  

Europe from the Beginning of the Christian Era to the Fourteenth Century (University of  Chicago Press, 1980), at p. 292

448

5    

6.4. The Marginal Note of Section 377, refers to “Unnatural  

Offences”. Section 377 reads as under:  

“377. Unnatural offences.— Whoever  voluntarily has carnal intercourse against the  order of nature with any man, woman or animal,  shall be punished with imprisonment for life, or  with imprisonment of either description for a term  which may extend to ten years, and shall also be  liable to fine.  

Explanation.—Penetration is sufficient to  constitute the carnal intercourse necessary to the  offence described in this section.”  

(emphasis supplied)  

6.5. Section 377 does not define “carnal intercourse against  

the order of nature”. Even though the provision is  

facially neutral, the Petitioners submit that the thrust of  

this provision has been to target the LGBT community in  

light of the colonial history of anti-sodomy laws, and  

penalise what was perceived to be ‘deviant’ or ‘perverse’  

sexual behaviour.  

7. In the early 20th century, there were many psychiatric theories  

which regarded homosexuality as a form of psychopathology or  

developmental arrest.3 It was believed that normal  

development resulted in a child growing up to be a  

heterosexual adult, and that homosexuality was but a state of  

                                                           3 Report of the Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution, 1957, at para 30.

449

6    

arrested development.4 Homosexuality was treated as a  

disorder or mental illness, which was meted out with social  

ostracism and revulsion.  

8. Towards the end of the 20th century, this notion began to  

change, and the earlier theories gave way to a more  

enlightened perspective that characterized homosexuality as a  

normal and natural variant of human sexuality. Scientific  

studies indicated that human sexuality is complex and  

inherent.5  

Kurt Hiller in his speech delivered at the Second  

International Congress for Sexual Reform held at Copenhagen  

in 19286, stated:  

“Same-sex love is not a mockery of nature, but rather  nature at play…As Nietzsche expressed it in Daybreak,  Procreation is a frequently occurring accidental result of  one way of satisfying the sexual drive – it is neither its  goal nor its necessary consequence. The theory which  would make procreation the goal of sexuality is exposed  as hasty, simplistic and false by the phenomenon of  same-sex love alone. Nature’s laws, unlike the laws  formulated by the human mind, cannot be violated. The  assertion that a specific phenomenon of nature could  somehow be “contrary to nature” amounts to pure  absurdity…To belong, not to the rule, not to the norm,  but rather to the exception, to the minority, to the variety,  is neither a symptom of degeneration nor of pathology.”  

                                                           4 Benjamin J. Sadock et al., Kaplan and Sadock’s Comprehensive Textbook of Psychiatry   

(9th ed., 2009), at pp. 2060-89  5   Id  6 Great Speeches on Gay Rights (James Daley ed.; Dover Publications, 2010), at pp. 24-30

450

7    

(emphasis supplied)  

 

9. In 1957, the United Kingdom published the Wolfenden  

Committee Report (supra) which recognised how the anti-

sodomy laws had created an atmosphere for blackmail,  

harassment and violence against homosexuals. An extract of  

the findings of this Committee reads as under:  

“We have found it hard to decide whether the  

blackmailer’s primary weapon is the threat of disclosure  to the police, with attendant legal consequences, or the  threat of disclosure to the victim’s relatives, employers or  friends, with attendant social consequences. It may well  be that the latter is the more effective weapon, but it  may yet be true that it would lose much of its edge if the  social consequences were not associated with the  present legal position.”  

 

Pursuant to this Report, the House of Lords initiated  

legislation to de-criminalise homosexual acts done in private  

by consenting parties. The Sexual Offences Act, 1967 came to  

be passed in England which de-criminalised homosexual acts  

done in private, provided the parties had consented to it, and  

were above the age of 21.  

10. The trend of decriminalizing anti-sodomy laws world over  

has gained currency during the past few decades since such  

laws have been recognised to be violative of human rights. In

451

8    

2017, the International Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, Trans and  

Intersex Association noted in its Annual State Sponsored  

Homophobia Report7 that 124 countries no longer penalise  

homosexuality. The change in laws in these countries was  

given effect to, either through legislative amendments to the  

statutory enactments, or by way of court judgments.  

Relationships between same-sex couples have been  

increasingly accorded protection by States across the world. As  

per the aforesaid Report, a total of 24 countries now allow  

same-sex couples to marry, while 28 countries legally  

recognise partnerships between same-sex couples. Several  

countries have enacted enabling legislations which protect  

LGBT persons from discrimination, and allow them to adopt  

children.8 For instance, the United Kingdom now outlaws  

discrimination in employment, education, social protection  

and housing on the ground of sexual orientation. Marriage  

between same-sex couples have been recognised in England  

and Wales.  

                                                           7 Aengus Carroll And Lucas Ramón Mendos, Ilga Annual State Sponsored Homophobia  

Report 2017: A World Survey Of Sexual Orientation Laws: Criminalisation, Protection And  Recognition (12th Edition, 2017), at pp. 26-36  8 Id

452

9    

The British Prime Minister Theresa May in her speech at the  

Commonwealth Joint Forum on April 17, 2018 urged  

Commonwealth Nations to overhaul “outdated” anti-gay laws,  

and expressed regret regarding Britain’s role in introducing  

such laws.9 The relevant excerpt of her speech is extracted  

hereinbelow:  

“ Across the world, discriminatory laws made many  years ago continue to affect the lives of many people,  criminalising same-sex relations and failing to protect  women and girls.  I am all too aware that these laws were often put in  place by my own country. They were wrong then, and  they are wrong now. As the UK’s Prime Minister, I  deeply regret both the fact that such laws were  introduced, and the legacy of discrimination, violence  and even death that persists today. ”  

 

11. Section 377 has, however, remained in its original form in the  

IPC to date.  

12. JUDICIAL INTERPRETATION  

12.1. The essential ingredient required to constitute an offence  

under Section 377 is “carnal intercourse against the  

order of nature”, which is punishable with life  

imprisonment, or imprisonment of either description up  

                                                           9 Theresa May’s Speech at the Commonwealth Joint Forum Plenary available at  https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/pm-speaks-at-the-commonwealth-joint-forum-

plenary-17-april-2018

453

10    

to ten years. Section 377 applies irrespective of gender,  

age, or consent.  

12.2. The expression ‘carnal intercourse’ used in Section 377  

is distinct from ‘sexual intercourse’ which appears in  

Sections 375 and 497 of the IPC. The phrase “carnal  

intercourse against the order of nature” is not defined by  

Section 377, or in the Code.  

12.3. The term ‘carnal’ has been the subject matter of judicial  

interpretation in various decisions. According to the New  

International Webster’s Comprehensive Dictionary of the  

English Language10,  ‘carnal’ means:  

“1.Pertaining to the fleshly nature or to bodily  appetites.  

2. Sensual ; sexual.  3.Pertaining to the flesh or to the body; not  

spiritual; hence worldly.”    

12.4. The courts had earlier interpreted the term “carnal” to  

refer to acts which fall outside penile-vaginal  

intercourse, and were not for the purposes of  

procreation.  

                                                           10 The New International Webster’s Comprehensive Dictionary of the English Language  

(Deluxe Encyclopedic Edition, 1996)

454

11    

In Khanu v. Emperor11, the Sindh High Court was  

dealing with a case where the accused was found guilty  

of having committed Gomorrah coitus per os with a little  

child, and was convicted under Section 377. The Court  

held that the act of carnal intercourse was clearly  

against the order of nature, because the natural object of  

carnal intercourse is that there should be the possibility  

of conception of human beings, which in the case of  

coitus per os is impossible.  

The Lahore High Court in Khandu v. Emperor12 was  

dealing with a case wherein the accused had penetrated  

the nostril of a bullock with his penis. The Court, while  

relying on the decision of the Sindh High Court in Khanu  

v. Emperor (supra) held that the acts of the accused  

constituted coitus per os, were punishable under Section  

377.  

In Lohana Vasantlal Devchand & Ors v. State13 the  

Gujarat High Court convicted two accused under Section  

377 read with Section 511 of the IPC, on account of  

                                                           11 AIR 1925 Sind 286  12 AIR 1934 Lah 261 : 1934 Cri LJ 1096  13 AIR 1968 Guj 252

455

12    

having carnal intercourse per anus, and inserting the  

penis in the mouth of a young boy.  It was held that:   

“…words used (in Section 377) are quite  comprehensive and in my opinion, an act like the  present act (oral sex), which was an imitative act  of sexual intercourse for the purpose of his  satisfying the sexual appetite, would be an act  punishable under Section 377 of the Indian Penal  Code.”     

Later this Court in Fazal Rab Choudhary v. State of  

Bihar14 while reducing the sentence of the appellant who  

was convicted for having committed an offence on a  

young boy under Section 377 IPC, held that:  

“…The offence is one under Section 377 I.P.C.,  which implies sexual perversity. No force  appears to have been used. Neither the notions  of permissive society nor the fact that in some  countries homosexuality has ceased to be an  offence has influenced our thinking.”  

(emphasis supplied)    

The test for attracting penal provisions under Section  

377 changed over the years from non-procreative sexual  

acts in Khanu v. Emperor (supra), to imitative sexual  

intercourse like oral sex in Lohana Vasantlal Devchand  

& Ors. v. State (supra), to sexual perversity in Fazal Rab  

                                                           14 (1982) 3 SCC 9

456

13    

v. State of Bihar (supra). These cases referred to non-

consensual sexual intercourse by coercion.  

13. HOMOSEXUALITY – NOT AN ABERRATION BUT A VARIATION OF SEXUALITY  

13.1. Whilst a great deal of scientific research has examined  

possible genetic, hormonal, developmental,  

psychological, social and cultural influences on sexual  

orientation, no findings have conclusively linked sexual  

orientation to any one particular factor or factors. It is  

believed that one’s sexuality is the result of a complex  

interplay between nature and nurture.  

Sexual orientation is an innate attribute of one’s  

identity, and cannot be altered. Sexual orientation is not  

a matter of choice. It manifests in early adolescence.  

Homosexuality is a natural variant of human sexuality.  

The U.S. Supreme Court in Lawrence et al. v. Texas15  

relied upon the Brief of the Amici Curiae16  which stated:  

“Heterosexual and homosexual behavior are both  normal aspects of human sexuality. Both have  been documented in many different human  cultures and historical eras, and in a wide variety  of animal species. There is no consensus among  

                                                           15 539 U.S. 558 (2003)  16 Brief for the Amici Curiae American Psychological Association, American Psychiatric  

Association, National Association of Social Workers, and Texas Chapter of the National  

Association of Social Workers in Lawrence et al. v. Texas 539 U.S. 558(2003), available at  http://www.apa.org/about/offices/ogc/amicus/lawrence.pdf

457

14    

scientists about the exact reasons why an  individual develops a heterosexual, bisexual, or  homosexual orientation. According to current  scientific and professional understanding,  however, the core feelings and attractions that  form the basis for adult sexual orientation  typically emerge between middle childhood and  early adolescence. Moreover, these patterns of  sexual attraction generally arise without any prior  sexual experience. Most or many gay men and  lesbians experience little or no choice about their  sexual orientation.”  

(emphasis supplied)    

13.2. An article by K.K. Gulia and H.N. Mallick titled  

“Homosexuality: A Dilemma in Discourse”17 states:  

“In general, homosexuality as a sexual orientation  refers to an enduring pattern or disposition to  experience sexual, affectional, or romantic  attractions primarily to people of the same sex. It  also refers to an individual’s sense of personal  and social identity based on those attractions,  behaviours, expressing them, and membership in  a community of others who share them. It is a  condition in which one is attracted and drawn to  his/her own gender, which is evidenced by the  erotic and emotional involvement with members of  his/her own sex…  …In the course of the 20th century, homosexuality  became a subject of considerable study and  debate in western societies. It was predominantly  viewed as a disorder or mental illness. At that  time, emerged two major pioneering studies on  homosexuality carried out by Alfred Charles  Kinsey (1930) and Evelyn Hooker (1957)…This  empirical study of sexual behavior among  American adults revealed that a significant  

                                                           17 KK Gulia and HN Mallick, Homosexuality: a dilemma in discourse, 54 Indian Journal of  

Physiology and Pharmacology (2010), at pp. 5, 6 and 8

458

15    

number of participants were homosexuals. In this  study when people were asked directly if they  had engaged in homosexual relations, the  percentage of positive responses nearly doubled.  The result of this study became the widely  popularized Kinsey Scale of Sexuality. This scales  rates all individuals on a spectrum of sexuality,  ranging from 100% heterosexual to 100%  homosexual…”  

(emphasis supplied)    

13.3. The American Psychiatric Association in December 1973  

removed ‘homosexuality’ from the Diagnostic and  

Statistical Manual of Psychological Disorders, and  

opined that the manifestation of sexual attraction  

towards persons of the opposite sex, or same sex, is a  

natural condition.18  

13.4. The World Health Organization removed homosexuality  

from the list of diseases in the International  

Classification of Diseases in the publication of ICD-10 in  

1992.19  

                                                           18 Jack Drescher, Out of DSM: Depathologizing Homosexuality, 5(4) Behavioral Sciences  (2015), at p. 565  19 The ICD-10 classification of mental and behavioural disorders: clinical descriptions and  

diagnostic guidelines, World Health Organization, Geneva (1992) available at  

http://www.who.int/classifications/icd/en/bluebook.pdf

459

16    

13.5. In India, the Indian Psychiatric Society has also opined  

that sexual orientation is not a psychiatric disorder.20 It  

was noted that:  

“…there is no scientific evidence that sexual  orientation can be altered by any treatment and  that any such attempts may in fact lead to low  self-esteem and stigmatization of the person.”    

13.6. It is relevant to note that under Section 3 of the Mental  

Healthcare Act, 2017, determination of what constitutes  

a “mental illness” has to be done in accordance with  

nationally and internationally accepted medical  

standards, including the latest edition of the  

International Classification of Disease of the World  

Health Organisation.  

14. SECTION 377 IF APPLIED TO CONSENTING ADULTS IS VIOLATIVE OF  

ARTICLE 14  

14.1. One of the main contentions raised by the Petitioners to  

challenge the Constitutional validity of Section 377 is  

founded on Article 14 of the Constitution. Article 14  

enshrines the principle of equality as a fundamental  

right, and mandates that the State shall not deny to any  

                                                           20  Indian Psychiatry Society: "Position statement on Homosexuality"  

IPS/Statement/02/07/2018 available at  http://www.indianpsychiatricsociety.org/upload_images/imp_download_files/15311250

54_1.pdf

460

17    

person equality before the law, or the equal protection of  

the laws within the territory of India. It recognizes and  

guarantees the right of equal treatment to all persons in  

this country.  

It is contended that Section 377 discriminates against  

adults of the same gender, from having a consensual  

sexual relationship in private, by treating it as a penal  

offence, and hence is violative of Article 14.  

14.2. The twin-test of classification under Article 14 provides  

that:  

(i) there should be a reasonable classification based  

on intelligible differentia; and,  

(ii) this classification should have a rational nexus  

with the objective sought to be achieved.  

14.3. Section 377 operates in a vastly different manner for two  

classes of persons based on their “sexual orientation” i.e.  

the LGBT persons and heterosexual persons. Section 377  

penalises all forms of non penile-vaginal intercourse. In  

effect, voluntary consensual relationships between LGBT  

persons are criminalised in totality.

461

18    

The import and effect of Section 377 is that while a  

consensual heterosexual relationship is permissible, a  

consensual relationship between LGBT persons is  

considered to be ‘carnal’, and against the order of nature.  

Section 377 creates an artificial dichotomy. The  

natural or innate sexual orientation of a person cannot  

be a ground for discrimination. Where a legislation  

discriminates on the basis of an intrinsic and core trait  

of an individual, it cannot form a reasonable  

classification based on an intelligible differentia.  

14.4. In National Legal Services Authority v. Union of India &  

Ors.21 this Court granted equal protection of laws to  

transgender persons. There is therefore no justification  

to deny the same to LGBT persons.  

14.5. A person’s sexual orientation is intrinsic to their being. It  

is connected with their individuality, and identity. A  

classification which discriminates between persons  

based on their innate nature, would be violative of their  

fundamental rights, and cannot withstand the test of  

constitutional morality.  

                                                           21 (2014) 5 SCC 438

462

19    

14.6. In contemporary civilised jurisprudence, with States  

increasingly recognising the status of same-sex  

relationships, it would be retrograde to describe such  

relationships as being ‘perverse’, ‘deviant’, or ‘unnatural’.  

14.7. Section 375 defines the offence of rape. It provides for  

penetrative acts which if performed by a man against a  

woman without her consent, or by obtaining her consent  

under duress, would amount to rape. Penetrative acts  

(after the 2013 Amendment) include anal and oral sex.   

The necessary implication which can be drawn from  

the amended provision is that if such penetrative acts  

are done with the consent of the woman they are not  

punishable under Section 375.   

While Section 375 permits consensual penetrative acts  

(the definition of ‘penetration’ includes oral and anal  

sex), Section 377 makes the same acts of penetration  

punishable irrespective of consent. This creates a  

dichotomy in the law.  

14.8. The proscription of a consensual sexual relationship  

under Section 377 is not founded on any known or  

rational criteria. Sexual expression and intimacy of a

463

20    

consensual nature, between adults in private, cannot be  

treated as “carnal intercourse against the order of  

nature”.  

14.9. Emphasising on the second part of Article 14 which  

enjoins the State to provide equal protection of laws to all  

persons, Nariman, J. in his concurring opinion in  

Shayara Bano v. Union of India & Ors.22 elucidated on the  

doctrine of manifest arbitrariness as a facet of Article 14.  

Apart from the conventional twin-tests of classification  

discussed in the preceding paragraphs, a legislation, or  

part thereof, can also be struck down under Article 14 on  

the ground that it is manifestly arbitrary. It would be  

instructive to refer to the following passage from the  

judgment of this Court in Shayara Bano v. Union of India  

& Ors. (supra):  

“101…Manifest arbitrariness, therefore, must be  something done by the legislature capriciously,  irrationally and/or without adequate determining  principle. Also, when something is done which is  excessive and disproportionate, such legislation  would be manifestly arbitrary.”    

Section 377 insofar as it criminalises consensual  

sexual acts between adults in private, is not based on  

                                                           22 (2017) 9 SCC 1

464

21    

any sound or rational principle, since the basis of  

criminalisation is the “sexual orientation” of a person,  

over which one has “little or no choice”.  

Further, the phrase “carnal intercourse against the  

order of nature” in Section 377 as a determining  

principle in a penal provision, is too open-ended, giving  

way to the scope for misuse against members of the  

LGBT community.  

Thus, apart from not satisfying the twin-test under  

Article 14, Section 377 is also manifestly arbitrary, and  

hence violative of Article 14 of the Constitution.   

15. SECTION 377 IS VIOLATIVE OF ARTICLE 15  

Article 15 prohibits the State from discrimination  

against any citizen on the grounds of religion, race,  

caste, sex, or place of birth. The object of this provision  

was to guarantee protection to those citizens who had  

suffered historical disadvantage, whether it be of a  

political, social, or economic nature.   

15.1. The term ‘sex’, as it occurs in Article 15 has been given  

an expansive interpretation by this Court in National  

Legal Services Authority v. Union of India & Ors. (supra)

465

22    

to include sexual identity. Paragraph 66 of the judgment  

reads thus:  

“66…Both gender and biological attributes  constitute distinct components of sex. The  biological characteristics, of course, include  genitals, chromosomes and secondary sexual  features, but gender attributes includes one’s self- image, the deep psychological or emotional sense  of sexual identity and character. The  discrimination on the ground of sex under Article  15 and 16, therefore includes discrimination on  the ground of gender identity. The expression sex  used in Articles 15 and 16 is not just limited to  biological sex of male and female, but intended to  include people who consider themselves neither  male nor female.”  (emphasis supplied and internal quotations omitted)  

 

Sex as it occurs in Article 15, is not merely restricted  

to the biological attributes of an individual, but also  

includes their “sexual identity and character”.  

The J.S. Verma Committee23 had recommended that  

‘sex’ under Article 15 must include ‘sexual orientation’:  

“65. We must also recognize that our society has  the need to recognize different sexual orientations  a human reality. In addition to homosexuality,  bisexuality, and lesbianism, there also exists the  transgender community. In view of the lack of  scientific understanding of the different variations  of orientation, even advanced societies have had  to first declassify ‘homosexuality’ from being a  mental disorder and now it is understood as a  

                                                           23 Report of the Committee on Amendments to Criminal Law (2013)

466

23    

triangular development occasioned by evolution,  partial conditioning and neurological  underpinnings owing to genetic reasons. Further,  we are clear that Article 15(c) of the constitution of  India uses the word “sex” as including sexual  orientation.”    

The prohibition against discrimination under Article 15  

on the ground of ‘sex’ should therefore encompass  

instances where such discrimination takes place on the  

basis of one’s sexual orientation.  

In this regard, the view taken by the Human Rights  

Committee of the United Nations in Nicholas Toonen v.  

Australia24 is relevant to cite, wherein the Committee  

noted that the reference to ‘sex’ in Article 2, Paragraph 1  

and Article 26 of the International Covenant on Civil and  

Political Rights would include ‘sexual orientation’.  

15.2. In an article titled “Reading Swaraj into Article 15: A New  

Deal For All Minorities”25, Tarunabh Khaitan notes that  

the underlying commonality between the grounds  

specified in Article 15 is based on the ideas of ‘immutable  

status’ and ‘fundamental choice’. He refers to the  

                                                           24 Communication No. 488/1992, U.N. Doc.CCPR/C/50/D/488/1992 (1994)  25 Tarunabh Khaitan, Reading Swaraj into Article 15: A New Deal For All Minorities, 2 NUJS  

Law Review (2009), at p. 419

467

24    

following quote by John Gardener to provide context to  

the aforesaid commonality:  

“Discrimination on the basis of our immutable  status tends to deny us [an autonomous] life. Its  result is that our further choices are constrained  not mainly by our own choices, but by the choices  of others. Because these choices of others are  based on our immutable status, our own choices  can make no difference to them. .... And  discrimination on the ground of fundamental  choices can be wrongful by the same token. To  lead an autonomous life we need an adequate  range of valuable options throughout that life....  there are some particular valuable options that  each of us should have irrespective of our other  choices. Where a particular choice is a choice  between valuable options which ought to be  available to people whatever else they may  choose, it is a fundamental choice. Where there is  discrimination against people based on their  fundamental choices it tends to skew those  choices by making one or more of the valuable  options from which they must choose more painful  or burdensome than others.”26  

(emphasis supplied)    

Race, caste, sex, and place of birth are aspects over  

which a person has no control, ergo they are immutable.  

On the other hand, religion is a fundamental choice of a  

person.27 Discrimination based on any of these grounds  

would undermine an individual’s personal autonomy.  

                                                           26 John Gardner, On the Ground of Her Sex (uality), 18(2) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies  

(1998), at p. 167  27 Supra note 25

468

25    

The Supreme Court of Canada in its decisions in the  

cases of Egan v. Canada28, and Vriend v. Alberta29,  

interpreted Section 15(1)30 of the Canadian Charter of  

Rights and Freedoms which is pari materia to Article 15  

of the Indian Constitution.  

Section 15(1), of the Canadian Charter like Article 15  

of our Constitution, does not include “sexual orientation”  

as a prohibited ground of discrimination.  

Notwithstanding that, the Canadian Supreme Court in  

the aforesaid decisions has held that sexual orientation  

is a “ground analogous” to the other grounds specified  

under Section 15(1). Discrimination based on any of  

these grounds has adverse impact on an individual’s  

personal autonomy, and is undermining of his  

personality.  

                                                           28 [1995] SCC 98  29 [1998] SCC 816  30 “15. Equality before and under law and equal protection and benefit of law  

(1) Every individual is equal before and under the law and has the right to the equal  protection and equal benefit of the law without discrimination and, in particular,  

without discrimination based on race, national or ethnic origin, colour, religion, sex,  age or mental or physical disability…”  

Article 15(1), Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms.

469

26    

A similar conclusion can be reached in the Indian  

context as well in light of the underlying aspects of  

immutability and fundamental choice.  

The LGBT community is a sexual minority which has  

suffered from unjustified and unwarranted hostile  

discrimination, and is equally entitled to the protection  

afforded by Article 15.  

16. SECTION 377 VIOLATES THE RIGHT TO LIFE AND LIBERTY GUARANTEED  

BY ARTICLE 21  

Article 21 provides that no person shall be deprived of  

his life or personal liberty except according to the  

procedure established by law. Such procedure  

established by law must be fair, just and reasonable.31  

The right to life and liberty affords protection to every  

citizen or non-citizen, irrespective of their identity or  

orientation, without discrimination.  

16.1. RIGHT TO LIVE WITH DIGNITY  

This Court has expansively interpreted the terms “life”  

and “personal liberty” to recognise a panoply of rights  

                                                           31 Maneka Gandhi v. Union of India & Anr., (1978) 1 SCC 248, at paragraph 48

470

27    

under Article 21 of the Constitution, so as to  

comprehend the true scope and contours of the right to  

life under Article 21. Article 21 is “the most precious  

human right and forms the ark of all other rights” as held  

in Francis Coralie Mullin v. Administrator, Union Territory  

of Delhi & Ors.,32 wherein it was noted that the right to  

life could not be restricted to a mere animal existence,  

and provided for much more than only physical  

survival.33 Bhagwati J. observed as under:  

“8…We think that the right to life includes the  right to live with human dignity and all that goes  along with it, namely the bare necessaries of life  such as adequate nutrition, clothing and shelter  and facilities for reading, writing and expressing  oneself in diverse forms, freely moving about and  mixing and commingling with fellow human  beings…it must in any view of the matter, include  the right to the basic necessities of life and also  the right to carry on such functions and activities  as constitute the bare minimum expression of the  human-self. Every act which offends against or  impairs human dignity would constitute  deprivation pro tanto of this right to live and it  would have to be in accordance with reasonable,  fair and just procedure established by law which  stands the test of other fundamental rights.”  

(emphasis supplied)  

                                                           32 (1981) 1 SCC 608  33 (1981) 1 SCC 608 at paragraph 7

471

28    

This was re-affirmed by the Constitution bench  

decision in K.S. Puttaswamy & Anr. v. Union of India &  

Ors.34 and Common Cause (A Registered Society) v. Union  

of India & Anr.35  

Although dignity is an amorphous concept which is  

incapable of being defined, it is a core intrinsic value of  

every human being. Dignity is considered essential for a  

meaningful existence.36  

In National Legal Services Authority v. Union of India &  

Ors. (supra), this Court recognised the right of  

transgender persons to decide their self-identified  

gender. In the context of the legal rights of transgender  

persons, this Court held that sexual orientation and  

gender identity is an integral part of their personality.   

The relevant excerpt from Radhakrishnan, J.’s view is  

extracted hereinbelow:  

“22. …Each person’s self-defined sexual  orientation and gender identity is integral to their  personality and is one of the most basic aspects of  self-determination, dignity and freedom…”  

(emphasis supplied)  

                                                           34 (2017) 10 SCC 1  35 (2018) 5 SCC 1 at paragraphs 156, 437, 438, 488 & 516  36 Common Cause (A Registered Society) v. Union of India and Anr., (2018) 5 SCC 1, at  

paragraphs 437 and 438

472

29    

 

Sexual orientation is innate to a human being. It is an  

important attribute of one’s personality and identity.  

Homosexuality and bisexuality are natural variants of  

human sexuality. LGBT persons have little or no choice  

over their sexual orientation. LGBT persons, like other  

heterosexual persons, are entitled to their privacy, and  

the right to lead a dignified existence, without fear of  

persecution. They are entitled to complete autonomy over  

the most intimate decisions relating to their personal life,  

including the choice of their partners. Such choices must  

be protected under Article 21. The right to life and liberty  

would encompass the right to sexual autonomy, and  

freedom of expression.  

The following excerpt from the decision of the  

Constitutional Court of South Africa in National Coalition  

for Gay and Lesbian Equality and Anr. v. Minister of  

Justice and Ors.37 is also instructive in this regard:  

“While recognising the unique worth of each  person, the Constitution does not presuppose that  a holder of rights is an isolated, lonely and  abstract figure possessing a disembodied and  

                                                           37 [1998] ZACC 15

473

30    

socially disconnected self. It acknowledges that  people live in their bodies, their communities, their  cultures, their places and their times. The  expression of sexuality requires a partner, real or  imagined. It is not for the state to choose or  arrange the choice of partner, but for the partners  to choose themselves.”  

(emphasis supplied)  

Section 377 insofar as it curtails the personal liberty of  

LGBT persons to engage in voluntary consensual sexual  

relationships with a partner of their choice, in a safe and  

dignified environment, is violative of Article 21. It inhibits  

them from entering and nurturing enduring  

relationships. As a result, LGBT individuals are forced to  

either lead a life of solitary existence without a  

companion, or lead a closeted life as “unapprehended  

felons”.38  

Section 377 criminalises the entire class of LGBT  

persons since sexual intercourse between such persons,  

is considered to be carnal and “against the order of  

nature”. Section 377 prohibits LGBT persons from  

engaging in intimate sexual relations in private.  

                                                           38 According to Professor Edwin Cameron, LGBT persons are reduced to the status of  

“unapprehended felons” owing to the ever-so-present threat of prosecution.  Edwin Cameron, Sexual Orientation and the Constitution: A Test Case for Human Rights,  110 South African Law Journal (1993), at p. 450

474

31    

The social ostracism against LGBT persons prevents  

them from partaking in all activities as full citizens, and  

in turn impedes them from realising their fullest  

potential as human beings.  

On the issue of criminalisation of homosexuality, the  

dissenting opinion of Blackmun J. of the U.S. Supreme  

Court in Bowers v. Hardwick39 is instructive, which cites  

a previous decision in Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton40  

and noted as follows:  

“Only the most wilful blindness could obscure the  fact that sexual intimacy is a sensitive, key  relationship of human existence, central to family  life, community welfare, and the development of  human personality.”  

(emphasis supplied)    

The U.S. Supreme Court over-ruled Bowers v.  

Hardwick (supra) in Lawrence et al. v. Texas. (supra) and  

declared that a statute proscribing homosexuals from  

engaging in intimate sexual conduct as invalid on the  

ground that it violated the right to privacy, and dignity of  

homosexual persons. Kennedy, J. in his majority opinion  

observed as under:  

                                                           39 478 U.S. 186 (1986)  

40 413 U.S. 49 (1973)

475

32    

“To say that the issue in Bowers was simply the  right to engage in certain sexual conduct demeans  the claim the individual put forward, just as it  would demean a married couple were it to be said  marriage is simply about the right to have sexual  intercourse…  …It suffices for us to acknowledge that adults  may choose to enter upon this relationship in the  confines of their homes and their own private lives  and still retain their dignity as free persons. When  sexuality finds overt expression in intimate  conduct with another person, the conduct can be  but one element in a personal bond that is more  enduring. The liberty protected by the Constitution  allows homosexual persons the right to make this  choice…This stigma this criminal statute imposes,  moreover, is not trivial. The offence, to be sure, is  but a class C misdemeanour, a minor offence in  the Texas legal system. Still, it remains a criminal  offence with all that imports for the dignity of the  persons charged. The petitioners will bear on their  record the history of criminal convictions...  …The present case does not involve minors. It  does not involve persons who might be injured or  coerced or who are situated in relationships where  consent might not easily be refused. It does not  involve public conduct or prostitution. It does not  involve whether the government must give formal  recognition to any relationship that homosexuals  persons seek to enter. The case does involve two  adults who, with full and mutual consent from  each other, engage in sexual practices, common to  a homosexual lifestyle. The Petitioners are entitled  to respect for their private lives. The State cannot  demean their existence or control their destiny by  making their private sexual conduct a crime. The  right to liberty under the Due Process Clause gives  them the full right to engage in their conduct  without intervention of the government. It is a  promise of the Constitution that there is a realm of  personal liberty which the government may not  enter. Casey, supra at 847. The Texas statute

476

33    

furthers no legitimate state interest which can  justify its intrusion into the personal and private  life of the individual.”  

(emphasis supplied)  

Thus, Section 377 prevents LGBT persons from leading  

a dignified life as guaranteed by Article 21.  

16.2. RIGHT TO PRIVACY  

The right to privacy has now been recognised to be an  

intrinsic part of the right to life and personal liberty  

under Article 21.41  

Sexual orientation is an innate part of the identity of  

LGBT persons. Sexual orientation of a person is an  

essential attribute of privacy. Its protection lies at the  

core of Fundamental Rights guaranteed by Articles 14,  

15, and 21.42  

The right to privacy is broad-based and pervasive  

under our Constitutional scheme, and encompasses  

decisional autonomy, to cover intimate/personal  

                                                           41 K.S. Puttaswamy & Anr. v. Union of India & Ors., (2017) 10 SCC 1  42 K.S. Puttaswamy & Anr. v. Union of India & Ors., (2017) 10 SCC 1, at paragraphs 144,  

145, 479 and 647

477

34    

decisions and preserves the sanctity of the private sphere  

of an individual.43  

The right to privacy is not simply the “right to be let  

alone”, and has travelled far beyond that initial concept.  

It now incorporates the ideas of spatial privacy, and  

decisional privacy or privacy of choice.44 It extends to the  

right to make fundamental personal choices, including  

those relating to intimate sexual conduct, without  

unwarranted State interference.  

Section 377 affects the private sphere of the lives of  

LGBT persons. It takes away the decisional autonomy of  

LGBT persons to make choices consistent with their  

sexual orientation, which would further a dignified  

existence and a meaningful life as a full person. Section  

377 prohibits LGBT persons from expressing their sexual  

orientation and engaging in sexual conduct in private, a  

decision which inheres in the most intimate spaces of  

one’s existence.  

                                                           43 K.S. Puttaswamy & Anr. v. Union of India & Ors., (2017) 10 SCC 1, at paragraph 248,  

250, 371 and 403  44 K.S. Puttaswamy & Anr. v. Union of India & Ors., (2017) 10 SCC 1, at paragraphs 248,  

249, 371 and 521

478

35    

The Constitutional Court of South Africa in National  

Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality & Anr. v. Minister  

of Justice & Ors. (supra) noted as under:  

“Privacy recognises that we all have a right to a  sphere of private intimacy and autonomy which  allows us to establish and nurture human  relationships without interference from the outside  community. The way in which we give expression  to our sexuality is at the core of this area of  private intimacy. If, in expressing our sexuality,  we act consensually and without harming one  another, invasion of that precinct will be a breach  of our privacy.”  

  Just like other fundamental rights, the right to privacy  

is not an absolute right and is subject to reasonable  

restrictions. Any restriction on the right to privacy must  

adhere to the requirements of legality, existence of a  

legitimate state interest, and proportionality.45  

A subjective notion of public or societal morality which  

discriminates against LGBT persons, and subjects them  

to criminal sanction, simply on the basis of an innate  

characteristic runs counter to the concept of  

Constitutional morality, and cannot form the basis of a  

legitimate State interest.  

                                                           45 K.S. Puttaswamy & Anr. v. Union of India & Ors., (2017) 10 SCC 1, at paragraphs 325,  

638 and 645

479

36    

The theme of inclusiveness permeates through Part III  

of the Constitution. Apart from the equality code of the  

Constitution comprised in Articles 14, 15(1), 16, and  

other provisions in the form of Article 17 (Abolition of  

Untouchability), Article 21A (Right to Education), Article  

25 (Freedom of Conscience and Free Profession, Practice  

and Propagation of Religion), Article 26 (Freedom to  

Manage Religious Affairs), Article 29 (Protection of  

Interest of Minorities), Article 30 (Right of Minorities to  

Establish and Administer Educational Institutions) are  

aimed at creating an inclusive society where rights are  

guaranteed to all, regardless of their status as a  

minority.  

16.3. RIGHT TO HEALTH  

The right to health, and access to healthcare are also  

crucial facets of the right to life guaranteed under Article  

21 of the Constitution.46  

LGBT persons being a sexual minority have been  

subjected to societal prejudice, discrimination and  

                                                           46 Common Cause (A Registered Society) v. Union of India & Anr., (2018) 5 SCC 1, at  

paragraph 304; C.E.S.C. Limited & Ors. v. Subhash Chandra Bose & Ors., (1992) 1 SCC  

441, at paragraph 32; Union of India v. Mool Chand Khairati Ram Trust, (2018) SCC  OnLine SC 675, at paragraph 66; and, Centre for Public Interest Litigation v. Union of  India & Ors., (2013) 16 SCC 279, at paragraph 25

480

37    

violence on account of their sexual orientation. Since  

Section 377 criminalises “carnal intercourse against the  

order of nature” it compels LGBT persons to lead  

closeted lives. As a consequence, LGBT persons are  

seriously disadvantaged and prejudiced when it comes to  

access to health-care facilities. This results in serious  

health issues, including depression and suicidal  

tendencies amongst members of this community.47  

LGBT persons, and more specifically the MSM, and  

transgender persons are at a higher risk of contracting  

HIV as they lack safe spaces to engage in safe-sex  

practices. They are inhibited from seeking medical help  

for testing, treatment and supportive care on account of  

the threat of being ‘exposed’ and the resultant  

prosecution.48 Higher rates of prevalence of HIV-AIDS in  

MSM, who are in turn married to other people of the  

opposite sex, coupled with the difficulty in detection and  

                                                           47 M.V. Lee Badgett, The Economic Cost of Stigma and the Exclusion of LGBT People: A Case  

Study of India, World Bank Group (2014) available at  http://documents.worldbank.org/curated/en/527261468035379692/The-economic- cost-of-stigma-and-the-exclusion-of-LGBT-people-a-case-study-of-India (Last accessed  

on August 11, 2018)  48 Govindasamy Agoramoorthy and Minna J Hsu, India’s homosexual discrimination and  

health consequences, 41(4) Rev Saude Publica (2007), at pp. 567-660 available at  http://www.scielo.br/pdf/rsp/v41n4/6380.pdf

481

38    

treatment, makes them highly susceptible to contraction  

and further transmission of the virus.  

It is instructive to refer to the findings of the Human  

Rights Committee of the United Nations in Nicholas  

Toonen v. Australia (supra):  

“8.5 As far as the public health argument of the  Tasmanian authorities is concerned, the  Committee notes that the criminalization of  homosexual practices cannot be considered a  reasonable means or proportionate measure to  achieve the aim of preventing the spread of  AIDS/HIV. The Australian Government observes  that statutes criminalizing homosexual activity  tend to impede public health programmes by  driving underground many of the people at the  risk of infection. Criminalization of homosexual  activity thus would appear to run counter to the  implementation of effective education programmes  in respect of the HIV/AIDS prevention. Secondly,  the Committee notes that no link has been shown  between the continued criminalization of  homosexual activity and the effective control of the  spread of the HIV/AIDS virus.”  

(emphasis supplied and internal footnotes omitted)  

 

The American Psychological Association, American  

Psychiatric Association, National Association of Social  

Workers and the Texas Chapter of the National  

Association of Social Workers in their Amicus Brief in  

Lawrence et al. v. Texas (supra) stated as follows:

482

39    

“III. Texas Penal Code S. 21.06 reinforces  prejudice, discrimination, and violence against  gay men and lesbians…Although many gay men  and lesbians learn to cope with the social stigma  against homosexuality, this pattern of prejudice  can cause gay people serious psychological  distress, especially if they attempt to conceal or  deny their sexual orientation….”49  

(emphasis supplied)  

It is pertinent to mention that in India the Mental  

Healthcare Act, 2017 came into force on July 7,  

2018. Sections 18(1) and (2) read with 21(1)(a) of the  

Mental Healthcare Act, 2017 provide for the right to  

access mental healthcare and equal treatment of  

people with physical and mental illnesses without  

discrimination, inter alia, on the basis of “sexual  

orientation”.   

This gives rise to a paradoxical situation since  

Section 377 criminalises LGBT persons, which  

inhibits them from accessing health-care facilities,  

while the Mental Healthcare Act, 2017 provides a  

right to access mental healthcare without  

discrimination, even on the ground of ‘sexual  

orientation’.  

                                                           49 Supra note 16, at page 3

483

40    

17. SECTION 377 VIOLATES THE RIGHT TO FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION OF  

LGBT PERSONS  

17.1. Article 19(1)(a) guarantees freedom of expression to  

all citizens. However, reasonable restrictions can be  

imposed on the exercise of this right on the grounds  

specified in Article 19(2).  

LGBT persons express their sexual orientation in  

myriad ways. One such way is engagement in intimate  

sexual acts like those proscribed under Section 377.50  

Owing to the fear of harassment from law enforcement  

agencies and prosecution, LGBT persons tend to stay ‘in  

the closet’. They are forced not to disclose a central  

aspect of their personal identity i.e. their sexual  

orientation, both in their personal and professional  

spheres to avoid persecution in society and the  

opprobrium attached to homosexuality. Unlike  

heterosexual persons, they are inhibited from openly  

forming and nurturing fulfilling relationships, thereby  

restricting rights of full personhood and a dignified  

                                                           50 Lawrence et al. v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003); and, National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian  

Equality & Anr. v. Minister of Justice & Ors., [1998] ZACC 15

484

41    

existence. It also has an impact on their mental well-

being.  

17.2. In National Legal Services Authority v. Union of India &  

Ors. (supra), this Court noted that gender identity is an  

important aspect of personal identity and is inherent to a  

person. It was held that transgender persons have the  

right to express their self-identified gender by way of  

speech, mannerism, behaviour, presentation and  

clothing, etc.51  

The Court also noted that like gender identity, sexual  

orientation is integral to one’s personality, and is a basic  

aspect of self-determination, dignity and freedom.52 The  

proposition that sexual orientation is integral to one’s  

personality and identity was affirmed by the Constitution  

Bench in K.S. Puttaswamy & Anr. v. Union of India &  

Ors.53  

In this regard, it is instructive to refer to the decision  

of this Court in S. Khushboo v. Kanniammal & Anr.54  

wherein the following observation was made in the  

                                                           51 (2014) 5 SCC 438, at paragraphs 69-72  52 (2014) 5 SCC 438, at paragraph 22  53 (2017) 10 SCC 1, at paragraphs 144, 145, 647  54 (2010) 5 SCC 600

485

42    

context of the phrase “decency and morality” as it occurs  

in Article 19(2):  

“45. Even though the constitutional freedom of  speech and expression is not absolute and can be  subjected to reasonable restrictions on grounds  such as “decency and morality” among others, we  must lay stress on the need to tolerate unpopular  views in the sociocultural space. The Framers of  our Constitution recognised the importance of  safeguarding this right since the free flow of  opinions and ideas is essential to sustain the  collective life of the citizenry. While an informed  citizenry is a precondition for meaningful  governance in the political sense, we must also  promote a culture of open dialogue when it comes  to societal attitudes.  46…Notions of social morality are inherently  subjective and the criminal law cannot be used as  a means to unduly interfere with the domain of  personal autonomy. Morality and criminality are  not coextensive.”  

(emphasis supplied)  

 

Therefore, Section 377 cannot be justified as a  

reasonable restriction under Article 19(2) on the basis of  

public or societal morality, since it is inherently  

subjective.  

18. SURESH KUMAR KOUSHAL OVERRULED  

The two-Judge bench of this Court in Suresh Kumar  

Koushal & Anr. v. Naz Foundation & Ors. (supra) over-ruled the

486

43    

decision of the Delhi High Court in Naz Foundation v.  

Government of NCT of Delhi & Ors.55 which had declared  

Section 377 insofar as it criminalised consensual sexual acts  

of adults in private to be violative of Articles 14, 15 and 21 of  

the Constitution.   

The grounds on which the two-judge bench of this Court  

over-ruled the judgment in Naz Foundation v. Government of  

NCT of Delhi & Ors. (supra) were that:  

i. Section 377 does not criminalise particular people  

or identity or orientation. It merely identifies certain  

acts which if committed would constitute an  

offence. Such a prohibition regulates sexual  

conduct, regardless of gender identity and  

orientation.  

Those who indulge in carnal intercourse in the  

ordinary course, and those who indulge in carnal  

intercourse against the order of nature, constitute  

different classes. Persons falling in the latter  

category cannot claim that Section 377 suffers from  

the vice of arbitrariness and irrational  

                                                           55 (2009) 111 DRJ 1 (DB)

487

44    

classification. Section 377 merely defines a  

particular offence, and prescribes a punishment for  

the same.  

ii. LGBT persons constitute a “miniscule fraction” of  

the country’s population, and there have been very  

few prosecutions under this Section. Hence, it could  

not have been made a sound basis for declaring  

Section 377 to be ultra-vires Articles 14, 15, and  

21.   

iii. It was held that merely because Section 377, IPC  

has been used to perpetrate harassment, blackmail  

and torture to persons belonging to the LGBT  

community, cannot be a ground for challenging the  

vires of the Section.  

iv. After noting that Section 377 was intra vires, this  

Court observed that the legislature was free to  

repeal or amend Section 377.  

19. The fallacy in the Judgment of Suresh Kumar Koushal & Anr.  

v. Naz Foundation & Ors. (supra) is that:   

i. The offence of “carnal intercourse against the  

order of nature” has not been defined in Section

488

45    

377. It is too wide, and open-ended, and would  

take within its sweep, and criminalise even  

sexual acts of consenting adults in private.   

In this context, it would be instructive to  

refer to the decision of a Constitution Bench of  

this Court in A.K. Roy v. Union of India56 wherein  

it was held that:  

“ 62. The requirement that crimes must be  defined with appropriate definiteness is  regarded as a fundamental concept in  criminal law and must now be regarded as  a pervading theme of our Constitution since  the decision in Maneka Gandhi. The  underlying principle is that every person is  entitled to be informed as to what the State  commands or forbids and that the life and  liberty of a person cannot be put in peril on  an ambiguity. However, even in the domain  of criminal law, the processes of which can  result in the taking away of life itself, no  more than a reasonable degree of certainty  has to be accepted as a fact. Neither the  criminal law nor the Constitution requires  the application of impossible standards and  therefore, what is expected is that the  language of the law must contain an  adequate warning of the conduct which  may fall within the proscribed area, when  measured by common understanding….”  

(emphasis supplied)    

                                                           56 (1982) 1 SCC 271

489

46    

The Judgment does not advert to the  

distinction between consenting adults engaging  

in sexual intercourse, and sexual acts which are  

without the will, or consent of the other party. A  

distinction has to be made between consensual  

relationships of adults in private, whether they  

are heterosexual or homosexual in nature.  

Furthermore, consensual relationships  

between adults cannot be classified along with  

offences of bestiality, sodomy and non-

consensual relationships.   

Sexual orientation is immutable, since it is  

an innate feature of one’s identity, and cannot  

be changed at will. The choice of LGBT persons  

to enter into intimate sexual relations with  

persons of the same sex is an exercise of their  

personal choice, and an expression of their  

autonomy and self-determination.  

Section 377 insofar as it criminalises  

voluntary sexual relations between LGBT  

persons of the same sex in private,

490

47    

discriminates against them on the basis of their  

“sexual orientation” which is violative of their  

fundamental rights guaranteed by Articles 14,  

19, and 21 of the Constitution.   

ii. The mere fact that the LGBT persons constitute  

a “miniscule fraction” of the country’s population  

cannot be a ground to deprive them of their  

Fundamental Rights guaranteed by Part III of  

the Constitution. Even though the LGBT  

constitute a sexual minority, members of the  

LGBT community are citizens of this country  

who are equally entitled to the enforcement of  

their Fundamental Rights guaranteed by Articles  

14, 15, 19, and 21.  

Fundamental Rights are guaranteed to all  

citizens alike, irrespective of whether they are a  

numerical minority. Modern democracies are  

based on the twin principles of majority rule,  

and protection of fundamental rights guaranteed  

under Part III of the Constitution. Under the  

Constitutional scheme, while the majority is

491

48    

entitled to govern; the minorities like all other  

citizens are protected by the solemn guarantees  

of rights and freedoms under Part III.  

The J.S. Verma Committee, in this regard, in  

paragraph 77 of its Report (supra) states that:  

“77. We need to remember that the founding  fathers of our Constitution never thought  that the Constitution is ‘mirror of perverse  social discrimination’. On the contrary, it  promised the mirror in which equality will  be reflected brightly. Thus, all the sexual  identities, including sexual minorities,  including transgender communities are  entitled to be totally protected. The  Constitution enables change of beliefs,  greater understanding and is also an  equally guaranteed instrument to secure the  rights of sexually despised minorities. ”  

(emphasis supplied)    

iii. Even though Section 377 is facially neutral, it  

has been misused by subjecting members of the  

LGBT community to hostile discrimination,  

making them vulnerable and living in fear of the  

ever-present threat of prosecution on account of  

their sexual orientation.  

The criminalisation of “carnal intercourse  

against the order of nature” has the effect of  

criminalising the entire class of LGBT persons

492

49    

since any kind of sexual intercourse in the case  

of such persons would be considered to be  

against the “order of nature”, as per the existing  

interpretation.  

iv. The conclusion in case of Suresh Kumar Koushal  

& Anr. v. Naz Foundation & Ors. (supra) to await  

legislative amendments to this provision may not  

be necessary. Once it is brought to the notice of  

the Court of any violation of the Fundamental  

Rights of a citizen, or a group of citizens the  

Court will not remain a mute spectator, and wait  

for a majoritarian government to bring about  

such a change.   

Given the role of this Court as the sentinel  

on the qui vive, it is the Constitutional duty of  

this Court to review the provisions of the  

impugned Section, and read it down to the  

extent of its inconsistency with the Constitution.  

In the present case, reading down Section  

377 is necessary to exclude consensual sexual  

relationships between adults, whether of the

493

50    

same sex or otherwise, in private, so as to  

remove the vagueness of the provision to the  

extent it is inconsistent with Part III of the  

Constitution.  

20. History owes an apology to the members of this community  

and their families, for the delay in providing redressal for the  

ignominy and ostracism that they have suffered through the  

centuries. The members of this community were compelled to  

live a life full of fear of reprisal and persecution. This was on  

account of the ignorance of the majority to recognise that  

homosexuality is a completely natural condition, part of a  

range of human sexuality. The mis-application of this  

provision denied them the Fundamental Right to equality  

guaranteed by Article 14. It infringed the Fundamental Right  

to non-discrimination under Article 15, and the Fundamental  

Right to live a life of dignity and privacy guaranteed by Article  

21. The LGBT persons deserve to live a life unshackled from  

the shadow of being ‘unapprehended felons’.  

21. CONCLUSION  

i. In view of the aforesaid findings, it is declared  

that insofar as Section 377 criminalises

494

51    

consensual sexual acts of adults (i.e. persons  

above the age of 18 years who are competent to  

consent) in private, is violative of Articles 14, 15,  

19, and 21 of the Constitution.  

It is, however, clarified that such consent must  

be free consent, which is completely voluntary  

in nature, and devoid of any duress or coercion.  

ii. The declaration of the aforesaid reading down of  

Section 377 shall not, however, lead to the re-

opening of any concluded prosecutions, but can  

certainly be relied upon in all pending matters  

whether they are at the trial, appellate, or  

revisional stages.  

iii. The provisions of Section 377 will continue to  

govern non-consensual sexual acts against  

adults, all acts of carnal intercouse against  

minors, and acts of beastiality.   

iv. The judgment in Suresh Kumar Koushal & Anr.  

v. Naz Foundation & Ors.57 is hereby overruled  

for the reasons stated in paragraph 19.  

                                                           57 (2014) 1 SCC 1

495

52    

The Reference is answered accordingly.   

In view of the above findings, the Writ  

Petitions are allowed.  

 

     ……………..……..…………………J.               (Indu Malhotra)  

   

New Delhi;  September 6, 2018.